|
Book XI
OF THE SOVEREIGN AUTHORITY WHICH SACRED LOVE HOLDS OVER ALL THE VIRTUES, ACTIONS AND PERFECTIONS OF THE SOUL.
CHAPTER VII. THAT PERFECT VIRTUES ARE NEVER ONE WITHOUT THE OTHER.
|
It is said that the heart is the first part of a man which receives life by
the infusion of the soul, and the eye the last, as, contrariwise, in a
natural death the eye begins first to die, and the heart is the last. Now
when the heart begins to live, before the other parts are animated, life is
certainly very feeble, frail and imperfect, but ever as it establishes
itself more thoroughly in the rest of the body, it is also more vigorous in
each part and particularly in the heart, and we see that when life is
injured in any one of the members it is weakened in all the rest. If a man's
foot or arm be hurt all the body is troubled, excited, disturbed and
affected; if the stomach is disordered, the eyes, the voice and the whole
countenance show the effects of it, so great is the sympathy amongst the
organs of man's natural life.
All the virtues are not acquired together, in an instant, but one after
another, in proportion as reason, which is like the soul of our heart, takes
possession, first of one passion then of another, to moderate and govern
them: and ordinarily this life of our soul begins in the heart of our
passions, which is love, and spreading itself over all the rest it quickens
at last the very understanding by contemplation; as, on the contrary, moral
or spiritual death makes its entry into the soul by the want of reflection
[517] death enters by the windows, [518] says the sacred text and its last
effect is to destroy good love, which once perishing, all our moral life is
dead in us. So then, although we may perhaps possess some virtues without
others, yet are they but languishing, imperfect and weak virtues, since
reason, which is the life of our soul, is never satisfied nor at ease in a
soul unless it occupy and possess all the faculties and passions; and when
it is aggrieved and wounded in some one of our passions or affections, all
the rest lose their force and vigour, and grow exceedingly weak.
You see, Theotimus, all the virtues are virtues by the proportion or
conformity they have with reason, and an action cannot be called virtuous if
it proceed not from the affection which the heart bears to the excellence
and beauty of reason. Now if the love of reason possess and animate a soul,
it will be obedient to reason in all occurrences, and consequently will
practise all the virtues. If Jacob loved Rachel in consideration of her
being Laban's daughter, why did he despise Lia who was not only the
daughter, but the eldest daughter, of the same Laban? But because he loved
Rachel by reason of her beauty, he could never equally love poor Lia, though
a fruitful and wise maid, because to his mind she was not so fair. He who
loves one virtue for the love of the reason and comeliness which shine in
it, will love all the virtues, since he will find the same motive in them
all, and he will love each of them more or less, as reason shall appear in
them more or less resplendent. He who loves liberality and not chastity,
shows sufficiently that he loves not liberality for reason's sake, because
reason is still more radiant in chastity, and where the cause is more strong
the effects ought also to be more strong. It is, therefore, an evident sign
that such a heart is not moved to liberality by the motive and consideration
of reason; whence it follows that this liberality which seemed to be virtue
is but an appearance of it, since it proceeds not from reason, which is the
true motive of virtues, but from some other and foreign motive. It is
sufficient for a child to be born in marriage to bear in the world the name,
the arms, and the titles of his mother's husband, but to have his blood and
nature he must not only be born in the marriage but of the marriage. Actions
have the name, arms and badges of the virtues, because being born of a heart
endowed with reason we presume them to be reasonable, yet they have neither
the substance nor vigour of virtue when they proceed from a foreign and
illegitimate motive, and not from reason. It may happen then, that a man may
have some virtues and lack others; but they will either be virtues newly
springing and as yet tender, like flowers in blossom; or else perishing and
dying virtues, like fading flowers: for, in conclusion, virtues cannot have
their true integrity and sufficiency unless they be all together, as all
philosophy and divinity assure us. What prudence, I pray you, Theotimus, can
an intemperate, unjust and cowardly man have, since he makes choice of vice
and forsakes virtue? And how can one be just without being prudent, strong,
and temperate, since justice is no other thing than a perpetual, strong and
constant will to render to every one his own, and since the science by which
right is done is called jurisprudence, and since, to give each one his own,
we must live wisely and moderately, and hinder the disorders of intemperance
in ourselves so as to give ourselves what belongs to us? And the word
virtue, does it not signify a force and vigour belonging to the soul as a
quality, even as we say that herbs and precious stones have such and such a
virtue or property?
But is not prudence itself imprudent in an intemperate man? Fortitude,
without prudence, justice and temperance, is not fortitude, but folly; and
justice is unjust in the weak man who dares not do it, in the intemperate
man who permits himself to be carried away with passion, and in the
imprudent man who is not able to discern between the right and the wrong.
Justice is not justice unless it be strong, prudent and temperate; nor is
prudence prudence unless it be temperate, just and strong; nor fortitude
fortitude unless it be just, prudent and temperate; nor temperance
temperance unless it be prudent, strong and just. In fine, a virtue is not
perfect virtue, unless it be accompanied by all the rest.
It is true, Theotimus, that one cannot exercise all the virtues at once,
because the occasions are not all presented at once; yea, there are virtues
which some of God's greatest saints had never occasion to practise: for S.
Paul, the first hermit, for example, what occasion could he have to exercise
the pardoning of injuries, affability, magnificence, and mildness?
Nevertheless, such souls stand so affected to the rectitude of reason, that
though they have not all the virtues in effect, yet they have them all in
affection, being ready and prepared to follow and obey reason in all
occurences, without exception or reservation.
There are certain inclinations which are esteemed virtues and are not so,
but favours and advantages of nature. How many are there who are naturally
sober, mild, silent, chaste and modest? Now all these seem to be virtues,
and yet have no more the merit thereof than bad inclinations are blameworthy
before we have given free and voluntary consent to such natural
dispositions. It is no virtue to be by nature a man of little meat, yet to
abstain by choice is a virtue. It is no virtue to be silent by nature,
though it is a virtue to bridle one's tongue by reason. Many consider they
have the virtues as long as they do not practise the contrary vices. One
that has never been assaulted may truly boast that he was never a runaway,
yet he has no ground to boast of his valour. He that has never been
afflicted may boast of not being impatient, but not of being patient. In
like manner, some think they have virtues who have only good inclinations,
and as those inclinations are some without others, they suppose that virtues
may be so too.
In truth the great S. Augustine shows, in an epistle which he wrote to S.
Jerome, that we may have some sort of virtue without having the rest, but
that we cannot have perfect ones without having them all; whilst, as for
vices, we may have some without having others, yea, it is even impossible to
have them all together: so that it does not follow that he who has lost all
the virtues has by consequence all the vices, since almost every virtue has
two opposite vices, which are not only contrary to the virtue but also to
one another. He who has forfeited valour by rashness cannot at the same time
be taxed with cowardice; nor can he who has lost liberality by prodigality,
be at the same time reproached with niggardliness. Catiline, says S.
Augustine, was sober, vigilant, patient in suffering cold, heat and hunger;
so that both himself and his accomplices deemed him marvellously constant;
but this constancy wanted prudence, since it made choice of bad instead of
good; it was not temperate, for it gave the bridle to repulsive uncleanness;
it was not just, since he conspired against his country: it was not then
constancy but obstinacy, which to deceive fools bore the name of constancy.
[517] inconsideration i.e., failure of the spiritual eye (Tr.)
[518] Jer. ix. 21.
|