|
Varied
Types
G.
K. Chesterton
1905 by Dodd, Mead, New York, US..
This
work is published for the greater Glory of Jesus Christ through His
most Holy Mother Mary and for the sanctification of the militant
Church and her members.
PUBLISHER
www.eCatholic2000.com
INDEX
TABLE
OF CONTENTS
VARIED
TYPES
ILLUSTRATIONS
PUBLISHER
II
VARIED TYPES
CHARLOTTE BRONTË
Objection is often raised against
realistic biography because it reveals so much that is important and
even sacred about a man’s life. The real objection to it will
rather be found in the fact that it reveals about a man the precise
points which are unimportant. It reveals and asserts and insists on
exactly those things in a man’s life of which the man himself
is wholly unconscious; his exact class in society, the circumstances
of his ancestry, the place of his present location. These are things
which do not, properly speaking, ever arise before the human vision.
They do not occur to a man’s mind; it may be said, with almost
equal truth, that they do not occur in a man’s life. A man no
more thinks about himself as the inhabitant of the third house in a
row of Brixton villas than he thinks about himself as a strange
animal with two legs. What a man’s name was, what his income
was, whom he married, where he lived, these are not sanctities; they
are irrelevancies.
A very strong case of this is the
case of the Brontës. The Brontë is in the position of the
mad lady in a country village; her eccentricities form an endless
source of innocent conversation to that exceedingly mild and bucolic
circle, the literary world. The truly glorious gossips of literature,
like Mr. Augustine Birrell and Mr. Andrew Lang, never tire of
collecting all the glimpses and anecdotes and sermons and side-lights
and sticks and straws which will go to make a Brontë museum.
They are the most personally discussed of all Victorian authors, and
the limelight of biography has left few darkened corners in the dark
old Yorkshire house. And yet the whole of this biographical
investigation, though natural and picturesque, is not wholly suitable
to the Brontës. For the Brontë genius was above all things
deputed to assert the supreme unimportance of externals. Up to that
point truth had always been conceived as existing more or less in the
novel of manners. Charlotte Brontë electrified the world by
showing that an infinitely older and more elemental truth could be
conveyed by a novel in which no person, good or bad, had any manners
at all. Her work represents the first great assertion that the
humdrum life of modern civilisation is a disguise as tawdry and
deceptive as the costume of a bal masqué. She showed
that abysses may exist inside a governess and eternities inside a
manufacturer; her heroine is the commonplace spinster, with the dress
of merino and the soul of flame. It is significant to notice that
Charlotte Brontë, following consciously or unconsciously the
great trend of her genius, was the first to take away from the
heroine not only the artificial gold and diamonds of wealth and
fashion, but even the natural gold and diamonds of physical beauty
and grace. Instinctively she felt that the whole of the exterior must
be made ugly that the whole of the interior might be made sublime.
She chose the ugliest of women in the ugliest of centuries, and
revealed within them all the hells and heavens of Dante.
It may, therefore, I think, be
legitimately said that the externals of the Brontës’ life,
though singularly picturesque in themselves, matter less than the
externals of almost any other writers. It is interesting to know
whether Jane Austen had any knowledge of the lives of the officers
and women of fashion whom she introduced into her masterpieces. It is
interesting to know whether Dickens had ever seen a shipwreck or been
inside a workhouse. For in these authors much of the conviction is
conveyed, not always by adherence to facts, but always by grasp of
them. But the whole aim and purport and meaning of the work of the
Brontës is that the most futile thing in the whole universe is
fact. Such a story as “Jane Eyre” is in itself so
monstrous a fable that it ought to be excluded from a book of fairy
tales. The characters do not do what they ought to do, nor what they
would do, nor it might be said, such is the insanity of the
atmosphere, not even what they intend to do. The conduct of Rochester
is so primevally and superhumanly caddish that Bret Harte in his
admirable travesty scarcely exaggerated it. “Then, resuming his
usual manner, he threw his boots at my head and withdrew,” does
perhaps reach to something resembling caricature. The scene in which
Rochester dresses up as an old gipsy has something in it which is
really not to be found in any other branch of art, except in the end
of the pantomime, where the Emperor turns into a pantaloon. Yet,
despite this vast nightmare of illusion and morbidity and ignorance
of the world, “Jane Eyre” is perhaps the truest book that
was ever written. Its essential truth to life sometimes makes one
catch one’s breath. For it is not true to manners, which are
constantly false, or to facts, which are almost always false; it is
true to the only existing thing which is true, emotion, the
irreducible minimum, the indestructible germ. It would not matter a
single straw if a Brontë story were a hundred times more
moonstruck and improbable than “Jane Eyre,” or a hundred
times more moonstruck and improbable than “Wuthering Heights.”
It would not matter if George Read stood on his head, and Mrs. Read
rode on a dragon, if Fairfax Rochester had four eyes and St. John
Rivers three legs, the story would still remain the truest story in
the world. The typical Brontë character is, indeed, a kind of
monster. Everything in him except the essential is dislocated. His
hands are on his legs and his feet on his arms, his nose is above his
eyes, but his heart is in the right place.
The great and abiding truth for which
the Brontë cycle of fiction stands is a certain most important
truth about the enduring spirit of youth, the truth of the near
kinship between terror and joy. The Brontë heroine, dingily
dressed, badly educated, hampered by a humiliating inexperience, a
kind of ugly innocence, is yet, by the very fact of her solitude and
her gaucherie, full of the greatest delight that is possible to a
human being, the delight of expectation, the delight of an ardent and
flamboyant ignorance. She serves to show how futile it is of humanity
to suppose that pleasure can be attained chiefly by putting on
evening dress every evening, and having a box at the theatre every
first night. It is not the man of pleasure who has pleasure; it is
not the man of the world who appreciates the world. The man who has
learnt to do all conventional things perfectly has at the same time
learnt to do them prosaically. It is the awkward man, whose evening
dress does not fit him, whose gloves will not go on, whose
compliments will not come off, who is really full of the ancient
ecstasies of youth. He is frightened enough of society actually to
enjoy his triumphs. He has that element of fear which is one of the
eternal ingredients of joy. This spirit is the central spirit of the
Brontë novel. It is the epic of the exhilaration of the shy man.
As such it is of incalculable value in our time, of which the curse
is that it does not take joy reverently because it does not take it
fearfully. The shabby and inconspicuous governess of Charlotte
Brontë, with the small outlook and the small creed, had more
commerce with the awful and elemental forces which drive the world
than a legion of lawless minor poets. She approached the universe
with real simplicity, and, consequently, with real fear and delight.
She was, so to speak, shy before the multitude of the stars, and in
this she had possessed herself of the only force which can prevent
enjoyment being as black and barren as routine. The faculty of being
shy is the first and the most delicate of the powers of enjoyment.
The fear of the Lord is the beginning of pleasure.
Upon the whole, therefore, I think it
may justifiably be said that the dark wild youth of the Brontës
in their dark wild Yorkshire home has been somewhat exaggerated as a
necessary factor in their work and their conception. The emotions
with which they dealt were universal emotions, emotions of the
morning of existence, the springtide joy and the springtide terror.
Every one of us as a boy or girl has had some midnight dream of
nameless obstacle and unutterable menace, in which there was, under
whatever imbecile forms, all the deadly stress and panic of
“Wuthering Heights.” Every one of us has had a day-dream
of our own potential destiny not one atom more reasonable than “Jane
Eyre.” And the truth which the Brontës came to tell us is
the truth that many waters cannot quench love, and that suburban
respectability cannot touch or damp a secret enthusiasm. Clapham,
like every other earthly city, is built upon a volcano. Thousands of
people go to and fro in the wilderness of bricks and mortar, earning
mean wages, professing a mean religion, wearing a mean attire,
thousands of women who have never found any expression for their
exaltation or their tragedy but to go on working harder and yet
harder at dull and automatic employments, at scolding children or
stitching shirts. But out of all these silent ones one suddenly
became articulate, and spoke a resonant testimony, and her name was
Charlotte Brontë. Spreading around us upon every side to-day
like a huge and radiating geometrical figure are the endless branches
of the great city. There are times when we are almost stricken crazy,
as well we may be, by the multiplicity of those appalling
perspectives, the frantic arithmetic of that unthinkable population.
But this thought of ours is in truth nothing but a fancy. There are
no chains of houses; there are no crowds of men. The colossal diagram
of streets and houses is an illusion, the opium dream of a
speculative builder. Each of these men is supremely solitary and
supremely important to himself. Each of these houses stands in the
centre of the world. There is no single house of all those millions
which has not seemed to someone at some time the heart of all things
and the end of travel.
WILLIAM MORRIS AND HIS SCHOOL
It is proper enough that the
unveiling of the bust of William Morris should approximate to a
public festival, for while there have been many men of genius in the
Victorian era more despotic than he, there have been none so
representative. He represents not only that rapacious hunger for
beauty which has now for the first time become a serious problem in
the healthy life of humanity, but he represents also that honourable
instinct for finding beauty in common necessities of workmanship
which gives it a stronger and more bony structure. The time has
passed when William Morris was conceived to be irrelevant to be
described as a designer of wall-papers. If Morris had been a hatter
instead of a decorator, we should have become gradually and painfully
conscious of an improvement in our hats. If he had been a tailor, we
should have suddenly found our frock-coats trailing on the ground
with the grandeur of mediæval raiment. If he had been a
shoemaker, we should have found, with no little consternation, our
shoes gradually approximating to the antique sandal. As a
hairdresser, he would have invented some massing of the hair worthy
to be the crown of Venus; as an ironmonger, his nails would have had
some noble pattern, fit to be the nails of the Cross.
The limitations of William Morris,
whatever they were, were not the limitations of common decoration. It
is true that all his work, even his literary work, was in some sense
decorative, had in some degree the qualities of a splendid
wall-paper. His characters, his stories, his religious and political
views, had, in the most emphatic sense, length and breadth without
thickness. He seemed really to believe that men could enjoy a
perfectly flat felicity. He made no account of the unexplored and
explosive possibilities of human nature, of the unnameable terrors,
and the yet more unnameable hopes. So long as a man was graceful in
every circumstance, so long as he had the inspiring consciousness
that the chestnut colour of his hair was relieved against the blue
forest a mile behind, he would be serenely happy. So he would be, no
doubt, if he were really fitted for a decorative existence; if he
were a piece of exquisitely coloured card-board.
But although Morris took little
account of the terrible solidity of human nature–took little
account, so to speak, of human figures in the round, it is altogether
unfair to represent him as a mere æsthete. He perceived a great
public necessity and fulfilled it heroically. The difficulty with
which he grappled was one so immense that we shall have to be
separated from it by many centuries before we can really judge of it.
It was the problem of the elaborate and deliberate ugliness of the
most self-conscious of centuries. Morris at least saw the absurdity
of the thing. He felt it was monstrous that the modern man, who was
pre-eminently capable of realising the strangest and most
contradictory beauties, who could feel at once the fiery aureole of
the ascetic and the colossal calm of the Hellenic god, should
himself, by a farcical bathos, be buried in a black coat, and hidden
under a chimney-pot hat. He could not see why the harmless man who
desired to be an artist in raiment should be condemned to be, at
best, a black and white artist. It is indeed difficult to account for
the clinging curse of ugliness which blights everything brought forth
by the most prosperous of centuries. In all created nature there is
not, perhaps, anything so completely ugly as a pillar-box. Its shape
is the most unmeaning of shapes, its height and thickness just
neutralising each other; its colour is the most repulsive of
colours–a fat and soulless red, a red without a touch of blood
or fire, like the scarlet of dead men’s sins. Yet there is no
reason whatever why such hideousness should possess an object full of
civic dignity, the treasure-house of a thousand secrets, the fortress
of a thousand souls. If the old Greeks had had such an institution,
we may be sure that it would have been surmounted by the severe, but
graceful, figure of the god of letter-writing. If the mediæval
Christians has possessed it, it would have had a niche filled with
the golden aureole of St. Rowland of the Postage Stamps. As it is,
there it stands at all our street-corners, disguising one of the most
beautiful of ideas under one of the most preposterous of forms. It is
useless to deny that the miracles of science have not been such an
incentive to art and imagination as were the miracles of religion. If
men in the twelfth century had been told that the lightning had been
driven for leagues underground, and had dragged at its destroying
tail loads of laughing human beings, and if they had then been told
that the people alluded to this pulverising portent chirpily as “The
Twopenny Tube,” they would have called down the fire of Heaven
on us as a race of half-witted atheists. Probably they would have
been quite right.
This clear and fine perception of
what may be called the anæsthetic element in the Victorian era
was, undoubtedly, the work of a great reformer: it requires a fine
effort of the imagination to see an evil that surrounds us on every
side. The manner in which Morris carried out his crusade may,
considering the circumstances, be called triumphant. Our carpets
began to bloom under our feet like the meadows in spring, and our
hitherto prosaic stools and sofas seemed growing legs and arms at
their own wild will. An element of freedom and rugged dignity came in
with plain and strong ornaments of copper and iron. So delicate and
universal has been the revolution in domestic art that almost every
family in England has had its taste cunningly and treacherously
improved, and if we look back at the early Victorian drawing-rooms it
is only to realise the strange but essential truth that art, or human
decoration, has, nine times out of ten in history, made things uglier
than they were before, from the “coiffure” of a Papuan
savage to the wall-paper of a British merchant in 1830.
But great and beneficent as was the
æsthetic revolution of Morris, there was a very definite limit
to it. It did not lie only in the fact that his revolution was in
truth a reaction, though this was a partial explanation of his
partial failure. When he was denouncing the dresses of modern ladies,
“upholstered like arm-chairs instead of being draped like
women,” as he forcibly expressed it, he would hold up for
practical imitation the costumes and handicrafts of the Middle Ages.
Further than this retrogressive and imitative movement he never
seemed to go. Now, the men of the time of Chaucer had many evil
qualities, but there was at least one exhibition of moral weakness
they did not give. They would have laughed at the idea of dressing
themselves in the manner of the bowmen at the battle of Senlac, or
painting themselves an æsthetic blue, after the custom of the
ancient Britons. They would not have called that a movement at all.
Whatever was beautiful in their dress or manners sprang honestly and
naturally out of the life they led and preferred to lead. And it may
surely be maintained that any real advance in the beauty of modern
dress must spring honestly and naturally out of the life we lead and
prefer to lead. We are not altogether without hints and hopes of such
a change, in the growing orthodoxy of rough and athletic costumes.
But if this cannot be, it will be no substitute or satisfaction to
turn life into an interminable historical fancy-dress ball.
But the limitation of Morris’s
work lay deeper than this. We may best suggest it by a method after
his own heart. Of all the various works he performed, none, perhaps,
was so splendidly and solidly valuable as his great protest for the
fables and superstitions of mankind. He has the supreme credit of
showing that the fairy tales contain the deepest truth of the earth,
the real record of men’s feeling for things. Trifling details
may be inaccurate, Jack may not have climbed up so tall a beanstalk,
or killed so tall a giant; but it is not such things that make a
story false; it is a far different class of things that makes every
modern book of history as false as the father of lies; ingenuity,
self-consciousness, hypocritical impartiality. It appears to us that
of all the fairy-tales none contains so vital a moral truth as the
old story, existing in many forms, of Beauty and the Beast. There is
written, with all the authority of a human scripture, the eternal and
essential truth that until we love a thing in all its ugliness we
cannot make it beautiful. This was the weak point in William Morris
as a reformer: that he sought to reform modern life, and that he
hated modern life instead of loving it. Modern London is indeed a
beast, big enough and black enough to be the beast in Apocalypse,
blazing with a million eyes, and roaring with a million voices. But
unless the poet can love this fabulous monster as he is, can feel
with some generous excitement his massive and mysterious
joie-de-vivre, the vast scale of his iron anatomy and the
beating of his thunderous heart, he cannot and will not change the
beast into the fairy prince. Morris’s disadvantage was that he
was not honestly a child of the nineteenth century: he could not
understand its fascination, and consequently he could not really
develop it. An abiding testimony to his tremendous personal influence
in the æsthetic world is the vitality and recurrence of the
Arts and Crafts Exhibitions, which are steeped in his personality
like a chapel in that of a saint. If we look round at the exhibits in
one of these æsthetic shows, we shall be struck by the large
mass of modern objects that the decorative school leaves untouched.
There is a noble instinct for giving the right touch of beauty to
common and necessary things, but the things that are so touched are
the ancient things, the things that always to some extent commended
themselves to the lover of beauty. There are beautiful gates,
beautiful fountains, beautiful cups, beautiful chairs, beautiful
reading-desks. But there are no modern things made beautiful. There
are no beautiful lamp-posts, beautiful letter-boxes, beautiful
engines, beautiful bicycles. The spirit of William Morris has not
seized hold of the century and made its humblest necessities
beautiful. And this was because, with all his healthiness and energy,
he had not the supreme courage to face the ugliness of things; Beauty
shrank from the Beast and the fairy-tale had a different ending.
But herein, indeed, lay Morris’s
deepest claim to the name of a great reformer: that he left his work
incomplete. There is, perhaps, no better proof that a man is a mere
meteor, merely barren and brilliant, than that his work is done
perfectly. A man like Morris draws attention to needs he cannot
supply. In after-years we may have perhaps a newer and more daring
Arts and Crafts Exhibition. In it we shall not decorate the armour of
the twelfth century, but the machinery of the twentieth. A lamp-post
shall be wrought nobly in twisted iron, fit to hold the sanctity of
fire. A pillar-box shall be carved with figures emblematical of the
secrets of comradeship and the silence and honour of the State.
Railway signals, of all earthly things the most poetical, the
coloured stars of life and death, shall be lamps of green and crimson
worthy of their terrible and faithful service. But if ever this
gradual and genuine movement of our time towards beauty–not
backwards, but forwards–does truly come about, Morris will be
the first prophet of it. Poet of the childhood of nations, craftsman
in the new honesties of art, prophet of a merrier and wiser life, his
full-blooded enthusiasm will be remembered when human life has once
more assumed flamboyant colours and proved that this painful greenish
grey of the æsthetic twilight in which we now live is, in spite
of all the pessimists, not of the greyness of death, but the greyness
of dawn.
OPTIMISM OF BYRON
Everything is against our
appreciating the spirit and the age of Byron. The age that has just
passed from us is always like a dream when we wake in the morning, a
thing incredible and centuries away. And the world of Byron seems a
sad and faded world, a weird and inhuman world, where men were
romantic in whiskers, ladies lived, apparently, in bowers, and the
very word has the sound of a piece of stage scenery. Roses and
nightingales recur in their poetry with the monotonous elegance of a
wall-paper pattern. The whole is like a revel of dead men, a revel
with splendid vesture and half-witted faces.
But the more shrewdly and earnestly
we study the histories of men, the less ready shall we be to make use
of the word “artificial.” Nothing in the world has ever
been artificial. Many customs, many dresses, many works of art are
branded with artificiality because they exhibit vanity and
self-consciousness: as if vanity were not a deep and elemental thing,
like love and hate and the fear of death. Vanity may be found in
darkling deserts, in the hermit and in the wild beasts that crawl
around him. It may be good or evil, but assuredly it is not
artificial: vanity is a voice out of the abyss.
The remarkable fact is, however, and
it bears strongly on the present position of Byron, that when a thing
is unfamiliar to us, when it is remote and the product of some other
age or spirit, we think it not savage or terrible, but merely
artificial. There are many instances of this: a fair one is the case
of tropical plants and birds. When we see some of the monstrous and
flamboyant blossoms that enrich the equatorial woods, we do not feel
that they are conflagrations of nature; silent explosions of her
frightful energy. We simply find it hard to believe that they are not
wax flowers grown under a glass case. When we see some of the tropic
birds, with their tiny bodies attached to gigantic beaks, we do not
feel that they are freaks of the fierce humour of Creation. We almost
believe that they are toys out of a child’s play-box,
artificially carved and artificially coloured. So it is with the
great convulsion of Nature which was known as Byronism. The volcano
is not an extinct volcano now; it is the dead stick of a rocket. It
is the remains not of a natural but of an artificial fire.
But Byron and Byronism were something
immeasurably greater than anything that is represented by such a view
as this: their real value and meaning are indeed little understood.
The first of the mistakes about Byron lies in the fact that he is
treated as a pessimist. True, he treated himself as such, but a
critic can hardly have even a slight knowledge of Byron without
knowing that he had the smallest amount of knowledge of himself that
ever fell to the lot of an intelligent man. The real character of
what is known as Byron’s pessimism is better worth study than
any real pessimism could ever be.
It is the standing peculiarity of
this curious world of ours that almost everything in it has been
extolled enthusiastically and invariably extolled to the disadvantage
of everything else.
One after another almost every one of
the phenomena of the universe has been declared to be alone capable
of making life worth living. Books, love, business, religion,
alcohol, abstract truth, private emotion, money, simplicity,
mysticism, hard work, a life close to nature, a life close to
Belgrave Square are every one of them passionately maintained by
somebody to be so good that they redeem the evil of an otherwise
indefensible world. Thus, while the world is almost always condemned
in summary, it is always justified, and indeed extolled, in detail
after detail.
Existence has been praised and
absolved by a chorus of pessimists. The work of giving thanks to
Heaven is, as it were, divided ingeniously among them. Schopenhauer
is told off as a kind of librarian in the House of God, to sing the
praises of the austere pleasures of the mind. Carlyle, as steward,
undertakes the working department and eulogises a life of labour in
the fields. Omar Khayyam is established in the cellar, and swears
that it is the only room in the house. Even the blackest of
pessimistic artists enjoys his art. At the precise moment that he has
written some shameless and terrible indictment of Creation, his one
pang of joy in the achievement joins the universal chorus of
gratitude, with the scent of the wild flower and the song of the
bird.
Now Byron had a sensational
popularity, and that popularity was, as far as words and explanations
go, founded upon his pessimism. He was adored by an overwhelming
majority, almost every individual of which despised the majority of
mankind. But when we come to regard the matter a little more deeply
we tend in some degree to cease to believe in this popularity of the
pessimist. The popularity of pure and unadulterated pessimism is an
oddity; it is almost a contradiction in terms. Men would no more
receive the news of the failure of existence or of the harmonious
hostility of the stars with ardour or popular rejoicing than they
would light bonfires for the arrival of cholera or dance a breakdown
when they were condemned to be hanged. When the pessimist is popular
it must always be not because he shows all things to be bad, but
because he shows some things to be good.
Men can only join in a chorus of
praise, even if it is the praise of denunciation. The man who is
popular must be optimistic about something, even if he is only
optimistic about pessimism. And this was emphatically the case with
Byron and the Byronists. Their real popularity was founded not upon
the fact that they blamed everything, but upon the fact that they
praised something. They heaped curses upon man, but they used man
merely as a foil. The things they wished to praise by comparison were
the energies of Nature. Man was to them what talk and fashion were to
Carlyle, what philosophical and religious quarrels were to Omar, what
the whole race after practical happiness was to Schopenhauer, the
thing which must be censured in order that somebody else may be
exalted. It was merely a recognition of the fact that one cannot
write in white chalk except on a black-board.
Surely it is ridiculous to maintain
seriously that Byron’s love of the desolate and inhuman in
nature was the mark of vital scepticism and depression. When a young
man can elect deliberately to walk alone in winter by the side of the
shattering sea, when he takes pleasure in storms and stricken peaks,
and the lawless melancholy of the older earth, we may deduce with the
certainty of logic that he is very young and very happy. There is a
certain darkness which we see in wine when seen in shadow; we see it
again in the night that has just buried a gorgeous sunset. The wine
seems black, and yet at the same time powerfully and almost
impossibly red; the sky seems black, and yet at the same time to be
only too dense a blend of purple and green. Such was the darkness
which lay around the Byronic school. Darkness with them was only too
dense a purple. They would prefer the sullen hostility of the earth
because amid all the cold and darkness their own hearts were flaming
like their own firesides.
Matters are very different with the
more modern school of doubt and lamentation. The last movement of
pessimism is perhaps expressed in Mr. Aubrey Beardsley’s
allegorical designs. Here we have to deal with a pessimism which
tends naturally not towards the oldest elements of the cosmos, but
towards the last and most fantastic fripperies of artificial life.
Byronism tended towards the desert; the new pessimism towards the
restaurant. Byronism was a revolt against artificiality; the new
pessimism is a revolt in its favour.
The Byronic young man had an
affectation of sincerity; the decadent, going a step deeper into the
avenues of the unreal, has positively an affectation of affectation.
And it is by their fopperies and their frivolities that we know that
their sinister philosophy is sincere; in their lights and garlands
and ribbons we read their indwelling despair. It was so, indeed, with
Byron himself; his really bitter moments were his frivolous moments.
He went on year after year calling down fire upon mankind, summoning
the deluge and the destructive sea and all the ultimate energies of
nature to sweep away the cities of the spawn of man. But through all
this his subconscious mind was not that of a despairer; on the
contrary, there is something of a kind of lawless faith in thus
parleying with such immense and immemorial brutalities. It was not
until the time in which he wrote “Don Juan” that he
really lost this inward warmth and geniality, and a sudden shout of
hilarious laughter announced to the world that Lord Byron had really
become a pessimist.
One of the best tests in the world of
what a poet really means is his metre. He may be a hypocrite in his
metaphysics, but he cannot be a hypocrite in his prosody. And all the
time that Byron’s language is of horror and emptiness, his
metre is a bounding pas de quatre. He may arraign existence on
the most deadly charges, he may condemn it with the most desolating
verdict, but he cannot alter the fact that on some walk in a spring
morning when all the limbs are swinging and all the blood alive in
the body, the lips may be caught repeating:
“Oh,
there’s not a joy the world can give like that it takes
away, When the glow of early youth declines in beauty’s dull
decay; ’Tis not upon the cheek of youth the blush that fades
so fast, But the tender bloom of heart is gone ere youth itself be
past.”
That automatic recitation is the
answer to the whole pessimism of Byron.
The truth is that Byron was one of a
class who may be called the unconscious optimists, who are very
often, indeed, the most uncompromising conscious pessimists, because
the exuberance of their nature demands for an adversary a dragon as
big as the world. But the whole of his essential and unconscious
being was spirited and confident, and that unconscious being, long
disguised and buried under emotional artifices, suddenly sprang into
prominence in the face of a cold, hard, political necessity. In
Greece he heard the cry of reality, and at the time that he was
dying, he began to live. He heard suddenly the call of that buried
and subconscious happiness which is in all of us, and which may
emerge suddenly at the sight of the grass of a meadow or the spears
of the enemy.
POPE AND THE ART OF SATIRE
The general critical theory common in
this and the last century is that it was very easy for the imitators
of Pope to write English poetry. The classical couplet was a thing
that anyone could do. So far as that goes, one may justifiably answer
by asking anyone to try. It may be easier really to have wit, than
really, in the boldest and most enduring sense, to have imagination.
But it is immeasurably easier to pretend to have imagination than to
pretend to have wit. A man may indulge in a sham rhapsody, because it
may be the triumph of a rhapsody to be unintelligible. But a man
cannot indulge in a sham joke, because it is the ruin of a joke to be
unintelligible. A man may pretend to be a poet: he can no more
pretend to be a wit than he can pretend to bring rabbits out of a hat
without having learnt to be a conjuror. Therefore, it may be
submitted, there was a certain discipline in the old antithetical
couplet of Pope and his followers. If it did not permit of the great
liberty of wisdom used by the minority of great geniuses, neither did
it permit of the great liberty of folly which is used by the majority
of small writers. A prophet could not be a poet in those days,
perhaps, but at least a fool could not be a poet. If we take, for the
sake of example, such a line as Pope’s:
“Damn
with faint praise, assent with civil leer,”
the test is comparatively simple. A
great poet would not have written such a line, perhaps. But a minor
poet could not.
Supposing that a lyric poet of the
new school really had to deal with such an idea as that expressed in
Pope’s line about Man:
“A
being darkly wise and rudely great,”
Is it really so certain that he would
go deeper into the matter than that old antithetical jingle goes? I
venture to doubt whether he would really be any wiser or weirder or
more imaginative or more profound. The one thing that he would really
be, would be longer. Instead of writing,
“A
being darkly wise and rudely great,”
the contemporary poet, in his
elaborately ornamented book of verses, would produce something like
the following:
“A
creature Of feature More dark, more dark, more dark than
skies, Yea, darkly wise, yea, darkly wise: Darkly wise as a
formless fate. And if he be great, If he be great, then rudely
great, Rudely great as a plough that plies, And darkly wise,
and darkly wise.”
Have we really learnt to think more
broadly? Or have we only learnt to spread our thoughts thinner? I
have a dark suspicion that a modern poet might manufacture an
admirable lyric out of almost every line of Pope.
There is, of course, an idea in our
time that the very antithesis of the typical line of Pope is a mark
of artificiality. I shall have occasion more than once to point out
that nothing in the world has ever been artificial. But certainly
antithesis is not artificial. An element of paradox runs through the
whole of existence itself. It begins in the realm of ultimate physics
and metaphysics, in the two facts that we cannot imagine a space that
is infinite, and that we cannot imagine a space that is finite. It
runs through the inmost complications of divinity, in that we cannot
conceive that Christ in the wilderness was truly pure, unless we also
conceive that he desired to sin. It runs, in the same manner, through
all the minor matters of morals, so that we cannot imagine courage
existing except in conjunction with fear, or magnanimity existing
except in conjunction with some temptation to meanness. If Pope and
his followers caught this echo of natural irrationality, they were
not any the more artificial. Their antitheses were fully in harmony
with existence, which is itself a contradiction in terms.
Pope was really a great poet; he was
the last great poet of civilisation. Immediately after the fall of
him and his school come Burns and Byron, and the reaction towards the
savage and the elemental. But to Pope civilisation was still an
exciting experiment. Its perruques and ruffles were to him what
feathers and bangles are to a South Sea Islander–the real
romance of civilisation. And in all the forms of art which peculiarly
belong to civilisation, he was supreme. In one especially he was
supreme–the great and civilised art of satire. And in this we
have fallen away utterly.
We have had a great revival in our
time of the cult of violence and hostility. Mr. Henley and his young
men have an infinite number of furious epithets with which to
overwhelm anyone who differs from them. It is not a placid or
untroubled position to be Mr. Henley’s enemy, though we know
that it is certainly safer than to be his friend. And yet, despite
all this, these people produce no satire. Political and social satire
is a lost art, like pottery and stained glass. It may be worth while
to make some attempt to point out a reason for this.
It may seem a singular observation to
say that we are not generous enough to write great satire. This,
however, is approximately a very accurate way of describing the case.
To write great satire, to attack a man so that he feels the attack
and half acknowledges its justice, it is necessary to have a certain
intellectual magnanimity which realises the merits of the opponent as
well as his defects. This is, indeed, only another way of putting the
simple truth that in order to attack an army we must know not only
its weak points, but also its strong points. England in the present
season and spirit fails in satire for the same simple reason that it
fails in war: it despises the enemy. In matters of battle and
conquest we have got firmly rooted in our minds the idea (an idea fit
for the philosophers of Bedlam) that we can best trample on a people
by ignoring all the particular merits which give them a chance of
trampling upon us. It has become a breach of etiquette to praise the
enemy; whereas, when the enemy is strong, every honest scout ought to
praise the enemy. It is impossible to vanquish an army without having
a full account of its strength. It is impossible to satirise a man
without having a full account of his virtues. It is too much the
custom in politics to describe a political opponent as utterly
inhuman, as utterly careless of his country, as utterly cynical,
which no man ever was since the beginning of the world. This kind of
invective may often have a great superficial success: it may hit the
mood of the moment; it may raise excitement and applause; it may
impress millions. But there is one man among all those millions whom
it does not impress, whom it hardly ever touches; that is the man
against whom it is directed. The one person for whom the whole satire
has been written in vain is the man whom it is the whole object of
the institution of satire to reach. He knows that such a description
of him is not true. He knows that he is not utterly unpatriotic, or
utterly self-seeking, or utterly barbarous and revengeful. He knows
that he is an ordinary man, and that he can count as many kindly
memories, as many humane instincts, as many hours of decent work and
responsibility as any other ordinary man. But behind all this he has
his real weaknesses, the real ironies of his soul: behind all these
ordinary merits lie the mean compromises, the craven silences, the
sullen vanities, the secret brutalities, the unmanly visions of
revenge. It is to these that satire should reach if it is to touch
the man at whom it is aimed. And to reach these it must pass and
salute a whole army of virtues.
If we turn to the great English
satirists of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, for example,
we find that they had this rough, but firm, grasp of the size and
strength, the value and the best points of their adversary. Dryden,
before hewing Ahitophel in pieces, gives a splendid and spirited
account of the insane valour and inspired cunning of the
“daring
pilot in extremity,”
who was more untrustworthy in calm
than in storm, and
“Steered
too near the rocks to boast his wit.”
The whole is, so far as it goes, a
sound and picturesque version of the great Shaftesbury. It would, in
many ways, serve as a very sound and picturesque account of Lord
Randolph Churchill. But here comes in very pointedly the difference
between our modern attempts at satire and the ancient achievement of
it. The opponents of Lord Randolph Churchill, both Liberal and
Conservative, did not satirise him nobly and honestly, as one of
those great wits to madness near allied. They represented him as a
mere puppy, a silly and irreverent upstart whose impudence supplied
the lack of policy and character. Churchill had grave and even gross
faults, a certain coarseness, a certain hard boyish assertiveness, a
certain lack of magnanimity, a certain peculiar patrician vulgarity.
But he was a much larger man than satire depicted him, and therefore
the satire could not and did not overwhelm him. And here we have the
cause of the failure of contemporary satire, that it has no
magnanimity, that is to say, no patience. It cannot endure to be told
that its opponent has his strong points, just as Mr. Chamberlain
could not endure to be told that the Boers had a regular army. It can
be content with nothing except persuading itself that its opponent is
utterly bad or utterly stupid–that is, that he is what he is
not and what nobody else is. If we take any prominent politician of
the day–such, for example, as Sir William Harcourt–we
shall find that this is the point in which all party invective fails.
The Tory satire at the expense of Sir William Harcourt is always
desperately endeavouring to represent that he is inept, that he makes
a fool of himself, that he is disagreeable and disgraceful and
untrustworthy. The defect of all that is that we all know that it is
untrue. Everyone knows that Sir William Harcourt is not inept, but is
almost the ablest Parliamentarian now alive. Everyone knows that he
is not disagreeable or disgraceful, but a gentleman of the old school
who is on excellent social terms with his antagonists. Everyone knows
that he is not untrustworthy, but a man of unimpeachable honour who
is much trusted. Above all, he knows it himself, and is therefore
affected by the satire exactly as any one of us would be if we were
accused of being black or of keeping a shop for the receiving of
stolen goods. We might be angry at the libel, but not at the satire:
for a man is angry at a libel because it is false, but at a satire
because it is true.
Mr. Henley and his young men are very
fond of invective and satire; if they wish to know the reason of
their failure in these things, they need only turn to the opening of
Pope’s superb attack upon Addison. The Henleyite’s idea
of satirising a man is to express a violent contempt for him, and by
the heat of this to persuade others and himself that the man is
contemptible. I remember reading a satiric attack on Mr. Gladstone by
one of the young anarchic Tories, which began by asserting that Mr.
Gladstone was a bad public speaker. If these people would, as I have
said, go quietly and read Pope’s “Atticus,” they
would see how a great satirist approaches a great enemy:
“Peace
to all such! But were there one whose fires True genius kindles,
and fair fame inspires, Blest with each talent, and each art to
please, And born to write, converse, and live with ease. Should
such a man–”
And then follows the torrent of that
terrible criticism. Pope was not such a fool as to try to make out
that Addison was a fool. He knew that Addison was not a fool, and he
knew that Addison knew it. But hatred, in Pope’s case, had
become so great and, I was almost going to say, so pure, that it
illuminated all things, as love illuminates all things. He said what
was really wrong with Addison; and in calm and clear and everlasting
colours he painted the picture of the evil of the literary
temperament:
“Bear,
like the Turk, no brother near the throne, View him with scornful,
yet with jealous eyes, And hate for arts that caused himself to
rise. Like Cato give his little Senate laws, And sit attentive
to his own applause. While wits and templars every sentence
raise, And wonder with a foolish face of praise.”
This is the kind of thing which
really goes to the mark at which it aims. It is penetrated with
sorrow and a kind of reverence, and it is addressed directly to a
man. This is no mock-tournament to gain the applause of the crowd. It
is a deadly duel by the lonely seashore.
In current political materialism
there is everywhere the assumption that, without understanding
anything of his case or his merits, we can benefit a man practically.
Without understanding his case and his merits, we cannot even hurt
him.
FRANCIS
Asceticism is a thing which, in its
very nature, we tend in these days to misunderstand. Asceticism, in
the religious sense, is the repudiation of the great mass of human
joys because of the supreme joyfulness of the one joy, the religious
joy. But asceticism is not in the least confined to religious
asceticism: there is scientific asceticism which asserts that truth
is alone satisfying: there is æsthetic asceticism which asserts
that art is alone satisfying: there is amatory asceticism which
asserts that love is alone satisfying. There is even epicurean
asceticism, which asserts that beer and skittles are alone
satisfying. Wherever the manner of praising anything involves the
statement that the speaker could live with that thing alone, there
lies the germ and essence of asceticism. When William Morris, for
example, says that “love is enough,” it is obvious that
he asserts in those words that art, science, politics, ambition,
money, houses, carriages, concerts, gloves, walking-sticks,
door-knockers, railway-stations, cathedrals, and any other things one
may choose to tabulate are unnecessary. When Omar Khayyam says:
“A
book of verses underneath the bough, A loaf of bread, a jug of
wine, and thou Beside me singing in the wilderness– O
wilderness were Paradise enow.”
It is clear that he speaks fully as
much ascetically as he does æsthetically. He makes a list of
things and says that he wants no more. The same thing was done by a
mediæval monk. Examples might, of course, be multiplied a
hundred-fold. One of the most genuinely poetical of our younger poets
says, as the one thing certain, that
“From
quiet home and first beginning Out to the undiscovered
ends– There’s nothing worth the wear of winning But
laughter and the love of friends.”
Here we have a perfect example of the
main important fact, that all true joy expresses itself in terms of
asceticism.
But if, in any case, it should happen
that a class or a generation lose the sense of the peculiar kind of
joy which is being celebrated, they immediately begin to call the
enjoyers of that joy gloomy and self-destroying. The most formidable
liberal philosophers have called the monks melancholy because they
denied themselves the pleasures of liberty and marriage. They might
as well call the trippers on a Bank Holiday melancholy because they
deny themselves, as a rule, the pleasures of silence and meditation.
A simpler and stronger example is, however, to hand. If ever it
should happen that the system of English athletics should vanish from
the public schools and the universities, if science should supply
some new and non-competitive manner of perfecting the physique, if
public ethics swung round to an attitude of absolute contempt and
indifference towards the feeling called sport, then it is easy to see
what would happen. Future historians would simply state that in the
dark days of Queen Victoria young men at Oxford and Cambridge were
subjected to a horrible sort of religious torture. They were
forbidden, by fantastic monastic rules, to indulge in wine or tobacco
during certain arbitrarily fixed periods of time, before certain
brutal fights and festivals. Bigots insisted on their rising at
unearthly hours and running violently around fields for no object.
Many men ruined their health in these dens of superstition, many died
there. All this is perfectly true and irrefutable. Athleticism in
England is an asceticism, as much as the monastic rules. Men have
overstrained themselves and killed themselves through English
athleticism. There is one difference and one only: we do feel the
love of sport; we do not feel the love of religious offices. We see
only the price in the one case and only the purchase in the other.
The only question that remains is
what was the joy of the old Christian ascetics of which their
asceticism was merely the purchasing price? The mere possibility of
the query is an extraordinary example of the way in which we miss the
main points of human history. We are looking at humanity too close,
and see only the details and not the vast and dominant features. We
look at the rise of Christianity, and conceive it as a rise of
self-abnegation and almost of pessimism. It does not occur to us that
the mere assertion that this raging and confounding universe is
governed by justice and mercy is a piece of staggering optimism fit
to set all men capering. The detail over which these monks went mad
with joy was the universe itself; the only thing really worthy of
enjoyment. The white daylight shone over all the world, the endless
forests stood up in their order. The lightning awoke and the tree
fell and the sea gathered into mountains and the ship went down, and
all these disconnected and meaningless and terrible objects were all
part of one dark and fearful conspiracy of goodness, one merciless
scheme of mercy. That this scheme of Nature was not accurate or well
founded is perfectly tenable, but surely it is not tenable that it
was not optimistic. We insist, however, upon treating this matter
tail foremost. We insist that the ascetics were pessimists because
they gave up threescore years and ten for an eternity of happiness.
We forget that the bare proposition of an eternity of happiness is by
its very nature ten thousand times more optimistic than ten thousand
pagan saturnalias.
Mr. Adderley’s life of Francis
of Assisi does not, of course, bring this out; nor does it fully
bring out the character of Francis. It has rather the tone of a
devotional book. A devotional book is an excellent thing, but we do
not look in it for the portrait of a man, for the same reason that we
do not look in a love-sonnet for the portrait of a woman, because men
in such conditions of mind not only apply all virtues to their idol,
but all virtues in equal quantities. There is no outline, because the
artist cannot bear to put in a black line. This blaze of benediction,
this conflict between lights, has its place in poetry, not in
biography. The successful examples of it may be found, for instance,
in the more idealistic odes of Spenser. The design is sometimes
almost indecipherable, for the poet draws in silver upon white.
It is natural, of course, that Mr.
Adderley should see Francis primarily as the founder of the
Franciscan Order. We suspect this was only one, perhaps a minor one,
of the things that he was; we suspect that one of the minor things
that Christ did was to found Christianity. But the vast practical
work of Francis is assuredly not to be ignored, for this amazingly
unworldly and almost maddeningly simple-minded infant was one of the
most consistently successful men that ever fought with this bitter
world. It is the custom to say that the secret of such men is their
profound belief in themselves, and this is true, but not all the
truth. Workhouses and lunatic asylums are thronged with men who
believe in themselves. Of Francis it is far truer to say that the
secret of his success was his profound belief in other people, and it
is the lack of this that has commonly been the curse of these obscure
Napoleons. Francis always assumed that everyone must be just as
anxious about their common relative, the water-rat, as he was. He
planned a visit to the Emperor to draw his attention to the needs of
“his little sisters the larks.” He used to talk to any
thieves and robbers he met about their misfortune in being unable to
give rein to their desire for holiness. It was an innocent habit, and
doubtless the robbers often “got round him,” as the
phrase goes. Quite as often, however, they discovered that he had
“got round” them, and discovered the other side, the side
of secret nobility.
Conceiving of St. Francis as
primarily the founder of the Franciscan Order, Mr. Adderley opens his
narrative with an admirable sketch of the history of Monasticism in
Europe, which is certainly the best thing in the book. He
distinguishes clearly and fairly between the Manichæan ideal
that underlies so much of Eastern Monasticism and the ideal of
self-discipline which never wholly vanished from the Christian form.
But he does not throw any light on what must be for the outsider the
absorbing problem of this Catholic asceticism, for the excellent
reason that, not being an outsider, he does not find it a problem at
all.
To most people, however, there is a
fascinating inconsistency in the position of St. Francis. He
expressed in loftier and bolder language than any earthly thinker the
conception that laughter is as divine as tears. He called his monks
the mountebanks of God. He never forgot to take pleasure in a bird as
it flashed past him, or a drop of water, as it fell from his finger:
he was, perhaps, the happiest of the sons of men. Yet this man
undoubtedly founded his whole polity on the negation of what we think
the most imperious necessities; in his three vows of poverty,
chastity, and obedience, he denied to himself and those he loved
most, property, love, and liberty. Why was it that the most
large-hearted and poetic spirits in that age found their most
congenial atmosphere in these awful renunciations? Why did he who
loved where all men were blind, seek to blind himself where all men
loved? Why was he a monk, and not a troubadour? These questions are
far too large to be answered fully here, but in any life of Francis
they ought at least to have been asked; we have a suspicion that if
they were answered, we should suddenly find that much of the enigma
of this sullen time of ours was answered also. So it was with the
monks. The two great parties in human affairs are only the party
which sees life black against white, and the party which sees it
white against black, the party which macerates and blackens itself
with sacrifice because the background is full of the blaze of an
universal mercy, and the party which crowns itself with flowers and
lights itself with bridal torches because it stands against a black
curtain of incalculable night. The revellers are old, and the monks
are young. It was the monks who were the spendthrifts of happiness,
and we who are its misers.
Doubtless, as is apparent from Mr.
Adderley’s book, the clear and tranquil life of the Three Vows
had a fine and delicate effect on the genius of Francis. He was
primarily a poet. The perfection of his literary instinct is shown in
his naming the fire “brother,” and the water “sister,”
in the quaint demagogic dexterity of the appeal in the sermon to the
fishes “that they alone were saved in the Flood.” In the
amazingly minute and graphic dramatisation of the life,
disappointments, and excuses of any shrub or beast that he happened
to be addressing, his genius has a curious resemblance to that of
Burns. But if he avoided the weakness of Burns’ verses to
animals, the occasional morbidity, bombast, and moralisation on
himself, the credit is surely due to a cleaner and more transparent
life.
The general attitude of St. Francis,
like that of his Master, embodied a kind of terrible common sense.
The famous remark of the Caterpillar in “Alice in
Wonderland”–”Why not?” impresses us as his
general motto. He could not see why he should not be on good terms
with all things. The pomp of war and ambition, the great empire of
the Middle Ages, and all its fellows begin to look tawdry and
top-heavy, under the rationality of that innocent stare. His
questions were blasting and devastating, like the questions of a
child. He would not have been afraid even of the nightmares of
cosmogony, for he had no fear in him. To him the world was small, not
because he had any views as to its size, but for the reason that
gossiping ladies find it small, because so many relatives were to be
found in it. If you had taken him to the loneliest star that the
madness of an astronomer can conceive, he would have only beheld in
it the features of a new friend.
ROSTAND
When “Cyrano de Bergerac”
was published, it bore the subordinate title of a heroic comedy. We
have no tradition in English literature which would justify us in
calling a comedy heroic, though there was once a poet who called a
comedy divine. By the current modern conception, the hero has his
place in a tragedy, and the one kind of strength which is
systematically denied to him is the strength to succeed. That the
power of a man’s spirit might possibly go to the length of
turning a tragedy into a comedy is not admitted; nevertheless, almost
all the primitive legends of the world are comedies, not only in the
sense that they have a happy ending, but in the sense that they are
based upon a certain optimistic assumption that the hero is destined
to be the destroyer of the monster. Singularly enough, this modern
idea of the essential disastrous character of life, when seriously
considered, connects itself with a hyper-æsthetic view of
tragedy and comedy which is largely due to the influence of modern
France, from which the great heroic comedies of Monsieur Rostand have
come. The French genius has an instinct for remedying its own evil
work, and France gives always the best cure for “Frenchiness.”
The idea of comedy which is held in England by the school which pays
most attention to the technical niceties of art is a view which
renders such an idea as that of heroic comedy quite impossible. The
fundamental conception in the minds of the majority of our younger
writers is that comedy is, par excellence, a fragile thing. It
is conceived to be a conventional world of the most absolutely
delicate and gimcrack description. Such stories as Mr. Max Beerbohm’s
“Happy Hypocrite” are conceptions which would vanish or
fall into utter nonsense if viewed by one single degree too
seriously. But great comedy, the comedy of Shakespeare or Sterne, not
only can be, but must be, taken seriously. There is nothing to which
a man must give himself up with more faith and self-abandonment than
to genuine laughter. In such comedies one laughs with the heroes, and
not at them. The humour which steeps the stories of Falstaff and
Uncle Toby is a cosmic and philosophic humour, a geniality which goes
down to the depths. It is not superficial reading, it is not even,
strictly speaking, light reading. Our sympathies are as much
committed to the characters as if they were the predestined victims
in a Greek tragedy. The modern writer of comedies may be said to
boast of the brittleness of his characters. He seems always on the
eve of knocking his puppets to pieces. When John Oliver Hobbes wrote
for the first time a comedy of serious emotions, she named it, with a
thinly-disguised contempt for her own work, “A Sentimental
Comedy.” The ground of this conception of the artificiality of
comedy is a profound pessimism. Life in the eyes of these mournful
buffoons is itself an utterly tragic thing; comedy must be as hollow
as a grinning mask. It is a refuge from the world, and not even,
properly speaking, a part of it. Their wit is a thin sheet of shining
ice over the eternal waters of bitterness.
“Cyrano de
Bergerac” came to us as the new decoration of an old truth,
that merriment was one of the world’s natural flowers, and not
one of its exotics. The gigantesque levity, the flamboyant eloquence,
the Rabelaisian puns and digressions were seen to be once more what
they had been in Rabelais, the mere outbursts of a human sympathy and
bravado as old and solid as the stars. The human spirit demanded wit
as headlong and haughty as its will. All was expressed in the words
of Cyrano at his highest moment of happiness, Il
me faut des géants. An essential
aspect of this question of heroic comedy is the question of drama in
rhyme. There is nothing that affords so easy a point of attack for
the dramatic realist as the conduct of a play in verse. According to
his canons, it is indeed absurd to represent a number of characters
facing some terrible crisis in their lives by capping rhymes like a
party playing bouts rimés.
In his eyes it must appear somewhat ridiculous that two enemies
taunting each other with insupportable insults should obligingly
provide each other with metrical spacing and neat and convenient
rhymes. But the whole of this view rests finally upon the fact that
few persons, if any, to-day understand what is meant by a poetical
play. It is a singular thing that those poetical plays which are now
written in England by the most advanced students of the drama follow
exclusively the lines of Maeterlinck, and use verse and rhyme for the
adornment of a profoundly tragic theme. But rhyme has a supreme
appropriateness for the treatment of the higher comedy. The land of
heroic comedy is, as it were, a paradise of lovers, in which it is
not difficult to imagine that men could talk poetry all day long. It
is far more conceivable that men’s speech should flower
naturally into these harmonious forms, when they are filled with the
essential spirit of youth, than when they are sitting gloomily in the
presence of immemorial destiny. The great error consists in supposing
that poetry is an unnatural form of language. We should all like to
speak poetry at the moment when we truly live, and if we do not
speak, it is because we have an impediment in our speech. It is not
song that is the narrow or artificial thing, it is conversation that
is a broken and stammering attempt at song. When we see men in a
spiritual extravaganza, like “Cyrano de Bergerac,”
speaking in rhyme, it is not our language disguised or distorted, but
our language rounded and made whole. Rhymes answer each other as the
sexes in flowers and in humanity answer each other. Men do not speak
so, it is true. Even when they are inspired or in love they talk
inanities. But the poetic comedy does not misrepresent the speech one
half so much as the speech misrepresents the soul. Monsieur Rostand
showed even more than his usual insight when he called “Cyrano
de Bergerac” a comedy, despite the fact that, strictly
speaking, it ends with disappointment and death. The essence of
tragedy is a spiritual breakdown or decline, and in the great French
play the spiritual sentiment mounts unceasingly until the last line.
It is not the facts themselves, but our feeling about them, that
makes tragedy and comedy, and death is more joyful in Rostand than
life in Maeterlinck. The same apparent contradiction holds good in
the case of the drama of “L’Aiglon,” now being
performed with so much success. Although the hero is a weakling, the
subject a fiasco, the end a premature death and a personal
disillusionment, yet, in spite of this theme, which might have been
chosen for its depressing qualities, the unconquerable pæan of
the praise of things, the ungovernable gaiety of the poet’s
song swells so high that at the end it seems to drown all the weak
voices of the characters in one crashing chorus of great things and
great men. A multitude of mottoes might be taken from the play to
indicate and illustrate, not only its own spirit, but much of the
spirit of modern life. When in the vision of the field of Wagram the
horrible voices of the wounded cry out, Les
corbeaux, les corbeaux, the Duke,
overwhelmed with a nightmare of hideous trivialities, cries out, Où,
où, sont les aigles? That
antithesis might stand alone as an invocation at the beginning of the
twentieth century to the spirit of heroic comedy. When an ex-General
of Napoleon is asked his reason for having betrayed the Emperor, he
replies, La fatigue,
and at that a veteran private of the Great Army rushes forward, and
crying passionately, Et nous?
pours out a terrible description of the life lived by the commoner
soldier. To-day, when pessimism is almost as much a symbol of wealth
and fashion as jewels or cigars, when the pampered heirs of the ages
can sum up life in few other words but la
fatigue, there might surely come a cry
from the vast mass of common humanity from the beginning–et
nous? It is this potentiality for
enthusiasm among the mass of men that makes the function of comedy at
once common and sublime. Shakespeare’s “Much Ado About
Nothing” is a great comedy, because behind it is the whole
pressure of that love of love which is the youth of the world, which
is common to all the young, especially to those who swear they will
die bachelors and old maids. “Love’s Labour’s Lost”
is filled with the same energy, and there it falls even more
definitely into the scope of our subject, since it is a comedy in
rhyme in which all men speak lyrically as naturally as the birds sing
in pairing time. What the love of love is to the Shakespearean
comedies, that other and more mysterious human passion, the love of
death, is to “L’Aiglon.” Whether we shall ever have
in England a new tradition of poetic comedy it is difficult at
present to say, but we shall assuredly never have it until we realise
that comedy is built upon everlasting foundations in the nature of
things, that it is not a thing too light to capture, but too deep to
plumb. Monsieur Rostand, in his description of the Battle of Wagram,
does not shrink from bringing about the Duke’s ears the
frightful voices of actual battle, of men torn by crows, and
suffocated with blood, but when the Duke, terrified at these dreadful
appeals, asks them for their final word, they all cry together Vive
l’Empereur! Monsieur Rostand,
perhaps, did not know that he was writing an allegory. To me that
field of Wagram is the field of the modern war of literature. We hear
nothing but the voices of pain; the whole is one phonograph of
horror. It is right that we should hear these things, it is right
that not one of them should be silenced; but these cries of distress
are not in life, as they are in modern art, the only voices; they are
the voices of men, but not the voice of man. When questioned finally
and seriously as to their conception of their destiny, men have from
the beginning of time answered in a thousand philosophies and
religions with a single voice and in a sense most sacred and
tremendous, Vive l’Empereur.
CHARLES II
There are a great many bonds which
still connect us with Charles II., one of the idlest men of one of
the idlest epochs. Among other things Charles II. represented one
thing which is very rare and very satisfying; he was a real and
consistent sceptic. Scepticism, both in its advantages and
disadvantages, is greatly misunderstood in our time. There is a
curious idea abroad that scepticism has some connection with such
theories as materialism and atheism and secularism. This is of course
a mistake; the true sceptic has nothing to do with these theories
simply because they are theories. The true sceptic is as much a
spiritualist as he is a materialist. He thinks that the savage
dancing round an African idol stands quite as good a chance of being
right as Darwin. He thinks that mysticism is every bit as rational as
rationalism. He has indeed the most profound doubts as to whether St.
Matthew wrote his own gospel. But he has quite equally profound
doubts as to whether the tree he is looking at is a tree and not a
rhinoceros.
This is the real meaning of that
mystery which appears so prominently in the lives of great sceptics,
which appears with especial prominence in the life of Charles II. I
mean their constant oscillation between atheism and Roman
Catholicism. Roman Catholicism is indeed a great and fixed and
formidable system, but so is atheism. Atheism is indeed the most
daring of all dogmas, more daring than the vision of a palpable day
of judgment. For it is the assertion of a universal negative; for a
man to say that there is no God in the universe is like saying that
there are no insects in any of the stars.
Thus it was with that wholesome and
systematic sceptic, Charles II. When he took the Sacrament according
to the forms of the Roman Church in his last hour he was acting
consistently as a philosopher. The wafer might not be God; similarly
it might not be a wafer. To the genuine and poetical sceptic the
whole world is incredible, with its bulbous mountains and its
fantastic trees. The whole order of things is as outrageous as any
miracle which could presume to violate it. Transubstantiation might
be a dream, but if it was, it was assuredly a dream within a dream.
Charles II. sought to guard himself against hell fire because he
could not think hell itself more fantastic than the world as it was
revealed by science. The priest crept up the staircase, the doors
were closed, the few of the faithful who were present hushed
themselves respectfully, and so, with every circumstance of secrecy
and sanctity, with the cross uplifted and the prayers poured out, was
consummated the last great act of logical unbelief.
The problem of Charles II. consists
in this, that he has scarcely a moral virtue to his name, and yet he
attracts us morally. We feel that some of the virtues have been
dropped out in the lists made by all the saints and sages, and that
Charles II. was pre-eminently successful in these wild and
unmentionable virtues. The real truth of this matter and the real
relation of Charles II. to the moral ideal is worth somewhat more
exhaustive study.
It is a commonplace that the
Restoration movement can only be understood when considered as a
reaction against Puritanism. But it is insufficiently realised that
the tyranny which half frustrated all the good work of Puritanism was
of a very peculiar kind. It was not the fire of Puritanism, the
exultation in sobriety, the frenzy of a restraint, which passed away;
that still burns in the heart of England, only to be quenched by the
final overwhelming sea. But it is seldom remembered that the Puritans
were in their day emphatically intellectual bullies, that they relied
swaggeringly on the logical necessity of Calvinism, that they bound
omnipotence itself in the chains of syllogism. The Puritans fell,
through the damning fact that they had a complete theory of life,
through the eternal paradox that a satisfactory explanation can never
satisfy. Like Brutus and the logical Romans, like the logical French
Jacobins, like the logical English utilitarians, they taught the
lesson that men’s wants have always been right and their
arguments always wrong. Reason is always a kind of brute force; those
who appeal to the head rather than the heart, however pallid and
polite, are necessarily men of violence. We speak of “touching”
a man’s heart, but we can do nothing to his head but hit it.
The tyranny of the Puritans over the bodies of men was comparatively
a trifle; pikes, bullets, and conflagrations are comparatively a
trifle. Their real tyranny was the tyranny of aggressive reason over
the cowed and demoralised human spirit. Their brooding and raving can
be forgiven, can in truth be loved and reverenced, for it is humanity
on fire; hatred can be genial, madness can be homely. The Puritans
fell, not because they were fanatics, but because they were
rationalists.
When we consider these things, when
we remember that Puritanism, which means in our day a moral and
almost temperamental attitude, meant in that day a singularly
arrogant logical attitude, we shall comprehend a little more the
grain of good that lay in the vulgarity and triviality of the
Restoration. The Restoration, of which Charles II. was a pre-eminent
type, was in part a revolt of all the chaotic and unclassed parts of
human nature, the parts that are left over, and will always be left
over, by every rationalistic system of life. This does not merely
account for the revolt of the vices and of that empty recklessness
and horseplay which is sometimes more irritating than any vice. It
accounts also for the return of the virtue of politeness, for that
also is a nameless thing ignored by logical codes. Politeness has
indeed about it something mystical; like religion, it is everywhere
understood and nowhere defined. Charles is not entirely to be
despised because, as the type of this movement, he let himself float
upon this new tide of politeness. There was some moral and social
value in his perfection in little things. He could not keep the Ten
Commandments, but he kept the ten thousand commandments. His name is
unconnected with any great acts of duty or sacrifice, but it is
connected with a great many of those acts of magnanimous politeness,
of a kind of dramatic delicacy, which lie on the dim borderland
between morality and art. “Charles II.,” said Thackeray,
with unerring brevity, “was a rascal, but not a snob.”
Unlike George IV. he was a gentleman, and a gentleman is a man who
obeys strange statutes, not to be found in any moral text-book, and
practises strange virtues nameless from the beginning of the world.
So much may be said and should be
said for the Restoration, that it was the revolt of something human,
if only the debris of human nature. But more cannot be said. It was
emphatically a fall and not an ascent, a recoil and not an advance, a
sudden weakness and not a sudden strength. That the bow of human
nature was by Puritanism bent immeasurably too far, that it
overstrained the soul by stretching it to the height of an almost
horrible idealism, makes the collapse of the Restoration infinitely
more excusable, but it does not make it any the less a collapse.
Nothing can efface the essential distinction that Puritanism was one
of the world’s great efforts after the discovery of the true
order, whereas it was the essence of the Restoration that it involved
no effort at all. It is true that the Restoration was not, as has
been widely assumed, the most immoral epoch of our history. Its vices
cannot compare for a moment in this respect with the monstrous
tragedies and almost suffocating secrecies and villainies of the
Court of James I. But the dram-drinking and nose-slitting of the
saturnalia of Charles II. seem at once more human and more detestable
than the passions and poisons of the Renaissance, much in the same
way that a monkey appears inevitably more human and more detestable
than a tiger. Compared with the Renaissance, there is something
Cockney about the Restoration. Not only was it too indolent for great
morality, it was too indolent even for great art. It lacked that
seriousness which is needed even for the pursuit of pleasure, that
discipline which is essential even to a game of lawn tennis. It would
have appeared to Charles II.’s poets quite as arduous to write
“Paradise Lost” as to regain Paradise.
All old and vigorous languages abound
in images and metaphors, which, though lightly and casually used, are
in truth poems in themselves, and poems of a high and striking order.
Perhaps no phrase is so terribly significant as the phrase “killing
time.” It is a tremendous and poetical image, the image of a
kind of cosmic parricide. There are on the earth a race of revellers
who do, under all their exuberance, fundamentally regard time as an
enemy. Of these were Charles II. and the men of the Restoration.
Whatever may have been their merits, and as we have said we think
that they had merits, they can never have a place among the great
representatives of the joy of life, for they belonged to those lower
epicureans who kill time, as opposed to those higher epicureans who
make time live.
Of a people in this temper Charles
II. was the natural and rightful head. He may have been a pantomime
King, but he was a King, and with all his geniality he let nobody
forget it. He was not, indeed, the aimless flaneur that he has been
represented. He was a patient and cunning politician, who disguised
his wisdom under so perfect a mask of folly that he not only deceived
his allies and opponents, but has deceived almost all the historians
that have come after him. But if Charles was, as he emphatically was,
the only Stuart who really achieved despotism, it was greatly due to
the temper of the nation and the age. Despotism is the easiest of all
governments, at any rate for the governed.
It is indeed a form of slavery, and
it is the despot who is the slave. Men in a state of decadence employ
professionals to fight for them, professionals to dance for them, and
a professional to rule them.
Almost all the faces in the portraits
of that time look, as it were, like masks put on artificially with
the perruque. A strange unreality broods over the period. Distracted
as we are with civic mysteries and problems we can afford to rejoice.
Our tears are less desolate than their laughter, our restraints are
larger than their liberty.
STEVENSON
A recent incident has finally
convinced us that Stevenson was, as we suspected, a great man. We
knew from recent books that we have noticed, from the scorn of
“Ephemera Critica” and Mr. George Moore, that Stevenson
had the first essential qualification of a great man: that of being
misunderstood by his opponents. But from the book which Messrs.
Chatto & Windus have issued, in the same binding as Stevenson’s
works, “Robert Louis Stevenson,” by Mr. H. Bellyse
Baildon, we learn that he has the other essential qualification, that
of being misunderstood by his admirers. Mr. Baildon has many
interesting things to tell us about Stevenson himself, whom he knew
at college. Nor are his criticisms by any means valueless. That upon
the plays, especially “Beau Austin,” is remarkably
thoughtful and true. But it is a very singular fact, and goes far, as
we say, to prove that Stevenson had that unfathomable quality which
belongs to the great, that this admiring student of Stevenson can
number and marshal all the master’s work and distribute praise
and blame with decision and even severity, without ever thinking for
a moment of the principles of art and ethics which would have struck
us as the very things that Stevenson nearly killed himself to
express.
Mr. Baildon, for example, is
perpetually lecturing Stevenson for his “pessimism”;
surely a strange charge against a man who has done more than any
modern artist to make men ashamed of their shame of life. But he
complains that, in “The Master of Ballantrae” and “Dr.
Jekyll and Mr. Hyde,” Stevenson gives evil a final victory over
good. Now if there was one point that Stevenson more constantly and
passionately emphasised than any other it was that we must worship
good for its own value and beauty, without any reference whatever to
victory or failure in space and time. “Whatever we are intended
to do,” he said, “we are not intended to succeed.”
That the stars in their courses fight against virtue, that humanity
is in its nature a forlorn hope, this was the very spirit that
through the whole of Stevenson’s work sounded a trumpet to all
the brave. The story of Henry Durie is dark enough, but could anyone
stand beside the grave of that sodden monomaniac and not respect him?
It is strange that men should see sublime inspiration in the ruins of
an old church and see none in the ruins of a man.
The author has most extraordinary
ideas about Stevenson’s tales of blood and spoil; he appears to
think that they prove Stevenson to have had (we use Mr. Baildon’s
own phrase) a kind of “homicidal mania.” “He
[Stevenson] arrives pretty much at the paradox that one can hardly be
better employed than in taking life.” Mr. Baildon might as well
say that Dr. Conan Doyle delights in committing inexplicable crimes,
that Mr. Clark Russell is a notorious pirate, and that Mr. Wilkie
Collins thought that one could hardly be better employed than in
stealing moonstones and falsifying marriage registers. But Mr.
Baildon is scarcely alone in this error: few people have understood
properly the goriness of Stevenson. Stevenson was essentially the
robust schoolboy who draws skeletons and gibbets in his Latin
grammar. It was not that he took pleasure in death, but that he took
pleasure in life, in every muscular and emphatic action of life, even
if it were an action that took the life of another.
Let us suppose that one gentleman
throws a knife at another gentleman and pins him to the wall. It is
scarcely necessary to remark that there are in this transaction two
somewhat varying personal points of view. The point of view of the
man pinned is the tragic and moral point of view, and this Stevenson
showed clearly that he understood in such stories as “The
Master of Ballantrae” and “Weir of Hermiston.” But
there is another view of the matter–that in which the whole act
is an abrupt and brilliant explosion of bodily vitality, like
breaking a rock with a blow of a hammer, or just clearing a
five-barred gate. This is the standpoint of romance, and it is the
soul of “Treasure Island” and “The Wrecker.”
It was not, indeed, that Stevenson loved men less, but that he loved
clubs and pistols more. He had, in truth, in the devouring
universalism of his soul, a positive love for inanimate objects such
as has not been known since St. Francis called the sun brother and
the well sister. We feel that he was actually in love with the wooden
crutch that Silver sent hurtling in the sunlight, with the box that
Billy Bones left at the “Admiral Benbow,” with the knife
that Wicks drove through his own hand and the table. There is always
in his work a certain clean-cut angularity which makes us remember
that he was fond of cutting wood with an axe.
Stevenson’s new biographer,
however, cannot make any allowance for this deep-rooted poetry of
mere sight and touch. He is always imputing something to Stevenson as
a crime which Stevenson really professed as an object. He says of
that glorious riot of horror, “The Destroying Angel,” in
“The Dynamiter,” that it is “highly fantastic and
putting a strain on our credulity.” This is rather like
describing the travels of Baron Munchausen as “unconvincing.”
The whole story of “The Dynamiter” is a kind of humorous
nightmare, and even in that story “The Destroying Angel”
is supposed to be an extravagant lie made up on the spur of the
moment. It is a dream within a dream, and to accuse it of
improbability is like accusing the sky of being blue. But Mr.
Baildon, whether from hasty reading or natural difference of taste,
cannot in the least comprehend that rich and romantic irony of
Stevenson’s London stories. He actually says of that portentous
monument of humour, Prince Florizel of Bohemia, that, “though
evidently admired by his creator, he is to me on the whole rather an
irritating presence.” From this we are almost driven to believe
(though desperately and against our will) that Mr. Baildon thinks
that Prince Florizel is to be taken seriously, as if he were a man in
real life. For ourselves. Prince Florizel is almost our favourite
character in fiction; but we willingly add the proviso that if we met
him in real life we should kill him.
The fact is, that the whole mass of
Stevenson’s spiritual and intellectual virtues have been partly
frustrated by one additional virtue–that of artistic dexterity.
If he had chalked up his great message on a wall, like Walt Whitman,
in large and straggling letters, it would have startled men like a
blasphemy. But he wrote his light-headed paradoxes in so flowing a
copy-book hand that everyone supposed they must be copy-book
sentiments. He suffered from his versatility, not, as is loosely
said, by not doing every department well enough, but by doing every
department too well. As child, cockney, pirate, or Puritan, his
disguises were so good that most people could not see the same man
under all. It is an unjust fact that if a man can play the fiddle,
give legal opinions, and black boots just tolerably, he is called an
Admirable Crichton, but if he does all three thoroughly well, he is
apt to be regarded, in the several departments, as a common fiddler,
a common lawyer, and a common boot-black. This is what has happened
in the case of Stevenson. If “Dr. Jekyll,” “The
Master of Ballantrae,” “The Child’s Garden of
Verses,” and “Across the Plains” had been each of
them one shade less perfectly done than they were, everyone would
have seen that they were all parts of the same message; but by
succeeding in the proverbial miracle of being in five places at once,
he has naturally convinced others that he was five different people.
But the real message of Stevenson was as simple as that of Mohamet,
as moral as that of Dante, as confident as that of Whitman, and as
practical as that of James Watt. The conception which unites the
whole varied work of Stevenson was that romance, or the vision of the
possibilities of things, was far more important than mere
occurrences: that one was the soul of our life, the other the body,
and that the soul was the precious thing. The germ of all his stories
lies in the idea that every landscape or scrap of scenery has a soul:
and that soul is a story. Standing before a stunted orchard with a
broken stone wall, we may know as a mere fact that no one has been
through it but an elderly female cook. But everything exists in the
human soul: that orchard grows in our own brain, and there it is the
shrine and theatre of some strange chance between a girl and a ragged
poet and a mad farmer. Stevenson stands for the conception that ideas
are the real incidents: that our fancies are our adventures. To think
of a cow with wings is essentially to have met one. And this is the
reason for his wide diversities of narrative: he had to make one
story as rich as a ruby sunset, another as grey as a hoary monolith:
for the story was the soul, or rather the meaning, of the bodily
vision. It is quite inappropriate to judge “The Teller of
Tales” (as the Samoans called him) by the particular novels he
wrote, as one would judge Mr. George Moore by “Esther Waters.”
These novels were only the two or three of his soul’s
adventures that he happened to tell. But he died with a thousand
stories in his heart.
[This
Chapter: “Robert Louis Stevenson: A Life Study in Criticism.”
By H. Bellyse Baildon. Chatto & Windus.]
THOMAS CARLYLE
There are two main moral necessities
for the work of a great man: the first is that he should believe in
the truth of his message; the second is that he should believe in the
acceptability of his message. It was the whole tragedy of Carlyle
that he had the first and not the second.
The ordinary capital, however, which
is made out of Carlyle’s alleged gloom is a very paltry matter.
Carlyle had his faults, both as a man and as a writer, but the
attempt to explain his gospel in terms of his “liver” is
merely pitiful. If indigestion invariably resulted in a “Sartor
Resartus,” it would be a vastly more tolerable thing than it
is. Diseases do not turn into poems; even the decadent really writes
with the healthy part of his organism. If Carlyle’s private
faults and literary virtues ran somewhat in the same line, he is only
in the situation of every man; for every one of us it is surely very
difficult to say precisely where our honest opinions end and our
personal predilections begin. But to attempt to denounce Carlyle as a
mere savage egotist cannot arise from anything but a pure inability
to grasp Carlyle’s gospel. “Ruskin,” says a critic,
“did, all the same, verily believe in God; Carlyle believed
only in himself.” This is certainly a distinction between the
author he has understood and the author he has not understood.
Carlyle believed in himself, but he could not have believed in
himself more than Ruskin did; they both believed in God, because they
felt that if everything else fell into wrack and ruin, themselves
were permanent witnesses to God. Where they both failed was not in
belief in God or in belief in themselves; they failed in belief in
other people. It is not enough for a prophet to believe in his
message; he must believe in its acceptability. Christ, St. Francis,
Bunyan, Wesley, Mr. Gladstone, Walt Whitman, men of indescribable
variety, were all alike in a certain faculty of treating the average
man as their equal, of trusting to his reason and good feeling
without fear and without condescension. It was this simplicity of
confidence, not only in God, but in the image of God, that was
lacking in Carlyle.
But the attempts to discredit
Carlyle’s religious sentiment must absolutely fall to the
ground. The profound security of Carlyle’s sense of the unity
of the Cosmos is like that of a Hebrew prophet; and it has the same
expression that it had in the Hebrew prophets–humour. A man
must be very full of faith to jest about his divinity. No Neo-Pagan
delicately suggesting a revival of Dionysus, no vague, half-converted
Theosophist groping towards a recognition of Buddha, would ever think
of cracking jokes on the matter. But to the Hebrew prophets their
religion was so solid a thing, like a mountain or a mammoth, that the
irony of its contact with trivial and fleeting matters struck them
like a blow. So it was with Carlyle. His supreme contribution, both
to philosophy and literature, was his sense of the sarcasm of
eternity. Other writers had seen the hope or the terror of the
heavens, he alone saw the humour of them. Other writers had seen that
there could be something elemental and eternal in a song or statute,
he alone saw that there could be something elemental and eternal in a
joke. No one who ever read it will forget the passage, full of dark
and agnostic gratification, in which he narrates that some Court
chronicler described Louis XV. as “falling asleep in the Lord.”
“Enough for us that he did fall asleep; that, curtained in
thick night, under what keeping we ask not, he at least will never,
through unending ages, insult the face of the sun any more . . . and
we go on, if not to better forms of beastliness, at least to fresher
ones.”
The supreme value of Carlyle to
English literature was that he was the founder of modern
irrationalism; a movement fully as important as modern rationalism. A
great deal is said in these days about the value or valuelessness of
logic. In the main, indeed, logic is not a productive tool so much as
a weapon of defence. A man building up an intellectual system has to
build like Nehemiah, with the sword in one hand and the trowel in the
other. The imagination, the constructive quality, is the trowel, and
argument is the sword. A wide experience of actual intellectual
affairs will lead most people to the conclusion that logic is mainly
valuable as a weapon wherewith to exterminate logicians.
But though this may be true enough in
practice, it scarcely clears up the position of logic in human
affairs. Logic is a machine of the mind, and if it is used honestly
it ought to bring out an honest conclusion. When people say that you
can prove anything by logic, they are not using words in a fair
sense. What they mean is that you can prove anything by bad logic.
Deep in the mystic ingratitude of the soul of man there is an
extraordinary tendency to use the name for an organ, when what is
meant is the abuse or decay of that organ. Thus we speak of a man
suffering from “nerves,” which is about as sensible as
talking about a man suffering from ten fingers. We speak of “liver”
and “digestion” when we mean the failure of liver and the
absence of digestion. And in the same manner we speak of the dangers
of logic, when what we really mean is the danger of fallacy.
But the real point about the
limitation of logic and the partial overthrow of logic by writers
like Carlyle is deeper and somewhat different. The fault of the great
mass of logicians is not that they bring out a false result, or, in
other words, are not logicians at all. Their fault is that by an
inevitable psychological habit they tend to forget that there are two
parts of a logical process, the first the choosing of an assumption,
and the second the arguing upon it, and humanity, if it devotes
itself too persistently to the study of sound reasoning, has a
certain tendency to lose the faculty of sound assumption. It is
astonishing how constantly one may hear from rational and even
rationalistic persons such a phrase as “He did not prove the
very thing with which he started,” or, “The whole of his
case rested upon a pure assumption,” two peculiarities which
may be found by the curious in the works of Euclid. It is
astonishing, again, how constantly one hears rationalists arguing
upon some deep topic, apparently without troubling about the deep
assumptions involved, having lost their sense, as it were, of the
real colour and character of a man’s assumption. For instance,
two men will argue about whether patriotism is a good thing and never
discover until the end, if at all, that the cosmopolitan is basing
his whole case upon the idea that man should, if he can, become as
God, with equal sympathies and no prejudices, while the nationalist
denies any such duty at the very start, and regards man as an animal
who has preferences, as a bird has feathers.
Thus it was with Carlyle: he startled
men by attacking not arguments, but assumptions. He simply brushed
aside all the matters which the men of the nineteenth century held to
be incontrovertible, and appealed directly to the very different
class of matters which they knew to be true. He induced men to study
less the truth of their reasoning, and more the truth of the
assumptions upon which they reasoned. Even where his view was not the
highest truth, it was always a refreshing and beneficent heresy. He
denied every one of the postulates upon which the age of reason based
itself. He denied the theory of progress which assumed that we must
be better off than the people of the twelfth century. Whether we were
better than the people of the twelfth century, according to him,
depended entirely upon whether we chose or deserved to be.
He denied every type and species of
prop or association or support which threw the responsibility upon
civilisation or society, or anything but the individual conscience.
He has often been called a prophet. The real ground of the truth of
this phrase is often neglected. Since the last era of purely
religious literature, the era of English Puritanism, there has been
no writer in whose eyes the soul stood so much alone.
Carlyle was, as we have suggested, a
mystic, and mysticism was with him, as with all its genuine
professors, only a transcendent form of common sense. Mysticism and
common sense alike consist in a sense of the dominance of certain
truths and tendencies which cannot be formally demonstrated or even
formally named. Mysticism and common sense are alike appeals to
realities that we all know to be real, but which have no place in
argument except as postulates. Carlyle’s work did consist in
breaking through formulæ, old and new, to these old and silent
and ironical sanities. Philosophers might abolish kings a hundred
times over, he maintained, they could not alter the fact that every
man and woman does choose a king and repudiate all the pride of
citizenship for the exultation of humility. If inequality of this
kind was a weakness, it was a weakness bound up with the very
strength of the universe. About hero worship, indeed, few critics
have done the smallest justice to Carlyle. Misled by those hasty and
choleric passages in which he sometimes expressed a preference for
mere violence, passages which were a great deal more connected with
his temperament than with his philosophy, they have finally imbibed
the notion that Carlyle’s theory of hero worship was a theory
of terrified submission to stern and arrogant men. As a matter of
fact, Carlyle is really inhumane about some questions, but he is
never inhumane about hero worship. His view is not that human nature
is so vulgar and silly a thing that it must be guided and driven; it
is, on the contrary, that human nature is so chivalrous and
fundamentally magnanimous a thing that even the meanest have it in
them to love a leader more than themselves, and to prefer loyalty to
rebellion. When he speaks of this trait in human nature Carlyle’s
tone invariably softens. We feel that for the moment he is kindled
with admiration of mankind, and almost reaches the verge of
Christianity. Whatever else was acid and captious about Carlyle’s
utterances, his hero worship was not only humane, it was almost
optimistic. He admired great men primarily, and perhaps correctly,
because he thought that they were more human than other men. The evil
side of the influence of Carlyle and his religion of hero worship did
not consist in the emotional worship of valour and success; that was
a part of him, as, indeed, it is a part of all healthy children.
Where Carlyle really did harm was in the fact that he, more than any
modern man, is responsible for the increase of that modern habit of
what is vulgarly called “Going the whole hog.” Often in
matters of passion and conquest it is a singularly hoggish hog. This
remarkable modern craze for making one’s philosophy, religion,
politics, and temper all of a piece, of seeking in all incidents for
opportunities to assert and reassert some favourite mental attitude,
is a thing which existed comparatively little in other centuries.
Solomon and Horace, Petrarch and Shakespeare were pessimists when
they were melancholy, and optimists when they were happy. But the
optimist of to-day seems obliged to prove that gout and unrequited
love make him dance with joy, and the pessimist of to-day to prove
that sunshine and a good supper convulse him with inconsolable
anguish. Carlyle was strongly possessed with this mania for spiritual
consistency. He wished to take the same view of the wars of the
angels and of the paltriest riot at Donnybrook Fair. It was this
species of insane logic which led him into his chief errors, never
his natural enthusiasms. Let us take an example. Carlyle’s
defence of slavery is a thoroughly ridiculous thing, weak alike in
argument and in moral instinct. The truth is, that he only took it up
from the passion for applying everywhere his paradoxical defence of
aristocracy. He blundered, of course, because he did not see that
slavery has nothing in the world to do with aristocracy, that it is,
indeed, almost its opposite. The defence which Carlyle and all its
thoughtful defenders have made for aristocracy was that a few persons
could more rapidly and firmly decide public affairs in the interests
of the people. But slavery is not even supposed to be a government
for the good of the governed. It is a possession of the governed
avowedly for the good of the governors. Aristocracy uses the strong
for the service of the weak; slavery uses the weak for the service of
the strong. It is no derogation to man as a spiritual being, as
Carlyle firmly believed he was, that he should be ruled and guided
for his own good like a child–for a child who is always ruled
and guided we regard as the very type of spiritual existence. But it
is a derogation and an absolute contradiction to that human
spirituality in which Carlyle believed that a man should be owned
like a tool for someone else’s good, as if he had no personal
destiny in the Cosmos. We draw attention to this particular error of
Carlyle’s because we think that it is a curious example of the
waste and unclean places into which that remarkable animal, “the
whole hog,” more than once led him.
In this respect Carlyle has had
unquestionably long and an unquestionably bad influence. The whole of
that recent political ethic which conceives that if we only go far
enough we may finish a thing for once and all, that being strong
consists chiefly in being deliberately deaf and blind, owes a great
deal of its complete sway to his example. Out of him flows most of
the philosophy of Nietzsche, who is in modern times the supreme
maniac of this moonstruck consistency. Though Nietzsche and Carlyle
were in reality profoundly different, Carlyle being a stiff-necked
peasant and Nietzsche a very fragile aristocrat, they were alike in
this one quality of which we speak, the strange and pitiful audacity
with which they applied their single ethical test to everything in
heaven and earth. The disciple of Nietzsche, indeed, embraces
immorality like an austere and difficult faith. He urges himself to
lust and cruelty with the same tremulous enthusiasm with which a
Christian urges himself to purity and patience; he struggles as a
monk struggles with bestial visions and temptations with the ancient
necessities of honour and justice and compassion. To this madhouse,
it can hardly be denied, has Carlyle’s intellectual courage
brought many at last.
TOLSTOY AND THE CULT OF SIMPLICITY
The whole world is certainly heading
for a great simplicity, not deliberately, but rather inevitably. It
is not a mere fashion of false innocence, like that of the French
aristocrats before the Revolution, who built an altar to Pan, and who
taxed the peasantry for the enormous expenditure which is needed in
order to live the simple life of peasants. The simplicity towards
which the world is driving is the necessary outcome of all our
systems and speculations and of our deep and continuous contemplation
of things. For the universe is like everything in it; we have to look
at it repeatedly and habitually before we see it. It is only when we
have seen it for the hundredth time that we see it for the first
time. The more consistently things are contemplated, the more they
tend to unify themselves and therefore to simplify themselves. The
simplification of anything is always sensational. Thus monotheism is
the most sensational of things: it is as if we gazed long at a design
full of disconnected objects, and, suddenly, with a stunning thrill,
they came together into a huge and staring face.
Few people will dispute that all the
typical movements of our time are upon this road towards
simplification. Each system seeks to be more fundamental than the
other; each seeks, in the literal sense, to undermine the other. In
art, for example, the old conception of man, classic as the Apollo
Belvedere, has first been attacked by the realist, who asserts that
man, as a fact of natural history, is a creature with colourless hair
and a freckled face. Then comes the Impressionist, going yet deeper,
who asserts that to his physical eye, which alone is certain, man is
a creature with purple hair and a grey face. Then comes the
Symbolist, and says that to his soul, which alone is certain, man is
a creature with green hair and a blue face. And all the great writers
of our time represent in one form or another this attempt to
reestablish communication with the elemental, or, as it is sometimes
more roughly and fallaciously expressed, to return to nature. Some
think that the return to nature consists in drinking no wine; some
think that it consists in drinking a great deal more than is good for
them. Some think that the return to nature is achieved by beating
swords into ploughshares; some think it is achieved by turning
ploughshares into very ineffectual British War Office bayonets. It is
natural, according to the Jingo, for a man to kill other people with
gunpowder and himself with gin. It is natural, according to the
humanitarian revolutionist, to kill other people with dynamite and
himself with vegetarianism. It would be too obviously Philistine a
sentiment, perhaps, to suggest that the claim of either of these
persons to be obeying the voice of nature is interesting when we
consider that they require huge volumes of paradoxical argument to
persuade themselves or anyone else of the truth of their conclusions.
But the giants of our time are undoubtedly alike in that they
approach by very different roads this conception of the return to
simplicity. Ibsen returns to nature by the angular exterior of fact,
Maeterlinck by the eternal tendencies of fable. Whitman returns to
nature by seeing how much he can accept, Tolstoy by seeing how much
he can reject.
Now, this heroic desire to return to
nature, is, of course, in some respects, rather like the heroic
desire of a kitten to return to its own tail. A tail is a simple and
beautiful object, rhythmic in curve and soothing in texture; but it
is certainly one of the minor but characteristic qualities of a tail
that it should hang behind. It is impossible to deny that it would in
some degree lose its character if attached to any other part of the
anatomy. Now, nature is like a tail in the sense that it vitally
important, if it is to discharge its real duty, that it should be
always behind. To imagine that we can see nature, especially our own
nature, face to face, is a folly; it is even a blasphemy. It is like
the conduct of a cat in some mad fairy-tale, who should set out on
his travels with the firm conviction that he would find his tail
growing like a tree in the meadows at the end of the world. And the
actual effect of the travels of the philosopher in search of nature,
when seen from the outside, looks very like the gyrations of the
tail-pursuing kitten, exhibiting much enthusiasm but little dignity,
much cry and very little tail. The grandeur of nature is that she is
omnipotent and unseen, that she is perhaps ruling us most when we
think that she is heeding us least. “Thou art a God that hidest
Thyself,” said the Hebrew poet. It may be said with all
reverence that it is behind a man’s back that the spirit of
nature hides.
It is this consideration that lends a
certain air of futility even to all the inspired simplicities and
thunderous veracities of Tolstoy. We feel that a man cannot make
himself simple merely by warring on complexity; we feel, indeed, in
our saner moments, that a man cannot make himself simple at all. A
self-conscious simplicity may well be far more intrinsically ornate
than luxury itself. Indeed, a great deal of the pomp and
sumptuousness of the world’s history was simple in the truest
sense. It was born of an almost babyish receptiveness; it was the
work of men who had eyes to wonder and men who had ears to hear.
“King
Solomon brought merchant men Because of his desire With
peacocks, apes, and ivory, From Tarshish unto Tyre.”
But this proceeding was not a part of
the wisdom of Solomon; it was a part of his folly–I had almost
said of his innocence. Tolstoy, we feel, would not be content with
hurling satire and denunciation at “Solomon in all his glory.”
With fierce and unimpeachable logic he would go a step further. He
would spend days and nights in the meadows stripping the shameless
crimson coronals off the lilies of the field.
The new collection of “Tales
from Tolstoy,” translated and edited by Mr. R. Nisbet Bain, is
calculated to draw particular attention to this ethical and ascetic
side of Tolstoy’s work. In one sense, and that the deepest
sense, the work of Tolstoy is, of course, a genuine and noble appeal
to simplicity. The narrow notion that an artist may not teach is
pretty well exploded by now. But the truth of the matter is, that an
artist teaches far more by his mere background and properties, his
landscape, his costume, his idiom and technique–all the part of
his work, in short, of which he is probably entirely unconscious,
than by the elaborate and pompous moral dicta which he fondly
imagines to be his opinions. The real distinction between the ethics
of high art and the ethics of manufactured and didactic art lies in
the simple fact that the bad fable has a moral, while the good fable
is a moral. And the real moral of Tolstoy comes out constantly in
these stories, the great moral which lies at the heart of all his
work, of which he is probably unconscious, and of which it is quite
likely that he would vehemently disapprove. The curious cold white
light of morning that shines over all the tales, the folklore
simplicity with which “a man or a woman” are spoken of
without further identification, the love–one might almost say
the lust–for the qualities of brute materials, the hardness of
wood, and the softness of mud, the ingrained belief in a certain
ancient kindliness sitting beside the very cradle of the race of
man–these influences are truly moral. When we put beside them
the trumpeting and tearing nonsense of the didactic Tolstoy,
screaming for an obscene purity, shouting for an inhuman peace,
hacking up human life into small sins with a chopper, sneering at
men, women, and children out of respect to humanity, combining in one
chaos of contradictions an unmanly Puritan and an uncivilised prig,
then, indeed, we scarcely know whither Tolstoy has vanished. We know
not what to do with this small and noisy moralist who is inhabiting
one corner of a great and good man.
It is difficult in every case to
reconcile Tolstoy the great artist with Tolstoy the almost venomous
reformer. It is difficult to believe that a man who draws in such
noble outlines the dignity of the daily life of humanity regards as
evil that divine act of procreation by which that dignity is renewed
from age to age. It is difficult to believe that a man who has
painted with so frightful an honesty the heartrending emptiness of
the life of the poor can really grudge them every one of their
pitiful pleasures, from courtship to tobacco. It is difficult to
believe that a poet in prose who has so powerfully exhibited the
earth-born air of man, the essential kinship of a human being, with
the landscape in which he lives, can deny so elemental a virtue as
that which attaches a man to his own ancestors and his own land. It
is difficult to believe that the man who feels so poignantly the
detestable insolence of oppression would not actually, if he had the
chance, lay the oppressor flat with his fist. All, however, arises
from the search after a false simplicity, the aim of being, if I may
so express it, more natural than it is natural to be. It would not
only be more human, it would be more humble of us to be content to be
complex. The truest kinship with humanity would lie in doing as
humanity has always done, accepting with a sportsmanlike relish the
estate to which we are called, the star of our happiness, and the
fortunes of the land of our birth.
The work of Tolstoy has another and
more special significance. It represents the re-assertion of a
certain awful common sense which characterised the most extreme
utterances of Christ. It is true that we cannot turn the cheek to the
smiter; it is true that we cannot give our cloak to the robber;
civilisation is too complicated, too vain-glorious, too emotional.
The robber would brag, and we should blush; in other words, the
robber and we are alike sentimentalists. The command of Christ is
impossible, but it is not insane; it is rather sanity preached to a
planet of lunatics. If the whole world was suddenly stricken with a
sense of humour it would find itself mechanically fulfilling the
Sermon on the Mount. It is not the plain facts of the world which
stand in the way of that consummation, but its passions of vanity and
self-advertisement and morbid sensibility. It is true that we cannot
turn the cheek to the smiter, and the sole and sufficient reason is
that we have not the pluck. Tolstoy and his followers have shown that
they have the pluck, and even if we think they are mistaken, by this
sign they conquer. Their theory has the strength of an utterly
consistent thing. It represents that doctrine of mildness and
non-resistance which is the last and most audacious of all the forms
of resistance to every existing authority. It is the great strike of
the Quakers which is more formidable than many sanguinary
revolutions. If human beings could only succeed in achieving a real
passive resistance they would be strong with the appalling strength
of inanimate things, they would be calm with the maddening calm of
oak or iron, which conquer without vengeance and are conquered
without humiliation. The theory of Christian duty enunciated by them
is that we should never conquer by force, but always, if we can,
conquer by persuasion. In their mythology St. George did not conquer
the dragon: he tied a pink ribbon round its neck and gave it a saucer
of milk. According to them, a course of consistent kindness to Nero
would have turned him into something only faintly represented by
Alfred the Great. In fact, the policy recommended by this school for
dealing with the bovine stupidity and bovine fury of this world is
accurately summed up in the celebrated verse of Mr. Edward Lear:
“There
was an old man who said, ‘How Shall I flee from this
terrible cow? I will sit on a stile and continue to smile Till
I soften the heart of this cow.’”
Their confidence in human nature is
really honourable and magnificent; it takes the form of refusing to
believe the overwhelming majority of mankind, even when they set out
to explain their own motives. But although most of us would in all
probability tend at first sight to consider this new sect of
Christians as little less outrageous than some brawling and absurd
sect in the Reformation, yet we should fall into a singular error in
doing so. The Christianity of Tolstoy is, when we come to consider
it, one of the most thrilling and dramatic incidents in our modern
civilisation. It represents a tribute to the Christian religion more
sensational than the breaking of seals or the falling of stars.
From the point of view of a
rationalist, the whole world is rendered almost irrational by the
single phenomenon of Christian Socialism. It turns the scientific
universe topsy-turvy, and makes it essentially possible that the key
of all social evolution may be found in the dusty casket of some
discredited creed. It cannot be amiss to consider this phenomenon as
it realty is.
The religion of Christ has, like many
true things, been disproved an extraordinary number of times. It was
disproved by the Neo-Platonist philosophers at the very moment when
it was first starting forth upon its startling and universal career.
It was disproved again by many of the sceptics of the Renaissance
only a few years before its second and supremely striking embodiment,
the religion of Puritanism, was about to triumph over many kings and
civilise many continents. We all agree that these schools of negation
were only interludes in its history; but we all believe naturally and
inevitably that the negation of our own day is really a breaking up
of the theological cosmos, an Armageddon, a Ragnorak, a twilight of
the gods. The man of the nineteenth century, like a schoolboy of
sixteen, believes that his doubt and depression are symbols of the
end of the world. In our day the great irreligionists who did nothing
but dethrone God and drive angels before them have been outstripped,
distanced, and made to look orthodox and humdrum. A newer race of
sceptics has found something infinitely more exciting to do than
nailing down the lids upon a million coffins, and the body upon a
single cross. They have disputed not only the elementary creeds, but
the elementary laws of mankind, property, patriotism, civil
obedience. They have arraigned civilisation as openly as the
materialists have arraigned theology; they have damned all the
philosophers even lower than they have damned the saints. Thousands
of modern men move quietly and conventionally among their fellows
while holding views of national limitation or landed property that
would have made Voltaire shudder like a nun listening to blasphemies.
And the last and wildest phase of this saturnalia of scepticism, the
school that goes furthest among thousands who go so far, the school
that denies the moral validity of those ideals of courage or
obedience which are recognised even among pirates, this school bases
itself upon the literal words of Christ, like Dr. Watts or Messrs.
Moody and Sankey. Never in the whole history of the world was such a
tremendous tribute paid to the vitality of an ancient creed. Compared
with this, it would be a small thing if the Red Sea were cloven
asunder, or the sun did stand still at midday. We are faced with the
phenomenon that a set of revolutionists whose contempt for all the
ideals of family and nation would evoke horror in a thieves’
kitchen, who can rid themselves of those elementary instincts of the
man and the gentleman which cling to the very bones of our
civilisation, cannot rid themselves of the influence of two or three
remote Oriental anecdotes written in corrupt Greek. The fact, when
realised, has about it something stunning and hypnotic. The most
convinced rationalist is in its presence suddenly stricken with a
strange and ancient vision, sees the immense sceptical cosmogonies of
this age as dreams going the way of a thousand forgotten heresies,
and believes for a moment that the dark sayings handed down through
eighteen centuries may, indeed, contain in themselves the revolutions
of which we have only begun to dream.
This value which we have above
suggested unquestionably belongs to the Tolstoians, who may roughly
be described as the new Quakers. With their strange optimism, and
their almost appalling logical courage, they offer a tribute to
Christianity which no orthodoxies could offer. It cannot but be
remarkable to watch a revolution in which both the rulers and the
rebels march under the same symbol. But the actual theory of
non-resistance itself, with all its kindred theories, is not, I
think, characterised by that intellectual obviousness and necessity
which its supporters claim for it. A pamphlet before us shows us an
extraordinary number of statements about the new Testament, of which
the accuracy is by no means so striking as the confidence. To begin
with, we must protest against a habit of quoting and paraphrasing at
the same time. When a man is discussing what Jesus meant, let him
state first of all what He said, not what the man thinks He would
have said if he had expressed Himself more clearly. Here is an
instance of question and answer:
Q. “How did our Master Himself
sum up the law in a few words?”
A. “Be ye merciful, be ye
perfect even as your Father; your Father in the spirit world is
merciful, is perfect.”
There is nothing in this, perhaps,
which Christ might not have said except the abominable metaphysical
modernism of “the spirit world”; but to say that it is
recorded that He did say it, is like saying it is recorded that He
preferred palm trees to sycamores. It is a simple and unadulterated
untruth. The author should know that these words have meant a
thousand things to a thousand people, and that if more ancient sects
had paraphrased them as cheerfully as he, he would never have had the
text upon which he founds his theory. In a pamphlet in which plain
printed words cannot be left alone, it is not surprising if there are
mis-statements upon larger matters. Here is a statement clearly and
philosophically laid down which we can only content ourselves with
flatly denying: “The fifth rule of our Lord is that we should
take special pains to cultivate the same kind of regard for people of
foreign countries, and for those generally who do not belong to us,
or even have an antipathy to us, which we already entertain towards
our own people, and those who are in sympathy with us.” I
should very much like to know where in the whole of the New Testament
the author finds this violent, unnatural, and immoral proposition.
Christ did not have the same kind of regard for one person as for
another. We are specifically told that there were certain persons
whom He specially loved. It is most improbable that He thought of
other nations as He thought of His own. The sight of His national
city moved Him to tears, and the highest compliment He paid was,
“Behold an Israelite indeed.” The author has simply
confused two entirely distinct things. Christ commanded us to have
love for all men, but even if we had equal love for all men, to speak
of having the same love for all men is merely bewildering nonsense.
If we love a man at all, the impression he produces on us must be
vitally different to the impression produced by another man whom we
love. To speak of having the same kind of regard for both is about as
sensible as asking a man whether he prefers chrysanthemums or
billiards. Christ did not love humanity; He never said He loved
humanity; He loved men. Neither He nor anyone else can love humanity;
it is like loving a gigantic centipede. And the reason that the
Tolstoians can even endure to think of an equally distributed
affection is that their love of humanity is a logical love, a love
into which they are coerced by their own theories, a love which would
be an insult to a tom-cat.
But the greatest error of all lies in
the mere act of cutting up the teaching of the New Testament into
five rules. It precisely and ingeniously misses the most dominant
characteristic of the teaching–its absolute spontaneity. The
abyss between Christ and all His modern interpreters is that we have
no record that He ever wrote a word, except with His finger in the
sand. The whole is the history of one continuous and sublime
conversation. Thousands of rules have been deduced from it before
these Tolstoian rules were made, and thousands will be deduced
afterwards. It was not for any pompous proclamation, it was not for
any elaborate output of printed volumes; it was for a few splendid
and idle words that the cross was set up on Calvary, and the earth
gaped, and the sun was darkened at noonday.
SAVONAROLA
Savonarola is a man whom we shall
probably never understand until we know what horror may lie at the
heart of civilisation. This we shall not know until we are civilised.
It may be hoped, in one sense, that we may never understand
Savonarola.
The great deliverers of men have, for
the most part, saved them from calamities which we all recognise as
evil, from calamities which are the ancient enemies of humanity. The
great law-givers saved us from anarchy: the great physicians saved us
from pestilence: the great reformers saved us from starvation. But
there is a huge and bottomless evil compared with which all these are
fleabites, the most desolating curse that can fall upon men or
nations, and it has no name except we call it satisfaction.
Savonarola did not save men from anarchy, but from order; not from
pestilence, but from paralysis; not from starvation, but from luxury.
Men like Savonarola are the witnesses to the tremendous psychological
fact at the back of all our brains, but for which no name has ever
been found, that ease is the worst enemy of happiness, and
civilisation potentially the end of man.
For I fancy that Savonarola’s
thrilling challenge to the luxury of his day went far deeper than the
mere question of sin. The modern rationalistic admirers of
Savonarola, from George Eliot downwards, dwell, truly enough, upon
the sound ethical justification of Savonarola’s anger, upon the
hideous and extravagant character of the crimes which polluted the
palaces of the Renaissance. But they need not be so anxious to show
that Savonarola was no ascetic, that he merely picked out the black
specks of wickedness with the priggish enlightenment of a member of
an Ethical Society. Probably he did hate the civilisation of his
time, and not merely its sins; and that is precisely where he was
infinitely more profound than a modern moralist. He saw, that the
actual crimes were not the only evils: that stolen jewels and
poisoned wine and obscene pictures were merely the symptoms; that the
disease was the complete dependence upon jewels and wine and
pictures. This is a thing constantly forgotten in judging of ascetics
and Puritans in old times. A denunciation of harmless sports did not
always mean an ignorant hatred of what no one but a narrow moralist
would call harmful. Sometimes it meant an exceedingly enlightened
hatred of what no one but a narrow moralist would call harmless.
Ascetics are sometimes more advanced than the average man, as well as
less.
Such, at least, was the hatred in the
heart of Savonarola. He was making war against no trivial human sins,
but against godless and thankless quiescence, against getting used to
happiness, the mystic sin by which all creation fell. He was
preaching that severity which is the sign-manual of youth and hope.
He was preaching that alertness, that clean agility and vigilance,
which is as necessary to gain pleasure as to gain holiness, as
indispensable in a lover as in a monk. A critic has truly pointed out
that Savonarola could not have been fundamentally anti-æsthetic,
since he had such friends as Michael Angelo, Botticelli, and Luca
della Robbia. The fact is that this purification and austerity are
even more necessary for the appreciation of life and laughter than
for anything else. To let no bird fly past unnoticed, to spell
patiently the stones and weeds, to have the mind a storehouse of
sunset, requires a discipline in pleasure, and an education in
gratitude.
The civilisation which surrounded
Savonarola on every side was a civilisation which had already taken
the wrong turn, the turn that leads to endless inventions and no
discoveries, in which new things grow old with confounding rapidity,
but in which no old things ever grow new. The monstrosity of the
crimes of the Renaissance was not a mark of imagination; it was a
mark, as all monstrosity is, of the loss of imagination. It is only
when a man has really ceased to see a horse as it is, that he invents
a centaur, only when he can no longer be surprised at an ox, that he
worships the devil. Diablerie is the stimulant of the jaded fancy; it
is the dram-drinking of the artist. Savonarola addressed himself to
the hardest of all earthly tasks, that of making men turn back and
wonder at the simplicities they had learnt to ignore. It is strange
that the most unpopular of all doctrines is the doctrine which
declares the common life divine. Democracy, of which Savonarola was
so fiery an exponent, is the hardest of gospels; there is nothing
that so terrifies men as the decree that they are all kings.
Christianity, in Savonarola’s mind, identical with democracy,
is the hardest of gospels; there is nothing that so strikes men with
fear as the saying that they are all the sons of God.
Savonarola and his republic fell. The
drug of despotism was administered to the people, and they forgot
what they had been. There are some at the present day who have so
strange a respect for art and letters, and for mere men of genius,
that they conceive the reign of the Medici to be an improvement on
that of the great Florentine republican. It is such men as these and
their civilisation that we have at the present day to fear. We are
surrounded on many sides by the same symptoms as those which awoke
the unquenchable wrath of Savonarola–a hedonism that is more
sick of happiness than an invalid is sick of pain, an art sense that
seeks the assistance of crime since it has exhausted nature. In many
modern works we find veiled and horrible hints of a truly Renaissance
sense of the beauty of blood, the poetry of murder. The bankrupt and
depraved imagination does not see that a living man is far more
dramatic than a dead one. Along with this, as in the time of the
Medici, goes the falling back into the arms of despotism, the hunger
for the strong man which is unknown among strong men. The masterful
hero is worshipped as he is worshipped by the readers of the “Bow
Bells Novelettes,” and for the same reason–a profound
sense of personal weakness. That tendency to devolve our duties
descends on us, which is the soul of slavery, alike whether for its
menial tasks it employs serfs or emperors. Against all this the great
clerical republican stands in everlasting protest, preferring his
failure to his rival’s success. The issue is still between him
and Lorenzo, between the responsibilities of liberty and the license
of slavery, between the perils of truth and the security of silence,
between the pleasure of toil and the toil of pleasure. The supporters
of Lorenzo the Magnificent are assuredly among us, men for whom even
nations and empires only exist to satisfy the moment, men to whom the
last hot hour of summer is better than a sharp and wintry spring.
They have an art, a literature, a political philosophy, which are all
alike valued for their immediate effect upon the taste, not for what
they promise of the destiny of the spirit. Their statuettes and
sonnets are rounded and perfect, while “Macbeth” is in
comparison a fragment, and the Moses of Michael Angelo a hint. Their
campaigns and battles are always called triumphant, while Cæsar
and Cromwell wept for many humiliations. And the end of it all is the
hell of no resistance, the hell of an unfathomable softness, until
the whole nature recoils into madness and the chamber of civilisation
is no longer merely a cushioned apartment, but a padded cell.
This last and worst of human miseries
Savonarola saw afar off, and bent his whole gigantic energies to
turning the chariot into another course. Few men understood his
object; some called him a madman, some a charlatan, some an enemy of
human joy. They would not even have understood if he had told them,
if he had said that he was saving them from a calamity of contentment
which should be the end of joys and sorrows alike. But there are
those to-day who feel the same silent danger, and who bend themselves
to the same silent resistance. They also are supposed to be
contending for some trivial political scruple.
Mr. M’Hardy says, in defending
Savonarola, that the number of fine works of art destroyed in the
Burning of the Vanities has been much exaggerated. I confess that I
hope the pile contained stacks of incomparable masterpieces if the
sacrifice made that one real moment more real. Of one thing I am
sure, that Savonarola’s friend Michael Angelo would have piled
all his own statues one on top of the other, and burnt them to ashes,
if only he had been certain that the glow transfiguring the sky was
the dawn of a younger and wiser world.
THE POSITION OF SIR WALTER SCOTT
Walter Scott is a writer who should
just now be re-emerging into his own high place in letters, for
unquestionably the recent, though now dwindling, schools of severely
technical and æsthetic criticism have been unfavourable to him.
He was a chaotic and unequal writer, and if there is one thing in
which artists have improved since his time, it is in consistency and
equality. It would perhaps be unkind to inquire whether the level of
the modern man of letters, as compared with Scott, is due to the
absence of valleys or the absence of mountains. But in any case, we
have learnt in our day to arrange our literary effects carefully, and
the only point in which we fall short of Scott is in the incidental
misfortune that we have nothing particular to arrange.
It is said that Scott is neglected by
modern readers; if so, the matter could be more appropriately
described by saying that modern readers are neglected by Providence.
The ground of this neglect, in so far as it exists, must be found, I
suppose, in the general sentiment that, like the beard of Polonius,
he is too long. Yet it is surely a peculiar thing that in literature
alone a house should be despised because it is too large, or a host
impugned because he is too generous. If romance be really a pleasure,
it is difficult to understand the modern reader’s consuming
desire to get it over, and if it be not a pleasure, it is difficult
to understand his desire to have it at all. Mere size, it seems to
me, cannot be a fault. The fault must lie in some disproportion. If
some of Scott’s stories are dull and dilatory, it is not
because they are giants, but because they are hunchbacks or cripples.
Scott was very far indeed from being a perfect writer, but I do not
think that it can be shown that the large and elaborate plan on which
his stories are built was by any means an imperfection. He arranged
his endless prefaces and his colossal introductions just as an
architect plans great gates and long approaches to a really large
house. He did not share the latter-day desire to get quickly through
a story. He enjoyed narrative as a sensation; he did not wish to
swallow a story like a pill, that it should do him good afterwards.
He desired to taste it like a glass of port, that it might do him
good at the time. The reader sits late at his banquets. His
characters have that air of immortality which belongs to those of
Dumas and Dickens. We should not be surprised to meet them in any
number of sequels. Scott, in his heart of hearts, probably would have
liked to write an endless story without either beginning or close.
Walter Scott is a great, and,
therefore, mysterious man. He will never be understood until Romance
is understood, and that will be only when Time, Man, and Eternity are
understood. To say that Scott had more than any other man that ever
lived a sense of the romantic seems, in these days, a slight and
superficial tribute. The whole modern theory arises from one
fundamental mistake–the idea that romance is in some way a
plaything with life, a figment, a conventionality, a thing upon the
outside. No genuine criticism of romance will ever arise until we
have grasped the fact that romance lies not upon the outside of life,
but absolutely in the centre of it. The centre of every man’s
existence is a dream. Death, disease, insanity, are merely material
accidents, like toothache or a twisted ankle. That these brutal
forces always besiege and often capture the citadel does not prove
that they are the citadel. The boast of the realist (applying what
the reviewers call his scalpel) is that he cuts into the heart of
life; but he makes a very shallow incision, if he only reaches as
deep as habits and calamities and sins. Deeper than all these lies a
man’s vision of himself, as swaggering and sentimental as a
penny novelette. The literature of can-dour unearths innumerable
weaknesses and elements of lawlessness which is called romance. It
perceives superficial habits like murder and dipsomania, but it does
not perceive the deepest of sins–the sin of vanity–vanity
which is the mother of all day-dreams and adventures, the one sin
that is not shared with any boon companion, or whispered to any
priest.
In estimating, therefore, the ground
of Scott’s pre-eminence in romance we must absolutely rid
ourselves of the notion that romance or adventure are merely
materialistic things involved in the tangle of a plot or the
multiplicity of drawn swords. We must remember that it is, like
tragedy or farce, a state of the soul, and that, for some dark and
elemental reason which we can never understand, this state of the
soul is evoked in us by the sight of certain places or the
contemplation of certain human crises, by a stream rushing under a
heavy and covered wooden bridge, or by a man plunging a knife or
sword into tough timber. In the selection of these situations which
catch the spirit of romance as in a net, Scott has never been
equalled or even approached. His finest scenes affect us like
fragments of a hilarious dream. They have the same quality which is
often possessed by those nocturnal comedies–that of seeming
more human than our waking life–even while they are less
possible. Sir Arthur Wardour, with his daughter and the old beggar
crouching in a cranny of the cliff as night falls and the tide closes
around them, are actually in the coldest and bitterest of practical
situations. Yet the whole incident has a quality that can only be
called boyish. It is warmed with all the colours of an incredible
sunset. Rob Roy trapped in the Tolbooth, and confronted with Bailie
Nicol Jarvie, draws no sword, leaps from no window, affects none of
the dazzling external acts upon which contemporary romance depends,
yet that plain and humourous dialogue is full of the essential
philosophy of romance which is an almost equal betting upon man and
destiny. Perhaps the most profoundly thrilling of all Scott’s
situations is that in which the family of Colonel Mannering are
waiting for the carriage which may or may not arrive by night to
bring an unknown man into a princely possession. Yet almost the whole
of that thrilling scene consists of a ridiculous conversation about
food, and flirtation between a frivolous old lawyer and a fashionable
girl. We can say nothing about what makes these scenes, except that
the wind bloweth where it listeth, and that here the wind blows
strong.
It is in this quality of what may be
called spiritual adventurousness that Scott stands at so different an
elevation to the whole of the contemporary crop of romancers who have
followed the leadership of Dumas. There has, indeed, been a great and
inspiriting revival of romance in our time, but it is partly
frustrated in almost every case by this rooted conception that
romance consists in the vast multiplication of incidents and the
violent acceleration of narrative. The heroes of Mr. Stanley Weyman
scarcely ever have their swords out of their hands; the deeper
presence of romance is far better felt when the sword is at the hip
ready for innumerable adventures too terrible to be pictured. The
Stanley Weyman hero has scarcely time to eat his supper except in the
act of leaping from a window or whilst his other hand is employed in
lunging with a rapier. In Scott’s heroes, on the other hand,
there is no characteristic so typical or so worthy of humour as their
disposition to linger over their meals. The conviviality of the Clerk
of Copmanhurst or of Mr. Pleydell, and the thoroughly solid things
they are described as eating, is one of the most perfect of Scott’s
poetic touches. In short, Mr. Stanley Weyman is filled with the
conviction that the sole essence of romance is to move with
insatiable rapidity from incident to incident. In the truer romance
of Scott there is more of the sentiment of “Oh! still delay,
thou art so fair”! more of a certain patriarchal enjoyment of
things as they are–of the sword by the side and the wine-cup in
the hand. Romance, indeed, does not consist by any means so much in
experiencing adventures as in being ready for them. How little the
actual boy cares for incidents in comparison to tools and weapons may
be tested by the fact that the most popular story of adventure is
concerned with a man who lived for years on a desert island with two
guns and a sword, which he never had to use on an enemy.
Closely connected with this is one of
the charges most commonly brought against Scott, particularly in his
own day–the charge of a fanciful and monotonous insistence upon
the details of armour and costume. The critic in the Edinburgh
Review said indignantly that he could tolerate a somewhat
detailed description of the apparel of Marmion, but when it came to
an equally detailed account of the apparel of his pages and yeomen
the mind could bear it no longer. The only thing to be said about
that critic is that he had never been a little boy. He foolishly
imagined that Scott valued the plume and dagger of Marmion for
Marmion’s sake. Not being himself romantic, he could not
understand that Scott valued the plume because it was a plume, and
the dagger because it was a dagger. Like a child, he loved weapons
with a manual materialistic love, as one loves the softness of fur or
the coolness of marble. One of the profound philosophical truths
which are almost confined to infants is this love of things, not for
their use or origin, but for their own inherent characteristics, the
child’s love of the toughness of wood, the wetness of water,
the magnificent soapiness of soap. So it was with Scott, who had so
much of the child in him. Human beings were perhaps the principal
characters in his stories, but they were certainly not the only
characters. A battle-axe was a person of importance, a castle had a
character and ways of its own. A church bell had a word to say in the
matter. Like a true child, he almost ignored the distinction between
the animate and inanimate. A two-handed sword might be carried only
by a menial in a procession, but it was something important and
immeasurably fascinating–it was a two-handed sword.
There is one quality which is supreme
and continuous in Scott which is little appreciated at present. One
of the values we have really lost in recent fiction is the value of
eloquence. The modern literary artist is compounded of almost every
man except the orator. Yet Shakespeare and Scott are certainly alike
in this, that they could both, if literature had failed, have earned
a living as professional demagogues. The feudal heroes in the
“Waverley Novels” retort upon each other with a
passionate dignity, haughty and yet singularly human, which can
hardly be paralleled in political eloquence except in “Julius
Cæsar.” With a certain fiery impartiality which stirs the
blood, Scott distributes his noble orations equally among saints and
villains. He may deny a villain every virtue or triumph, but he
cannot endure to deny him a telling word; he will ruin a man, but he
will not silence him. In truth, one of Scott’s most splendid
traits is his difficulty, or rather incapacity, for despising any of
his characters. He did not scorn the most revolting miscreant as the
realist of to-day commonly scorns his own hero. Though his soul may
be in rags, every man of Scott can speak like a king.
This quality, as I have said, is
sadly to seek in the fiction of the passing hour. The realist would,
of course, repudiate the bare idea of putting a bold and brilliant
tongue in every man’s head, but even where the moment of the
story naturally demands eloquence the eloquence seems frozen in the
tap. Take any contemporary work of fiction and turn to the scene
where the young Socialist denounces the millionaire, and then compare
the stilted sociological lecture given by that self-sacrificing bore
with the surging joy of words in Rob Roy’s declaration of
himself, or Athelstane’s defiance of De Bracy. That ancient sea
of human passion upon which high words and great phrases are the
resplendent foam is just now at a low ebb. We have even gone the
length of congratulating ourselves because we can see the mud and the
monsters at the bottom.
In politics there is not a single man
whose position is due to eloquence in the first degree; its place is
taken by repartees and rejoinders purely intellectual, like those of
an omnibus conductor. In discussing questions like the farm-burning
in South Africa no critic of the war uses his material as Burke or
Grattan (perhaps exaggeratively) would have used it–the speaker
is content with facts and expositions of facts. In another age he
might have risen and hurled that great song in prose, perfect as
prose and yet rising into a chant, which Meg Merrilies hurled at
Ellangowan, at the rulers of Britain: “Ride your ways. Laird of
Ellangowan; ride your ways, Godfrey Bertram–this day have ye
quenched seven smoking hearths. See if the fire in your ain parlour
burns the blyther for that. Ye have riven the thack of seven cottar
houses. Look if your ain roof-tree stands the faster for that. Ye may
stable your stirks in the sheilings of Dern-cleugh. See that the hare
does not couch on the hearthstane of Ellangowan. Ride your ways,
Godfrey Bertram.”
The reason is, of course, that these
men are afraid of bombast and Scott was not. A man will not reach
eloquence if he is afraid of bombast, just as a man will not jump a
hedge if he is afraid of a ditch. As the object of all eloquence is
to find the least common denominator of men’s souls, to fall
just within the natural comprehension, it cannot obviously have any
chance with a literary ambition which aims at falling just outside
it. It is quite right to invent subtle analyses and detached
criticisms, but it is unreasonable to expect them to be punctuated
with roars of popular applause. It is possible to conceive of a mob
shouting any central and simple sentiment, good or bad, but it is
impossible to think of a mob shouting a distinction in terms. In the
matter of eloquence, the whole question is one of the immediate
effect of greatness, such as is produced even by fine bombast. It is
absurd to call it merely superficial; here there is no question of
superficiality; we might as well call a stone that strikes us between
the eyes merely superficial. The very word “superficial”
is founded on a fundamental mistake about life, the idea that second
thoughts are best. The superficial impression of the world is by far
the deepest. What we really feel, naturally and casually, about the
look of skies and trees and the face of friends, that and that alone
will almost certainly remain our vital philosophy to our dying day.
Scott’s bombast, therefore,
will always be stirring to anyone who approaches it, as he should
approach all literature, as a little child. We could easily excuse
the contemporary critic for not admiring melodramas and adventure
stories, and Punch and Judy, if he would admit that it was a slight
deficiency in his artistic sensibilities. Beyond all question, it
marks a lack of literary instinct to be unable to simplify one’s
mind at the first signal of the advance of romance. “You do me
wrong,” said Brian de Bois-Guilbert to Rebecca. “Many a
law, many a commandment have I broken, but my word, never.”
“Die,” cries Balfour of Burley to the villain in “Old
Mortality.” “Die, hoping nothing, believing nothing–”
“And fearing nothing,” replies the other. This is the old
and honourable fine art of bragging, as it was practised by the great
worthies of antiquity. The man who cannot appreciate it goes along
with the man who cannot appreciate beef or claret or a game with
children or a brass band. They are afraid of making fools of
themselves, and are unaware that that transformation has already been
triumphantly effected.
Scott is separated, then, from much
of the later conception of fiction by this quality of eloquence. The
whole of the best and finest work of the modern novelist (such as the
work of Mr. Henry James) is primarily concerned with that delicate
and fascinating speech which burrows deeper and deeper like a mole;
but we have wholly forgotten that speech which mounts higher and
higher like a wave and falls in a crashing peroration. Perhaps the
most thoroughly brilliant and typical man of this decade is Mr.
Bernard Shaw. In his admirable play of “Candida” it is
clearly a part of the character of the Socialist clergyman that he
should be eloquent, but he is not eloquent because the whole “G.B.S.”
condition of mind renders impossible that poetic simplicity which
eloquence requires. Scott takes his heroes and villains seriously,
which is, after all, the way that heroes and villains take
themselves–especially villains. It is the custom to call these
old romantic poses artificial; but the word artificial is the last
and silliest evasion of criticism. There was never anything in the
world that was really artificial. It had some motive or ideal behind
it, and generally a much better one than we think.
Of the faults of Scott as an artist
it is not very necessary to speak, for faults are generally and
easily pointed out, while there is yet no adequate valuation of the
varieties and contrasts of virtue. We have compiled a complete
botanical classification of the weeds in the poetical garden, but the
flowers still flourish, neglected and nameless. It is true, for
example, that Scott had an incomparably stiff and pedantic way of
dealing with his heroines: he made a lively girl of eighteen refuse
an offer in the language of Dr. Johnson. To him, as to most men of
his time, woman was not an individual, but an institution–a
toast that was drunk some time after that of Church and King. But it
is far better to consider the difference rather as a special merit,
in that he stood for all those clean and bracing shocks of incident
which are untouched by passion or weakness, for a certain breezy
bachelorhood, which is almost essential to the literature of
adventure. With all his faults, and all his triumphs, he stands for
the great mass of natural manliness which must be absorbed into art
unless art is to be a mere luxury and freak. An appreciation of Scott
might be made almost a test of decadence. If ever we lose touch with
this one most reckless and defective writer, it will be a proof to us
that we have erected round ourselves a false cosmos, a world of lying
and horrible perfection, leaving outside of it Walter Scott and that
strange old world which is as confused and as indefensible and as
inspiring and as healthy as he.
BRET HARTE
There are more than nine hundred and
ninety-nine excellent reasons which we could all have for admiring
the work of Bret Harte. But one supreme reason stands not in a
certain general superiority to them all–a reason which may be
stated in three propositions united in a common conclusion: first,
that he was a genuine American; second, that he was a genuine
humourist; and, third, that he was not an American humourist. Bret
Harte had his own peculiar humour, but it had nothing in particular
to do with American humour. American humour has its own peculiar
excellence, but it has nothing in particular to do with Bret Harte.
American humour is purely exaggerative; Bret Harte’s humour was
sympathetic and analytical.
In order fully to understand this, it
is necessary to realise, genuinely and thoroughly, that there is such
a thing as an international difference in humour. If we take the
crudest joke in the world–the joke, let us say, of a man
sitting down on his hat–we shall yet find that all the nations
would differ in their way of treating it humourously, and that if
American humour treated it at all, it would be in a purely American
manner. For example, there was a case of an orator in the House of
Commons, who, after denouncing all the public abuses he could think
of, did sit down on his hat. An Irishman immediately rose, full of
the whole wealth of Irish humour, and said, “Should I be in
order, Sir, in congratulating the honourable gentleman on the fact
that when he sat down on his hat his head was not in it?” Here
is a glorious example of Irish humour–the bull not unconscious,
not entirely conscious, but rather an idea so absurd that even the
utterer of it can hardly realise how abysmally absurd it is. But
every other nation would have treated the idea in a manner slightly
different. The Frenchman’s humour would have been logical: he
would have said, “The orator denounces modern abuses and
destroys to himself the top-hat: behold a good example!” What
the Scotchman’s humour would have said I am not so certain, but
it would probably have dealt with the serious advisability of making
such speeches on top of someone else’s hat. But American humour
on such a general theme would be the humour of exaggeration. The
American humourist would say that the English politicians so often
sat down on their hats that the noise of the House of Commons was one
crackle of silk. He would say that when an important orator rose to
speak in the House of Commons, long rows of hatters waited outside
the House with note-books to take down orders from the participants
in the debate. He would say that the whole hat trade of London was
disorganised by the news that a clever remark had been made by a
young M. P. on the subject of the imports of Jamaica. In short,
American humour, neither unfathomably absurd like the Irish, nor
transfiguringly lucid and appropriate like the French, nor sharp and
sensible and full of realities of life like the Scotch, is simply the
humour of imagination. It consists in piling towers on towers and
mountains on mountains; of heaping a joke up to the stars and
extending it to the end of the world.
With this distinctively American
humour Bret Harte had little or nothing in common. The wild,
sky-breaking humour of America has its fine qualities, but it must in
the nature of things be deficient in two qualities, not only of
supreme importance to life and letters, but of supreme importance to
humour–reverence and sympathy. And these two qualities were
knit into the closest texture of Bret Harte’s humour. Everyone
who has read and enjoyed Mark Twain as he ought to be read and
enjoyed will remember a very funny and irreverent story about an
organist who was asked to play appropriate music to an address upon
the parable of the Prodigal Son, and who proceeded to play with great
spirit, “We’ll all get blind drunk, when Johnny comes
marching home.” The best way of distinguishing Bret Harte from
the rest of American humour is to say that if Bret Harte had
described that scene, it would in some subtle way have combined a
sense of the absurdity of the incident with some sense of the
sublimity and pathos of the theme. You would have felt that the
organist’s tune was funny, but not that the Prodigal Son was
funny. But America is under a kind of despotism of humour. Everyone
is afraid of humour: the meanest of human nightmares. Bret Harte had,
to express the matter briefly but more or less essentially, the power
of laughing not only at things, but also with them. America has
laughed at things magnificently, with Gargantuan reverberations of
laughter. But she has not even begun to learn the richer lesson of
laughing with them.
The supreme proof of the fact that
Bret Harte had the instinct of reverence may be found in the fact
that he was a really great parodist. This may have the appearance of
being a paradox, but, as in the case of many other paradoxes, it is
not so important whether it is a paradox as whether it is not
obviously true. Mere derision, mere contempt, never produced or could
produce parody. A man who simply despises Paderewski for having long
hair is not necessarily fitted to give an admirable imitation of his
particular touch on the piano. If a man wishes to parody Paderewski’s
style of execution, he must emphatically go through one process
first: he must admire it, and even reverence it. Bret Harte had a
real power of imitating great authors, as in his parodies on Dumas,
on Victor Hugo, on Charlotte Brontë. This means, and can only
mean, that he had perceived the real beauty, the real ambition of
Dumas and Victor Hugo and Charlotte Brontë. To take an example,
Bret Harte has in his imitation of Hugo a passage like this:
“M. Madeline
was, if possible, better than M. Myriel. M. Myriel was an angel. M.
Madeline was a good man.” I do not know whether Victor Hugo
ever used this antithesis; but I am certain that he would have used
it and thanked his stars if he had thought of it. This is real
parody, inseparable from admiration. It is the same in the parody of
Dumas, which is arranged on the system of “Aramis killed three
of them. Porthos three. Athos three.” You cannot write that
kind of thing unless you have first exulted in the arithmetical
ingenuity of the plots of Dumas. It is the same in the parody of
Charlotte Brontë, which opens with a dream of a storm-beaten
cliff, containing jewels and pelicans. Bret Harte could not have
written it unless he had really understood the triumph of the
Brontës, the triumph of asserting that great mysteries lie under
the surface of the most sullen life, and that the most real part of a
man is in his dreams.
This kind of parody is for ever
removed from the purview of ordinary American humour. Can anyone
imagine Mark Twain, that admirable author, writing even a tolerable
imitation of authors so intellectually individual as Hugo or
Charlotte Brontë? Mark Twain would yield to the spirit of
contempt which destroys parody. All those who hate authors fail to
satirise them, for they always accuse them of the wrong faults. The
enemies of Thackeray call him a worldling, instead of what he was, a
man too ready to believe in the goodness of the unworldly. The
enemies of Meredith call his gospel too subtle, instead of what it
is, a gospel, if anything, too robust. And it is this vulgar
misunderstanding which we find in most parody–which we find in
all American parody–but which we never find in the parodies of
Bret Harte.
“The
skies they were ashen and sober, The streets they were dirty and
drear, It was the dark month of October, In that most
immemorial year. Like the skies, I was perfectly sober, But my
thoughts they were palsied and sear, Yes, my thoughts were
decidedly queer.”
This could only be written by a
genuine admirer of Edgar Allan Poe, who permitted himself for a
moment to see the fun of the thing. Parody might indeed be defined as
the worshipper’s half-holiday.
The same general characteristic of
sympathy amounting to reverence marks Bret Harte’s humour in
his better-known class of works, the short stories. He does not make
his characters absurd in order to make them contemptible: it might
almost be said that he makes them absurd in order to make them
dignified. For example, the greatest creation of Bret Harte, greater
even than Colonel Starbottle (and how terrible it is to speak of
anyone greater than Colonel Starbottle!) is that unutterable being
who goes by the name of Yuba Bill. He is, of course, the coach-driver
in the Bret Harte district. Some ingenious person, whose remarks I
read the other day, had compared him on this ground with old Mr.
Weller. It would be difficult to find a comparison indicating a more
completely futile instinct for literature. Tony Weller and Yuba Bill
were both coach-drivers, and this fact establishes a resemblance just
about as much as the fact that Jobson in “Rob Roy” and
George Warrington in “Pendennis” were both lawyers; or
that Antonio and Mr. Pickwick were both merchants; or that Sir
Galahad and Sir Willoughby Patten were both knights. Tony Weller is a
magnificent grotesque. He is a gargoyle, and his mouth, like the
mouths of so many gargoyles, is always open. He is garrulous,
exuberant, flowery, preposterously sociable. He holds that great
creed of the convivial, the creed which is at the back of so much
that is greatest in Dickens, the creed that eternity begins at ten
o’clock at night, and that nights last forever. But Yuba Bill
is a figure of a widely different character. He is not convivial; it
might almost be said that he is too great ever to be sociable. A
circle of quiescence and solitude such as that which might ring a
saint or a hermit rings this majestic and profound humourist. His
jokes do not flow upon him like those of Mr. Weller, sparkling,
continual, and deliberate, like the play of a fountain in a pleasure
garden; they fall suddenly and capriciously, like a crash of
avalanches from a great mountain. Tony Weller has the noisy humour of
London, Yuba Bill has the silent humour of the earth.
One of the worst of the disadvantages
of the rich and random fertility of Bret Harte is the fact that it is
very difficult to trace or recover all the stories that he has
written. I have not within reach at the moment the story in which the
character of Yuba Bill is exhibited in its most solemn grandeur, but
I remember that it concerned a ride on the San Francisco stage coach,
a difficulty arising from storm and darkness, and an intelligent
young man who suggested to Yuba Bill that a certain manner of driving
the coach in a certain direction might minimise the dangers of the
journey. A profound silence followed the intelligent young man’s
suggestion, and then (I quote from memory) Yuba Bill observed at
last:
“Air you
settin’ any value on that remark?”
The young man professed not fully to
comprehend him, and Yuba Bill continued reflectively:
“‘Cos
there’s a comic paper in ‘Frisco pays for them things,
and I’ve seen worse in it.”
To be rebuked thus is like being
rebuked by the Pyramids or by the starry heavens. There is about Yuba
Bill this air of a pugnacious calm, a stepping back to get his
distance for a shattering blow, which is like that of Dr. Johnson at
his best. And the effect is inexpressively increased by the
background and the whole picture which Bret Harte paints so
powerfully; the stormy skies, the sombre gorge, the rocking and
spinning coach, and high above the feverish passengers the huge dark
form of Yuba Bill, a silent mountain of humour.
Another unrecovered and possibly
irrecoverable fragment about Yuba Bill, I recall in a story about his
visiting a lad who had once been his protége in the Wild West,
and who had since become a distinguished literary man in Boston. Yuba
Bill visits him, and on finding him in evening dress lifts up his
voice in a superb lamentation over the tragedy of finding his old
friend at last “a ‘otel waiter.” Then, vindictively
pursuing the satire, he calls fiercely to his young friend, “Hi,
Alphonse! bring me a patty de foy gras, damme.” These are the
things that make us love the eminent Bill. He is one of those who
achieve the noblest and most difficult of all the triumphs of a
fictitious character–the triumph of giving us the impression of
having a great deal more in him than appears between the two boards
of the story. Smaller characters give us the impression that the
author has told the whole truth about them, greater characters give
the impression that the author has given of them, not the truth, but
merely a few hints and samples. In some mysterious way we seem to
feel that even if Shakespeare was wrong about Falstaff, Falstaff
existed and was real; that even if Dickens was wrong about Micawber,
Micawber existed and was real. So we feel that there is in the great
salt-sea of Yuba Bill’s humour as good fish as ever came out of
it. The fleeting jests which Yuba Bill throws to the coach passengers
only give us the opportunity of fancying and deducing the vast mass
of jests which Yuba Bill shares with his creator.
Bret Harte had to deal with countries
and communities of an almost unexampled laxity, a laxity passing the
laxity of savages, the laxity of civilised men grown savage. He dealt
with a life which we in a venerable and historic society may find it
somewhat difficult to realise. It was the life of an entirely new
people, a people who, having no certain past, could have no certain
future. The strangest of all the sardonic jests that history has ever
played may be found in this fact: that there is a city which is of
all cities the most typical of innovation and dissipation, and a
certain almost splendid vulgarity, and that this city bears the name
in a quaint old European language of the most perfect exponent of the
simplicity and holiness of the Christian tradition; the city is
called San Francisco. San Francisco, the capital of the Bret Harte
country, is a city typifying novelty in a manner in which it is
typified by few modern localities. San Francisco has in all
probability its cathedrals, but it may well be that its cathedrals
are less old and less traditional than many of our hotels. If its
inhabitants built a temple to the most primal and forgotten god of
whose worship we can find a trace, that temple would still be a
modern thing compared with many taverns in Suffolk round which there
lingers a faint tradition of Mr. Pickwick. And everything in that new
gold country was new, even to the individual inhabitants. Good, bad,
and indifferent, heroes and dastards, they were all men from nowhere.
Most of us have come across the
practical problem of London landladies, the problem of the doubtful
foreign gentleman in a street of respectable English people. Those
who have done so can form some idea of what it would be to live in a
street full of doubtful foreign gentlemen, in a parish, in a city, in
a nation composed entirely of doubtful foreign gentlemen. Old
California, at the time of the first rush after gold, was actually
this paradox of the nation of foreigners. It was a republic of
incognitos: no one knew who anyone else was, and only the more
ill-mannered and uneasy even desired to know. In such a country as
this, gentlemen took more trouble to conceal their gentility than
thieves living in South Kensington would take to conceal their
blackguardism. In such a country everyone is an equal, because
everyone is a stranger. In such a country it is not strange if men in
moral matters feel something of the irresponsibility of a dream. To
plan plans which are continually miscarrying against men who are
continually disappearing by the assistance of you know not whom, to
crush you know not whom, this must be a demoralising life for any
man; it must be beyond description demoralising for those who have
been trained in no lofty or orderly scheme of right. Small blame to
them indeed if they become callous and supercilious and cynical. And
the great glory and achievement of Bret Harte consists in this, that
he realised that they do not become callous, supercilious, and
cynical, but that they do become sentimental and romantic, and
profoundly affectionate. He discovered the intense sensibility of the
primitive man. To him we owe the realisation of the fact that while
modern barbarians of genius like Mr. Henley, and in his weaker
moments Mr. Rudyard Kipling, delight in describing the coarseness and
crude cynicism and fierce humour of the unlettered classes, the
unlettered classes are in reality highly sentimental and religious,
and not in the least like the creations of Mr. Henley and Mr.
Kipling. Bret Harte tells the truth about the wildest, the grossest,
the most rapacious of all the districts of the earth–the truth
that, while it is very rare indeed in the world to find a thoroughly
good man, it is rarer still, rare to the point of monstrosity, to
find a man who does not either desire to be one, or imagine that he
is one already.
ALFRED THE GREAT
The celebrations in connection with
the millenary of King Alfred struck a note of sympathy in the midst
of much that was unsympathetic, because, altogether apart from any
peculiar historical opinions, all men feel the sanctifying character
of that which is at once strong and remote; the ancient thing is
always the most homely, and the distant thing the most near. The only
possible peacemaker is a dead man, ever since by the sublime
religious story a dead man only could reconcile heaven and earth. In
a certain sense we always feel the past ages as human, and our own
age as strangely and even weirdly dehumanised. In our own time the
details overpower us; men’s badges and buttons seem to grow
larger and larger as in a horrible dream. To study humanity in the
present is like studying a mountain with a magnifying glass; to study
it in the past is like studying it through a telescope.
For this reason England, like every
other great and historic nation, has sought its typical hero in
remote and ill-recorded times. The personal and moral greatness of
Alfred is, indeed, beyond question. It does not depend any more than
the greatness of any other human hero upon the accuracy of any or all
of the stories that are told about him. Alfred may not have done one
of the things which are reported of him, but it is immeasurably
easier to do every one of those things than to be the man of whom
such things are reported falsely. Fable is, generally speaking, far
more accurate than fact, for fable describes a man as he was to his
own age, fact describes him as he is to a handful of inconsiderable
antiquarians many centuries after. Whether Alfred watched the cakes
for the neat-herd’s wife, whether he sang songs in the Danish
camp, is of no interest to anyone except those who set out to prove
under considerable disadvantages that they are genealogically
descended from him. But the man is better pictured in these stories
than in any number of modern realistic trivialities about his
favourite breakfast and his favourite musical composer. Fable is more
historical than fact, because fact tells us about one man and fable
tells us about a million men. If we read of a man who could make
green grass red and turn the sun into the moon, we may not believe
these particular details about him, but we learn something infinitely
more important than such trivialities, the fact that men could look
into his face and believe it possible. The glory and greatness of
Alfred, therefore, is like that of all the heroes of the morning of
the world, set far beyond the chance of that strange and sudden
dethronement which may arise from the unsealing of a manuscript or
the turning over of a stone. Men may have told lies when they said
that he first entrapped the Danes with his song and then overcame
them with his armies, but we know very well that it is not of us that
such lies are told. There may be myths clustering about each of our
personalities; local saga-men and chroniclers have very likely
circulated the story that we are addicted to drink, or that we
ferociously ill-use our wives. But they do not commonly lie to the
effect that we have shed our blood to save all the inhabitants of the
street. A story grows easily, but a heroic story is not a very easy
thing to evoke. Wherever that exists we may be pretty certain that we
are in the presence of a dark but powerful historic personality. We
are in the presence of a thousand lies all pointing with their
fantastic fingers to one undiscovered truth.
Upon this ground alone every
encouragement is due to the cult of Alfred. Every nation requires to
have behind it some historic personality, the validity of which is
proved, as the validity of a gun is proved, by its long range. It is
wonderful and splendid that we treasure, not the truth, but the very
gossip about a man who died a thousand years ago. We may say to him,
as M. Rostand says to the Austrian Prince:
“Dors,
ce n’est pas toujours la Légende qui ment: Une rêve
est parfois moins trompeur qu’un document.”
To have a man so simple and so
honourable to represent us in the darkness of primeval history, binds
all the intervening centuries together, and mollifies all their
monstrosities. It makes all history more comforting and intelligible;
it makes the desolate temple of the ages as human as an inn parlour.
But whether it come through reliable
facts or through more reliable falsehoods the personality of Alfred
has its own unmistakable colour and stature. Lord Rosebery uttered a
profound truth when he said that that personality was peculiarly
English. The great magnificence of the English character is expressed
in the word “service.” There is, perhaps, no nation so
vitally theocratical as the English; no nation in which the strong
men have so consistently preferred the instrumental to the despotic
attitude, the pleasures of the loyal to the pleasures of the royal
position. We have had tyrants like Edward I. and Queen Elizabeth, but
even our tyrants have had the worried and responsible air of stewards
of a great estate. Our typical hero is such a man as the Duke of
Wellington, who had every kind of traditional and external arrogance,
but at the back of all that the strange humility which made it
physically possible for him without a gleam of humour or discomfort
to go on his knees to a preposterous bounder like George IV. Across
the infinite wastes of time and through all the mists of legend we
still feel the presence in Alfred of this strange and unconscious
self-effacement. After the fullest estimate of our misdeeds we can
still say that our very despots have been less self-assertive than
many popular patriots. As we consider these things we grow more and
more impatient of any modern tendencies towards the enthronement of a
more self-conscious and theatrical ideal. Lord Rosebery called up
before our imaginations the picture of what Alfred would have thought
of the vast modern developments of his nation, its immense fleet, its
widespread Empire, its enormous contribution to the mechanical
civilisation of the world. It cannot be anything but profitable to
conceive Alfred as full of astonishment and admiration at these
things; it cannot be anything but good for us that we should realise
that to the childlike eyes of a great man of old time our inventions
and appliances have not the vulgarity and ugliness that we see in
them. To Alfred a steamboat would be a new and sensational
sea-dragon, and the penny postage a miracle achieved by the despotism
of a demi-god.
But when we have realised all this
there is something more to be said in connection with Lord Rosebery’s
vision. What would King Alfred have said if he had been asked to
expend the money which he devoted to the health and education of his
people upon a struggle with some race of Visigoths or Parthians
inhabiting a small section of a distant continent? What would he have
said if he had known that that science of letters which he taught to
England would eventually be used not to spread truth, but to drug the
people with political assurances as imbecile in themselves as the
assurance that fire does not burn and water does not drown? What
would he have said if the same people who, in obedience to that ideal
of service and sanity of which he was the example, had borne every
privation in order to defeat Napoleon, should come at last to find no
better compliment to one of their heroes than to call him the
Napoleon of South Africa? What would he have said if that nation for
which he had inaugurated a long line of incomparable men of principle
should forget all its traditions and coquette with the immoral
mysticism of the man of destiny?
Let us follow these things by all
means if we find them good, and can see nothing better. But to
pretend that Alfred would have admired them is like pretending that
St. Dominic would have seen eye to eye with Mr. Bradlaugh, or that
Fra Angelico would have revelled in the posters of Mr. Aubrey
Beardsley. Let us follow them if we will, but let us take honestly
all the disadvantages of our change; in the wildest moment of triumph
let us feel the shadow upon our glories of the shame of the great
king.
MAETERLINCK
The selection of “Thoughts from
Maeterlinck” is a very creditable and also a very useful
compilation. Many modern critics object to the hacking and hewing of
a consistent writer which is necessary for this kind of work, but
upon more serious consideration, the view is not altogether adequate.
Maeterlinck is a very great man; and in the long run this process of
mutilation has happened to all great men. It was the mark of a great
patriot to be drawn and quartered and his head set on one spike in
one city and his left leg on another spike in another city. It was
the mark of a saint that even these fragments began to work miracles.
So it has been with all the very great men of the world. However
careless, however botchy, may be the version of Maeterlinck or of
anyone else given in such a selection as this, it is assuredly far
less careless and far less botchy than the version, the parody, the
wild misrepresentation of Maeterlinck which future ages will hear and
distant critics be called upon to consider.
No one can feel any reasonable doubt
that we have heard about Christ and Socrates and Buddha and St.
Francis a mere chaos of excerpts, a mere book of quotations. But from
those fragmentary epigrams we can deduce greatness as clearly as we
can deduce Venus from the torso of Venus or Hercules ex pede
Herculem. If we knew nothing else about the Founder of
Christianity, for example, beyond the fact that a religious teacher
lived in a remote country, and in the course of his peregrinations
and proclamations consistently called Himself “the Son of Man,”
we should know by that alone that he was a man of almost immeasurable
greatness. If future ages happened to record nothing else about
Socrates except that he owned his title to be the wisest of men
because he knew that he knew nothing, they would be able to deduce
from that the height and energy of his civilisation, the glory that
was Greece. The credit of such random compilations as that which
“E.S.S.” and Mr. George Allen have just effected is quite
secure. It is the pure, pedantic, literal editions, the complete
works of this author or that author which are forgotten. It is such
books as this that have revolutionised the destiny of the world.
Great things like Christianity or Platonism have never been founded
upon consistent editions; all of them have been founded upon
scrap-books.
The position of Maeterlinck in modern
life is a thing too obvious to be easily determined in words. It is,
perhaps, best expressed by saying that it is the great glorification
of the inside of things at the expense of the outside. There is one
great evil in modern life for which nobody has found even
approximately a tolerable description: I can only invent a word and
call it “remotism.” It is the tendency to think first of
things which, as a matter of fact, lie far away from the actual
centre of human experience. Thus people say, “All our knowledge
of life begins with the amoeba.” It is false; our knowledge of
life begins with ourselves. Thus they say that the British Empire is
glorious, and at the very word Empire they think at once of Australia
and New Zealand, and Canada, and Polar bears, and parrots and
kangaroos, and it never occurs to any one of them to think of the
Surrey Hills. The one real struggle in modern life is the struggle
between the man like Maeterlinck, who sees the inside as the truth,
and the man like Zola, who sees the outside as the truth. A hundred
cases might be given. We may take, for the sake of argument, the case
of what is called falling in love. The sincere realist, the man who
believes in a certain finality in physical science, says, “You
may, if you like, describe this thing as a divine and sacred and
incredible vision; that is your sentimental theory about it. But what
it is, is an animal and sexual instinct designed for certain natural
purposes.” The man on the other side, the idealist, replies,
with quite equal confidence, that this is the very reverse of the
truth. I put it as it has always struck me; he replies, “Not at
all. You may, if you like, describe this thing as an animal and
sexual instinct, designed for certain natural purposes; that is your
philosophical or zoölogical theory about it. What it is, beyond
all doubt of any kind, is a divine and sacred and incredible vision.”
The fact that it is an animal necessity only comes to the
naturalistic philosopher after looking abroad, studying its origins
and results, constructing an explanation of its existence, more or
less natural and conclusive. The fact that it is a spiritual triumph
comes to the first errand boy who happens to feel it. If a lad of
seventeen falls in love and is struck dead by a hansom cab an hour
afterwards, he has known the thing as it is, a spiritual ecstasy; he
has never come to trouble about the thing as it may be, a physical
destiny. If anyone says that falling in love is an animal thing, the
answer is very simple. The only way of testing the matter is to ask
those who are experiencing it, and none of those would admit for a
moment that it was an animal thing.
Maeterlinck’s appearance in
Europe means primarily this subjective intensity; by this the
materialism is not overthrown: materialism is undermined. He brings,
not something which is more poetic than realism, not something which
is more spiritual than realism, not something which is more right
than realism, but something which is more real than realism. He
discovers the one indestructible thing. This material world on which
such vast systems have been superimposed–this may mean
anything. It may be a dream, it may be a joke, it may be a trap or
temptation, it may be a charade, it may be the beatific vision: the
only thing of which we are certain is this human soul. This human
soul finds itself alone in a terrible world, afraid of the grass. It
has brought forth poetry and religion in order to explain matters; it
will bring them forth again. It matters not one atom how often the
lulls of materialism and scepticism occur; they are always broken by
the reappearance of a fanatic. They have come in our time: they have
been broken by Maeterlinck.
RUSKIN
I do not think anyone could find any
fault with the way in which Mr. Collingwood has discharged his task,
except, of course, Mr. Ruskin himself, who would certainly have
scored through all the eulogies in passionate red ink and declared
that his dear friend had selected for admiration the very parts of
his work which were vile, brainless, and revolting. That, however,
was merely Ruskin’s humour, and one of the deepest
disappointments with Mr. Collingwood is that he, like everyone else,
fails to appreciate Ruskin as a humourist. Yet he was a great
humourist: half the explosions which are solemnly scolded as
“one-sided” were simply meant to be one-sided, were mere
laughing experiments in language. Like a woman, he saw the humour of
his own prejudices, did not sophisticate them by logic, but
deliberately exaggerated them by rhetoric. One tenth of his paradoxes
would have made the fortune of a modern young man with gloves of an
art yellow. He was as fond of nonsense as Mr. Max Beerbohm. Only . .
. he was fond of other things too. He did not ask humanity to dine on
pickles.
But while his kaleidoscope of fancy
and epigram gives him some kinship with the present day, he was
essentially of an earlier type: he was the last of the prophets. With
him vanishes the secret of that early Victorian simplicity which gave
a man the courage to mount a pulpit above the head of his fellows.
Many elements, good and bad, have destroyed it; humility as well as
fear, camaraderie as well as scepticism, have bred in us a desire to
give our advice lightly and persuasively, to mask our morality, to
whisper a word and glide away. The contrast was in some degree
typified in the House of Commons under the last leadership of Mr.
Gladstone: the old order with its fist on the box, and the new order
with its feet on the table. Doubtless the wine of that prophecy was
too strong even for the strong heads that carried it. It made Ruskin
capricious and despotic, Tennyson lonely and whimsical, Carlyle harsh
to the point of hatred, and Kingsley often rabid to the ruin of logic
and charity. One alone of that race of giants, the greatest and most
neglected, was sober after the cup. No mission, no frustration could
touch with hysteria the humanity of Robert Browning.
But though Ruskin seems to close the
roll of the militant prophets, we feel how needful are such figures
when we consider with what pathetic eagerness men pay prophetic
honours even to those who disclaim the prophetic character. Ibsen
declares that he only depicts life, that as far as he is concerned
there is nothing to be done, and still armies of “Ibsenites”
rally to the flag and enthusiastically do nothing. I have found
traces of a school which avowedly follows Mr. Henry James: an idea
full of humour. I like to think of a crowd with pikes and torches
shouting passages from “The Awkward Age.” It is right and
proper for a multitude to declare its readiness to follow a prophet
to the end of the world, but if he himself explains, with pathetic
gesticulations, that he is only going for a walk in the park, there
is not much for the multitude to do. But the disciple of Ruskin had
plenty to do. He made roads; in his spare moments he studied the
whole of geology and botany. He lifted up paving stones and got down
into early Florentine cellars, where, by hanging upside down, he
could catch a glimpse of a Cimabue unpraisable but by divine silence.
He rushed from one end of a city to the other comparing ceilings. His
limbs were weary, his clothes were torn, and in his eyes was that
unfathomable joy of life which man will never know again until once
more he takes himself seriously.
Mr. Collingwood’s excellent
chapters on the art criticism of Ruskin would be better, in my
opinion, if they showed more consciousness of the after revolutions
that have reversed, at least in detail, much of Ruskin’s
teaching. We no longer think that art became valueless when it was
first corrupted with anatomical accuracy. But if we return to that
Raphaelism to which he was so unjust, let us not fall into the old
error of intelligent reactionaries, that of ignoring our own debt to
revolutions. Ruskin could not destroy the market of Raphaelism, but
he could and did destroy its monopoly. We may go back to the
Renaissance, but let us remember that we go back free. We can picnic
now in the ruins of our dungeon and deride our deliverer.
But neither in Mr. Collingwood’s
book nor in Ruskin’s own delightful “Præterita”
shall we ever get to the heart of the matter. The work of Ruskin and
his peers remains incomprehensible by the very completeness of their
victory. Fallen forever is that vast brick temple of Utilitarianism,
of which we may find the fragments but never renew the spell. Liberal
Unionists howl in its high places, and in its ruins Mr. Lecky builds
his nest. Its records read with something of the mysterious arrogance
of Chinese: hardly a generation away from us, we read of a race who
believed in the present with the same sort of servile optimism with
which the Oriental believes in the past. It may be that banging his
head against that roof for twenty years did not improve the temper of
the prophet. But he made what he praised in the old Italian
pictures–”an opening into eternity.”
[This
Chapter: “The Life of John Ruskin.” By W.G. Collingwood.
London: Methuen]
QUEEN VICTORIA
Anyone who possesses spiritual or
political courage has made up his mind to a prospect of immutable
mutability; but even in a “transformation” there is
something catastrophic in the removal of the back scene. It is a
truism to say of the wise and noble lady who is gone from us that we
shall always remember her; but there is a subtler and higher
compliment still in confessing that we often forgot her. We forgot
her as we forget the sunshine, as we forget the postulates of an
argument, as we commonly forget our own existence. Mr. Gladstone is
the only figure whose loss prepared us for such earthquakes altering
the landscape. But Mr. Gladstone seemed a fixed and stationary object
in our age for the same reason that one railway train looks
stationary from another; because he and the age of progress were both
travelling at the same impetuous rate of speed. In the end, indeed,
it was probably the age that dropped behind. For a symbol of the
Queen’s position we must rather recur to the image of a stretch
of scenery, in which she was as a mountain so huge and familiar that
its disappearance would make the landscape round our own door seem
like a land of strangers. She had an inspired genius for the
familiarising virtues; her sympathy and sanity made us feel at home
even in an age of revolutions. That indestructible sense of security
which for good and evil is so typical of our nation, that almost
scornful optimism which, in the matter of ourselves, cannot take
peril or even decadence seriously, reached by far its highest and
healthiest form in the sense that we were watched over by one so
thoroughly English in her silence and self-control, in her shrewd
trustfulness and her brilliant inaction. Over and above those sublime
laws of labour and pity by which she ordered her life, there are a
very large number of minor intellectual matters in which we might
learn a lesson from the Queen. There is one especially which is
increasingly needed in an age when moral claims become complicated
and hysterical. That Queen Victoria was a model of political
unselfishness is well known; it is less often remarked that few
modern people have an unselfishness so completely free from
morbidity, so fully capable of deciding a moral question without
exaggerating its importance. No eminent person of our time has been
so utterly devoid of that disease of self-assertion which is often
rampant among the unselfish. She had one most rare and valuable
faculty, the faculty of letting things pass–Acts of Parliament
and other things. Her predecessors, whether honest men or knaves,
were attacked every now and then with a nightmare of despotic
responsibility; they suddenly conceived that it rested with them to
save the world and the Protestant Constitution. Queen Victoria had
far too much faith in the world to try to save it. She knew that Acts
of Parliament, even bad Acts of Parliament, do not destroy nations.
But she knew that ignorance, ill-temper, tyranny, and officiousness
do destroy nations, and not upon any provocation would she set an
example in these things. We fancy that this sense of proportion, this
largeness and coolness of intellectual magnanimity is the one of the
thousand virtues of Queen Victoria of which the near future will
stand most in need. We are gaining many new mental powers, and with
them new mental responsibilities. In psychology, in sociology, above
all in education, we are learning to do a great many clever things.
Unless we are much mistaken the next great task will be to learn not
to do them. If that time comes, assuredly we cannot do better than
turn once more to the memory of the great Queen who for seventy years
followed through every possible tangle and distraction the fairy
thread of common sense.
We are suffering just now from an
outbreak of the imagination which exhibits itself in politics and the
most unlikely places. The German Emperor, for example, is neither a
tyrant nor a lunatic, as used to be absurdly represented; he is
simply a minor poet; and he feels just as any minor poet would feel
if he found himself on the throne of Barbarossa. The revival of
militarism and ecclesiasticism is an invasion of politics by the
artistic sense; it is heraldry rather than chivalry that is lusted
after. Amid all this waving of wands and flaunting of uniforms, all
this hedonistic desire to make the most of everything, there is
something altogether quiet and splendid about the sober disdain with
which this simple and courteous lady in a black dress left idle
beside her the sceptre of a hundred tyrants. The heart of the whole
nation warmed as it had never warmed for centuries at the thought of
having in their midst a woman who cared nothing for her rights, and
nothing for those fantastic duties which are more egotistical than
rights themselves.
The work of the Queen for progressive
politics has surely been greatly underrated. She invented democratic
monarchy as much as James Watt invented the steam engine. William
IV., from whom we think of her as inheriting her Constitutional
position, held in fact a position entirely different to that which
she now hands on to Edward VII. William IV. was a limited monarch;
that is to say, he had a definite, open, and admitted power in
politics, but it was a limited power. Queen Victoria was not a
limited monarch; in the only way in which she cared to be a monarch
at all she was as unlimited as Haroun Alraschid. She had unlimited
willing obedience, and unlimited social supremacy. To her belongs the
credit of inventing a new kind of monarchy; in which the Crown, by
relinquishing the whole of that political and legal department of
life which is concerned with coercion, regimentation, and punishment,
was enabled to rise above it and become the symbol of the sweeter and
purer relations of humanity, the social intercourse which leads and
does not drive. Too much cannot be said for the wise audacity and
confident completeness with which the Queen cut away all those cords
of political supremacy to which her predecessors had clung madly as
the only stays of the monarchy. She had her reward. For while William
IV.’s supremacy may be called a survival, it is not too much to
say that the Queen’s supremacy might be called a prophecy. By
lifting a figure purely human over the heads of judges and warriors,
we uttered in some symbolic fashion the abiding, if unreasoning, hope
which dwells in all human hearts, that some day we may find a simpler
solution of the woes of nations than the summons and the treadmill,
that we may find in some such influence as the social influence of a
woman, what was called in the noble old language of mediæval
monarchy, “a fountain of mercy and a fountain of honour.”
In the universal reverence paid to
the Queen there was hardly anywhere a touch of snobbishness.
Snobbishness, in so far as it went out towards former sovereigns,
went out to them as aristocrats rather than as kings, as heads of
that higher order of men, who were almost angels or demons in their
admitted superiority to common lines of conduct. This kind of
reverence was always a curse: nothing can be conceived as worse for
the mass of the people than that they should think the morality for
which they have to struggle an inferior morality, a thing unfitted
for a haughtier class. But of this patrician element there was hardly
a trace in the dignity of the Queen. Indeed, the degree to which the
middle and lower classes took her troubles and problems to their
hearts was almost grotesque in its familiarity. No one thought of the
Queen as an aristocrat like the Duke of Devonshire, or even as a
member of the governing classes like Mr. Chamberlain. Men thought of
her as something nearer to them even in being further off; as one who
was a good queen, and who would have been, had her fate demanded,
with equal cheerfulness, a good washerwoman. Herein lay her
unexampled triumph, the greatest and perhaps the last triumph of
monarchy. Monarchy in its healthiest days had the same basis as
democracy: the belief in human nature when entrusted with power. A
king was only the first citizen who received the franchise.
Both royalty and religion have been
accused of despising humanity, and in practice it has been too often
true; but after all both the conception of the prophet and that of
the king were formed by paying humanity the supreme compliment of
selecting from it almost at random. This daring idea that a healthy
human being, when thrilled by all the trumpets of a great trust,
would rise to the situation, has often been tested, but never with
such complete success as in the case of our dead Queen. On her was
piled the crushing load of a vast and mystical tradition, and she
stood up straight under it. Heralds proclaimed her as the anointed of
God, and it did not seem presumptuous. Brave men died in thousands
shouting her name, and it did not seem unnatural. No mere intellect,
no mere worldly success could, in this age of bold inquiry, have
sustained that tremendous claim; long ago we should have stricken
Cæsar and dethroned Napoleon. But these glories and these
sacrifices did not seem too much to celebrate a hardworking human
nature; they were possible because at the heart of our Empire was
nothing but a defiant humility. If the Queen had stood for any novel
or fantastic imperial claims, the whole would have seemed a
nightmare; the whole was successful because she stood, and no one
could deny that she stood, for the humblest, the shortest and the
most indestructible of human gospels, that when all troubles and
troublemongers have had their say, our work can be done till sunset,
our life can be lived till death.
THE GERMAN EMPEROR
The list of the really serious, the
really convinced, the really important and comprehensible people now
alive includes, as most Englishmen would now be prepared to admit,
the German Emperor. He is a practical man and a poet. I do not know
whether there are still people in existence who think there is some
kind of faint antithesis between these two characters; but I incline
to think there must be, because of the surprise which the career of
the German Emperor has generally evoked. When he came to the throne
it became at once apparent that he was poetical; people assumed in
consequence that he was unpractical; that he would plunge Europe into
war, that he would try to annex France, that he would say he was the
Emperor of Russia, that he would stand on his head in the Reichstag,
that he would become a pirate on the Spanish Main. Years upon years
have passed; he has gone on making speeches, he has gone on talking
about God and his sword, he has poured out an ever increased rhetoric
and æstheticism. And yet all the time people have slowly and
surely realised that he knows what he is about, that he is one of the
best friends of peace, that his influence on Europe is not only
successful, but in many ways good, that he knows what world he is
living in better than a score of materialists.
The explanation never comes to
them–he is a poet; therefore, a practical man. The affinity of
the two words, merely as words, is much nearer than many people
suppose, for the matter of that. There is one Greek word for “I
do” from which we get the word practical, and another Greek
word for “I do” from which we get the word poet. I was
doubtless once informed of a profound difference between the two, but
I have forgotten it. The two words practical and poetical may mean
two subtly different things in that old and subtle language, but they
mean the same in English and the same in the long run. It is
ridiculous to suppose that the man who can understand the inmost
intricacies of a human being who has never existed at all cannot make
a guess at the conduct of man who lives next door. It is idle to say
that a man who has himself felt the mad longing under the mad moon
for a vagabond life cannot know why his son runs away to sea. It is
idle to say that a man who has himself felt the hunger for any kind
of exhilaration, from angel or devil, cannot know why his butler
takes to drink. It is idle to say that a man who has been fascinated
with the wild fastidiousness of destiny does not know why
stockbrokers gamble, to say that a man who has been knocked into the
middle of eternal life by a face in a crowd does not know why the
poor marry young; that a man who found his path to all things kindly
and pleasant blackened and barred suddenly by the body of a man does
not know what it is to desire murder. It is idle, in short, for a man
who has created men to say that he does not understand them. A man
who is a poet may, of course, easily make mistakes in these personal
and practical relations; such mistakes and similar ones have been
made by poets; such mistakes and greater ones have been made by
soldiers and statesmen and men of business. But in so far as a poet
is in these things less of a practical man he is also less of a poet.
If Shakespeare really married a bad
wife when he had conceived the character of Beatrice he ought to have
been ashamed of himself: he had failed not only in his life, he had
failed in his art. If Balzac got into rows with his publishers he
ought to be rebuked and not commiserated, having evolved so many
consistent business men from his own inside. The German Emperor is a
poet, and therefore he succeeds, because poetry is so much nearer to
reality than all the other human occupations. He is a poet, and
succeeds because the majority of men are poets. It is true, if that
matter is at all important, that the German Emperor is not a good
poet. The majority of men are poets, only they happen to be bad
poets. The German Emperor fails ridiculously, if that is all that is
in question, in almost every one of the artistic occupations to which
he addresses himself: he is neither a first-rate critic, nor a
first-rate musician, nor a first-rate painter, nor a first-rate poet.
He is a twelfth-rate poet, but because he is a poet at all he knocks
to pieces all the first-rate politicians in the war of politics.
Having made clear my position so far,
I discover with a certain amount of interest that I have not yet got
to the subject of these remarks. The German Emperor is a poet, and
although, as far as I know, every line he ever wrote may be nonsense,
he is a poet in this real sense, that he has realised the meaning of
every function he has performed. Why should we jeer at him because he
has a great many uniforms, for instance? The very essence of the
really imaginative man is that he realises the various types or
capacities in which he can appear. Every one of us, or almost every
one of us, does in reality fulfil almost as many offices as Pooh-Bah.
Almost every one of us is a ratepayer, an immortal soul, an
Englishman, a baptised person, a mammal, a minor poet, a juryman, a
married man, a bicyclist, a Christian, a purchaser of newspapers, and
a critic of Mr. Alfred Austin. We ought to have uniforms for all
these things. How beautiful it would be if we appeared to-morrow in
the uniform of a ratepayer, in brown and green, with buttons made in
the shape of coins, and a blue income-tax paper tastefully arranged
as a favour; or, again, if we appeared dressed as immortal souls, in
a blue uniform with stars. It would be very exciting to dress up as
Englishmen, or to go to a fancy dress ball as Christians.
Some of the costumes I have suggested
might appear a little more difficult to carry out. The dress of a
person who purchases newspapers (though it mostly consists of
coloured evening editions arranged in a stiff skirt, like that of a
saltatrice, round the waist of the wearer) has many mysterious
points. The attire of a person prepared to criticise the Poet
Laureate is something so awful and striking that I dare not even
begin to describe it; the one fact which I am willing to reveal, and
to state seriously and responsibly, is that it buttons up behind.
But most assuredly we ought not to
abuse the Kaiser because he is fond of putting on all his uniforms;
he does so because he has a large number of established and
involuntary incarnations. He tries to do his duty in that state of
life to which it shall please God to call him; and it so happens that
he has been called to as many different estates as there are
regiments in the German Army. He is a huntsman and proud of being a
huntsman, an engineer and proud of being an engineer, an infantry
soldier and proud of being so, a light horseman and proud of being
so. There is nothing wrong in all this; the only wrong thing is that
it should be confined to the merely destructive arts of war. The
sight of the German Kaiser in the most magnificent of the uniforms in
which he had led armies to victory is not in itself so splendid or
delightful as that of many other sights which might come before us
without a whisper of the alarms of war. It is not so splendid or
delightful as the sight of an ordinary householder showing himself in
that magnificent uniform of purple and silver which should signalise
the father of three children. It is not so splendid or delightful as
the appearance of a young clerk in an insurance office decorated with
those three long crimson plumes which are the well-known insignia of
a gentleman who is just engaged to be married. Nor can it compare
with the look of a man wearing the magnificent green and silver
armour by which we know one who has induced an acquaintance to give
up getting drunk, or the blue and gold which is only accorded to
persons who have prevented fights in the street. We belong to quite
as many regiments as the German Kaiser. Our regiments are regiments
that are embattled everywhere; they fight an unending fight against
all that is hopeless and rapacious and of evil report. The only
difference is that we have the regiments, but not the uniforms.
Only one obvious point occurs to me
to add. If the Kaiser has more than any other man the sense of the
poetry of the ancient things, the sword, the crown, the ship, the
nation, he has the sense of the poetry of modern things also. He has
one sense, and it is even a joke against him. He feels the poetry of
one thing that is more poetic than sword or crown or ship or nation,
the poetry of the telegram. No one ever sent a telegram who did not
feel like a god. He is a god, for he is a minor poet; a minor poet,
but a poet still.
TENNYSON
Mr. Morton Luce has written a short
study of Tennyson which has considerable cultivation and
suggestiveness, which will be sufficient to serve as a notebook for
Tennyson’s admirers, but scarcely sufficient, perhaps, to serve
as a pamphlet against his opponents. If a critic has, as he ought to
have, any of the functions anciently attributed to a prophet, it
ought not to be difficult for him to prophesy that Tennyson will pass
through a period of facile condemnation and neglect before we arrive
at the true appreciation of his work. The same thing has happened to
the most vigorous of essayists, Macaulay, and the most vigorous of
romancers, Dickens, because we live in a time when mere vigour is
considered a vulgar thing. The same idle and frigid reaction will
almost certainly discredit the stateliness and care of Tennyson, as
it has discredited the recklessness and inventiveness of Dickens. It
is only necessary to remember that no action can be discredited by a
reaction.
The attempts which have been made to
discredit the poetical position of Tennyson are in the main dictated
by an entire misunderstanding of the nature of poetry. When critics
like Matthew Arnold, for example, suggest that his poetry is
deficient in elaborate thought, they only prove, as Matthew Arnold
proved, that they themselves could never be great poets. It is no
valid accusation against a poet that the sentiment he expresses is
commonplace. Poetry is always commonplace; it is vulgar in the
noblest sense of that noble word. Unless a man can make the same kind
of ringing appeal to absolute and admitted sentiments that is made by
a popular orator, he has lost touch with emotional literature. Unless
he is to some extent a demagogue, he cannot be a poet. A man who
expresses in poetry new and strange and undiscovered emotions is not
a poet; he is a brain specialist. Tennyson can never be discredited
before any serious tribunal of criticism because the sentiments and
thoughts to which he dedicates himself are those sentiments and
thoughts which occur to anyone. These are the peculiar province of
poetry; poetry, like religion, is always a democratic thing, even if
it pretends the contrary. The faults of Tennyson, so far as they
existed, were not half so much in the common character of his
sentiments as in the arrogant perfection of his workmanship. He was
not by any means so wrong in his faults as he was in his perfections.
Men are very much too ready to speak
of men’s work being ordinary, when we consider that, properly
considered, every man is extraordinary. The average man is a tribal
fable, like the Man-Wolf or the Wise Man of the Stoics. In every
man’s heart there is a revolution; how much more in every
poet’s? The supreme business of criticism is to discover that
part of a man’s work which is his and to ignore that part which
belongs to others. Why should any critic of poetry spend time and
attention on that part of a man’s work which is unpoetical? Why
should any man be interested in aspects which are uninteresting? The
business of a critic is to discover the importance of men and not
their crimes. It is true that the Greek word critic carries with it
the meaning of a judge, and up to this point of history judges have
had to do with the valuation of men’s sins, and not with the
valuation of their virtues.
Tennyson’s work, disencumbered
of all that uninteresting accretion which he had inherited or copied,
resolves itself, like that of any other man of genius, into those
things which he really inaugurated. Underneath all his exterior of
polished and polite rectitude there was in him a genuine fire of
novelty; only that, like all the able men of his period, he disguised
revolution under the name of evolution. He is only a very shallow
critic who cannot see an eternal rebel in the heart of the
Conservative.
Tennyson had certain absolutely
personal ideas, as much his own as the ideas of Browning or Meredith,
though they were fewer in number. One of these, for example, was the
fact that he was the first of all poets (and perhaps the last) to
attempt to treat poetically that vast and monstrous vision of fact
which science had recently revealed to mankind. Scientific
discoveries seem commonly fables as fantastic in the ears of poets as
poems in the ears of men of science. The poet is always a Ptolemaist;
for him the sun still rises and the earth stands still. Tennyson
really worked the essence of modern science into his poetical
constitution, so that its appalling birds and frightful flowers were
really part of his literary imagery. To him blind and brutal
monsters, the products of the wild babyhood of the Universe, were as
the daisies and the nightingales were to Keats; he absolutely
realised the great literary paradox mentioned in the Book of Job: “He
saw Behemoth, and he played with him as with a bird.”
Instances of this would not be
difficult to find. But the tests of poetry are those instances in
which this outrageous scientific phraseology becomes natural and
unconscious. Tennyson wrote one of his own exquisite lyrics
describing the exultation of a lover on the evening before his bridal
day. This would be an occasion, if ever there was one, for falling
back on those ancient and assured falsehoods of the domed heaven and
the flat earth in which generations of poets have made us feel at
home. We can imagine the poet in such a lyric saluting the setting
sun and prophesying the sun’s resurrection. There is something
extraordinarily typical of Tennyson’s scientific faith in the
fact that this, one of the most sentimental and elemental of his
poems, opens with the two lines:
“Move
eastward, happy earth, and leave Yon orange sunset waning slow.”
Rivers had often been commanded to
flow by poets, and flowers to blossom in their season, and both were
doubtless grateful for the permission. But the terrestrial globe of
science has only twice, so far as we know, been encouraged in poetry
to continue its course, one instance being that of this poem, and the
other the incomparable “Address to the Terrestrial Globe”
in the “Bab Ballads.”
There was, again, another poetic
element entirely peculiar to Tennyson, which his critics have, in
many cases, ridiculously confused with a fault. This was the fact
that Tennyson stood alone among modern poets in the attempt to give a
poetic character to the conception of Liberal Conservatism, of
splendid compromise. The carping critics who have abused Tennyson for
this do not see that it was far more daring and original for a poet
to defend conventionality than to defend a cart-load of revolutions.
His really sound and essential conception of Liberty,
“Turning
to scorn with lips divine The falsehood of extremes,”
is as good a definition of Liberalism
as has been uttered in poetry in the Liberal century. Moderation is
not a compromise; moderation is a passion; the passion of
great judges. That Tennyson felt that lyrical enthusiasm could be
devoted to established customs, to indefensible and ineradicable
national constitutions, to the dignity of time and the empire of
unutterable common sense, all this did not make him a tamer poet, but
an infinitely more original one. Any poetaster can describe a
thunderstorm; it requires a poet to describe the ancient and quiet
sky.
I cannot, indeed, fall in with Mr.
Morton Luce in his somewhat frigid and patrician theory of poetry.
“Dialect,” he says, “mostly falls below the dignity
of art.” I cannot feel myself that art has any dignity higher
than the indwelling and divine dignity of human nature. Great poets
like Burns were far more undignified when they clothed their thoughts
in what Mr. Morton Luce calls “the seemly raiment of cultured
speech” than when they clothed them in the headlong and
flexible patois in which they thought and prayed and quarrelled and
made love. If Tennyson failed (which I do not admit) in such poems as
“The Northern Farmer,” it was not because he used too
much of the spirit of the dialect, but because he used too little.
Tennyson belonged undoubtedly to a
period from which we are divided; the period in which men had queer
ideas of the antagonism of science and religion; the period in which
the Missing Link was really missing. But his hold upon the old
realities of existence never wavered; he was the apostle of the
sanctity of laws, of the sanctity of customs; above all, like every
poet, he was the apostle of the sanctity of words.
ELIZABETH BARRETT BROWNING
The delightful new edition of Mrs.
Browning’s “Casa Guidi Windows” which Mr. John Lane
has just issued ought certainly to serve as an opportunity for the
serious criticism and inevitable admiration to which a great poet is
entitled. For Mrs. Browning was a great poet, and not, as is idly and
vulgarly supposed, only a great poetess. The word poetess is bad
English, and it conveys a particularly bad compliment. Nothing is
more remarkable about Mrs. Browning’s work than the absence of
that trite and namby-pamby elegance which the last two centuries
demanded from lady writers. Wherever her verse is bad it is bad from
some extravagance of imagery, some violence of comparison, some kind
of debauch of cleverness. Her nonsense never arises from weakness,
but from a confusion of powers. If the phrase explain itself, she is
far more a great poet than she is a good one.
Mrs. Browning often appears more
luscious and sentimental than many other literary women, but this was
because she was stronger. It requires a certain amount of internal
force to break down. A complete self-humiliation requires enormous
strength, more strength than most of us possess. When she was writing
the poetry of self-abandonment she really abandoned herself with the
valour and decision of an anchorite abandoning the world. Such a
couplet as:
“Our
Euripides, the human, With his dropping of warm tears,”
gives to most of us a sickly and
nauseous sensation. Nothing can be well conceived more ridiculous
than Euripides going about dropping tears with a loud splash, and
Mrs. Browning coming after him with a thermometer. But the one
emphatic point about this idiotic couplet is that Mrs. Hemans would
never have written it. She would have written something perfectly
dignified, perfectly harmless, perfectly inconsiderable. Mrs.
Browning was in a great and serious difficulty. She really meant
something. She aimed at a vivid and curious image, and she missed it.
She had that catastrophic and public failure which is, as much as a
medal or a testimonial, the badge of the brave.
In spite of the tiresome half-truth
that art is unmoral, the arts require a certain considerable number
of moral qualities, and more especially all the arts require courage.
The art of drawing, for example, requires even a kind of physical
courage. Anyone who has tried to draw a straight line and failed
knows that he fails chiefly in nerve, as he might fail to jump off a
cliff. And similarly all great literary art involves the element of
risk, and the greatest literary artists have commonly been those who
have run the greatest risk of talking nonsense. Almost all great
poets rant, from Shakespeare downwards. Mrs. Browning was Elizabethan
in her luxuriance and her audacity, and the gigantic scale of her
wit. We often feel with her as we feel with Shakespeare, that she
would have done better with half as much talent. The great curse of
the Elizabethans is upon her, that she cannot leave anything alone,
she cannot write a single line without a conceit:
“And
the eyes of the peacock fans Winked at the alien glory,”
she said of the Papal fans in the
presence of the Italian tricolour:
“And
a royal blood sends glances up her princely eye to trouble, And
the shadow of a monarch’s crown is softened in her hair,”
is her description of a beautiful and
aristocratic lady. The notion of peacock feathers winking like so
many London urchins is perhaps one of her rather aggressive and
outrageous figures of speech. The image of a woman’s hair as
the softened shadow of a crown is a singularly vivid and perfect one.
But both have the same quality of intellectual fancy and intellectual
concentration. They are both instances of a sort of ethereal epigram.
This is the great and dominant characteristic of Mrs. Browning, that
she was significant alike in failure and success. Just as every
marriage in the world, good or bad, is a marriage, dramatic,
irrevocable, and big with coming events, so every one of her wild
weddings between alien ideas is an accomplished fact which produces a
certain effect on the imagination, which has for good or evil become
part and parcel of our mental vision forever. She gives the reader
the impression that she never declined a fancy, just as some
gentlemen of the eighteenth century never declined a duel. When she
fell it was always because she missed the foothold, never because she
funked the leap.
“Casa Guidi
Windows” is, in one aspect, a poem very typical of its author.
Mrs. Browning may fairly be called the peculiar poet of Liberalism,
of that great movement of the first half of the nineteenth century
towards the emancipation of men from ancient institutions which had
gradually changed their nature, from the houses of refuge which had
turned into dungeons, and the mystic jewels which remained only as
fetters. It was not what we ordinarily understand by revolt. It had
no hatred in its heart for ancient and essentially human
institutions. It had that deeply conservative belief in the most
ancient of institutions, the average man, which goes by the name of
democracy. It had none of the spirit of modern Imperialism which is
kicking a man because he is down. But, on the other hand, it had none
of the spirit of modern Anarchism and scepticism which is kicking a
man merely because he is up. It was based fundamentally on a belief
in the destiny of humanity, whether that belief took an irreligious
form, as in Swinburne, or a religious form, as in Mrs. Browning. It
had that rooted and natural conviction that the Millennium was coming
to-morrow which has been the conviction of all iconoclasts and
reformers, and for which some rationalists have been absurd enough to
blame the early Christians. But they had none of that disposition to
pin their whole faith to some black-and-white scientific system which
afterwards became the curse of philosophical Radicalism. They were
not like the sociologists who lay down a final rectification of
things, amounting to nothing except an end of the world, a great deal
more depressing than would be the case if it were knocked to pieces
by a comet. Their ideal, like the ideal of all sensible people, was a
chaotic and confused notion of goodness made up of English primroses
and Greek statues, birds singing in April, and regiments being cut to
pieces for a flag. They were neither Radicals nor Socialists, but
Liberals, and a Liberal is a noble and indispensable lunatic who
tries to make a cosmos of his own head.
Mrs. Browning and her husband were
more liberal than most Liberals. Theirs was the hospitality of the
intellect and the hospitality of the heart, which is the best
definition of the term. They never fell into the habit of the idle
revolutionists of supposing that the past was bad because the future
was good, which amounted to asserting that because humanity had never
made anything but mistakes it was now quite certain to be right.
Browning possessed in a greater degree than any other man the power
of realising that all conventions were only victorious revolutions.
He could follow the mediæval logicians in all their sowing of
the wind and reaping of the whirlwind with all that generous ardour
which is due to abstract ideas. He could study the ancients with the
young eyes of the Renaissance and read a Greek grammar like a book of
love lyrics. This immense and almost confounding Liberalism of
Browning doubtless had some effect upon his wife. In her vision of
New Italy she went back to the image of Ancient Italy like an honest
and true revolutionist; for does not the very word “revolution”
mean a rolling backward. All true revolutions are reversions to the
natural and the normal. A revolutionist who breaks with the past is a
notion fit for an idiot. For how could a man even wish for something
which he had never heard of? Mrs. Browning’s inexhaustible
sympathy with all the ancient and essential passions of humanity was
nowhere more in evidence than in her conception of patriotism. For
some dark reason, which it is difficult indeed to fathom, belief in
patriotism in our day is held to mean principally a belief in every
other nation abandoning its patriotic feelings. In the case of no
other passion does this weird contradiction exist. Men whose lives
are mainly based upon friendship sympathise with the friendships of
others. The interest of engaged couples in each other is a proverb,
and like many other proverbs sometimes a nuisance. In patriotism
alone it is considered correct just now to assume that the sentiment
does not exist in other people. It was not so with the great Liberals
of Mrs. Browning’s time. The Brownings had, so to speak, a
disembodied talent for patriotism. They loved England and they loved
Italy; yet they were the very reverse of cosmopolitans. They loved
the two countries as countries, not as arbitrary divisions of the
globe. They had hold of the root and essence of patriotism. They knew
how certain flowers and birds and rivers pass into the mills of the
brain and come out as wars and discoveries, and how some triumphant
adventure or some staggering crime wrought in a remote continent may
bear about it the colour of an Italian city or the soul of a silent
village of Surrey.
ILLUSTRATIONS
Illustration
1
Illustration
2
Illustration
3
Illustration
4
Illustration
5
Illustration
6
Illustration
7
Illustration
8
Illustration
9
Illustration
10
TABLE OF CONTENTS
PUBLISHER II
www.eCatholic2000.com
|