|
The
Defendant
G.
K. Chesterton
1901 by J.M. Dent & Sons, London, UK.
This
work is published for the greater Glory of Jesus Christ through His
most Holy Mother Mary and for the sanctification of the militant
Church and her members.
PUBLISHER
www.eCatholic2000.com
INDEX
TABLE
OF CONTENTS
THE
DEFENDANT
ILLUSTRATIONS
PUBLISHER
II
THE DEFENDANT
IN DEFENCE OF A NEW EDITION
The reissue of a series of essays so
ephemeral and even superfluous may seem at the first glance to
require some excuse; probably the best excuse is that they will have
been completely forgotten, and therefore may be read again with
entirely new sensations. I am not sure, however, that this claim is
so modest as it sounds, for I fancy that Shakespeare and Balzac, if
moved to prayers, might not ask to be remembered, but to be
forgotten, and forgotten thus; for if they were forgotten they would
be everlastingly re-discovered and re-read. It is a monotonous memory
which keeps us in the main from seeing things as splendid as they
are. The ancients were not wrong when they made Lethe the boundary of
a better land; perhaps the only flaw in their system is that a man
who had bathed in the river of forgetfulness would be as likely as
not to climb back upon the bank of the earth and fancy himself in
Elysium.
If, therefore, I am certain that most
sensible people have forgotten the existence of this book–I do
not speak in modesty or in pride–I wish only to state a simple
and somewhat beautiful fact. In one respect the passing of the period
during which a book can be considered current has afflicted me with
some melancholy, for I had intended to write anonymously in some
daily paper a thorough and crushing exposure of the work inspired
mostly by a certain artistic impatience of the too indulgent tone of
the critiques and the manner in which a vast number of my most
monstrous fallacies have passed unchallenged. I will not repeat that
powerful article here, for it cannot be necessary to do anything more
than warn the reader against the perfectly indefensible line of
argument adopted at the end of p. 28. I am also conscious that the
title of the book is, strictly speaking, inaccurate. It is a legal
metaphor, and, speaking legally, a defendant is not an enthusiast for
the character of King John or the domestic virtues of the
prairie-dog. He is one who defends himself, a thing which the present
writer, however poisoned his mind may be with paradox, certainly
never dreamed of attempting.
Criticism upon the book considered as
literature, if it can be so considered, I should, of course, never
dream of discussing–firstly, because it is ridiculous to do so;
and, secondly, because there was, in my opinion, much justice in such
criticism.
But there is one matter on which an
author is generally considered as having a right to explain himself,
since it has nothing to do with capacity or intelligence, and that is
the question of his morals.
I am proud to say that a furious,
uncompromising, and very effective attack was made upon what was
alleged to be the utter immorality of this book by my excellent
friend Mr. C.F.G. Masterman, in the ‘Speaker.’ The
tendency of that criticism was to the effect that I was discouraging
improvement and disguising scandals by my offensive optimism. Quoting
the passage in which I said that ‘diamonds were to be found in
the dust-bin,’ he said: ‘There is no difficulty in
finding good in what humanity rejects. The difficulty is to find it
in what humanity accepts. The diamond is easy enough to find in the
dust-bin. The difficulty is to find it in the drawing-room.’ I
must admit, for my part, without the slightest shame, that I have
found a great many very excellent things in drawing-rooms. For
example, I found Mr. Masterman in a drawing-room. But I merely
mention this purely ethical attack in order to state, in as few
sentences as possible, my difference from the theory of optimism and
progress therein enunciated. At first sight it would seem that the
pessimist encourages improvement. But in reality it is a singular
truth that the era in which pessimism has been cried from the
house-tops is also that in which almost all reform has stagnated and
fallen into decay. The reason of this is not difficult to discover.
No man ever did, and no man ever can, create or desire to make a bad
thing good or an ugly thing beautiful. There must be some germ of
good to be loved, some fragment of beauty to be admired. The mother
washes and decks out the dirty or careless child, but no one can ask
her to wash and deck out a goblin with a heart like hell. No one can
kill the fatted calf for Mephistopheles. The cause which is blocking
all progress today is the subtle scepticism which whispers in a
million ears that things are not good enough to be worth improving.
If the world is good we are revolutionaries, if the world is evil we
must be conservatives. These essays, futile as they are considered as
serious literature, are yet ethically sincere, since they seek to
remind men that things must be loved first and improved afterwards.
G.
K. C.
INTRODUCTION
In certain endless uplands, uplands
like great flats gone dizzy, slopes that seem to contradict the idea
that there is even such a thing as a level, and make us all realize
that we live on a planet with a sloping roof, you will come from time
to time upon whole valleys filled with loose rocks and boulders, so
big as to be like mountains broken loose. The whole might be an
experimental creation shattered and cast away. It is often difficult
to believe that such cosmic refuse can have come together except by
human means. The mildest and most cockney imagination conceives the
place to be the scene of some war of giants. To me it is always
associated with one idea, recurrent and at last instinctive. The
scene was the scene of the stoning of some prehistoric prophet, a
prophet as much more gigantic than after-prophets as the boulders are
more gigantic than the pebbles. He spoke some words–words that
seemed shameful and tremendous–and the world, in terror, buried
him under a wilderness of stones. The place is the monument of an
ancient fear.
If we followed the same mood of
fancy, it would he more difficult to imagine what awful hint or wild
picture of the universe called forth that primal persecution, what
secret of sensational thought lies buried under the brutal stones.
For in our time the blasphemies are threadbare. Pessimism is now
patently, as it always was essentially, more commonplace than piety.
Profanity is now more than an affectation–it is a convention.
The curse against God is Exercise I. in the primer of minor poetry.
It was not, assuredly, for such babyish solemnities that our
imaginary prophet was stoned in the morning of the world. If we weigh
the matter in the faultless scales of imagination, if we see what is
the real trend of humanity, we shall feel it most probable that he
was stoned for saying that the grass was green and that the birds
sang in spring; for the mission of all the prophets from the
beginning has not been so much the pointing out of heavens or hells
as primarily the pointing out of the earth.
Religion has had to provide that
longest and strangest telescope–the telescope through which we
could see the star upon which we dwelt. For the mind and eyes of the
average man this world is as lost as Eden and as sunken as Atlantis.
There runs a strange law through the length of human history–that
men are continually tending to undervalue their environment, to
undervalue their happiness, to undervalue themselves. The great sin
of mankind, the sin typified by the fall of Adam, is the tendency,
not towards pride, but towards this weird and horrible humility.
This is the great fall, the fall by
which the fish forgets the sea, the ox forgets the meadow, the clerk
forgets the city, every man forgets his environment and, in the
fullest and most literal sense, forgets himself. This is the real
fall of Adam, and it is a spiritual fall. It is a strange thing that
many truly spiritual men, such as General Gordon, have actually spent
some hours in speculating upon the precise location of the Garden of
Eden. Most probably we are in Eden still. It is only our eyes that
have changed.
The pessimist is commonly spoken of
as the man in revolt. He is not. Firstly, because it requires some
cheerfulness to continue in revolt, and secondly, because pessimism
appeals to the weaker side of everybody, and the pessimist,
therefore, drives as roaring a trade as the publican. The person who
is really in revolt is the optimist, who generally lives and dies in
a desperate and suicidal effort to persuade all the other people how
good they are. It has been proved a hundred times over that if you
really wish to enrage people and make them angry, even unto death,
the right way to do it is to tell them that they are all the sons of
God. Jesus Christ was crucified, it may be remembered, not because of
anything he said about God, but on a charge of saying that a man
could in three days pull down and rebuild the Temple. Every one of
the great revolutionists, from Isaiah to Shelley, have been
optimists. They have been indignant, not about the badness of
existence, but about the slowness of men in realizing its goodness.
The prophet who is stoned is not a brawler or a marplot. He is simply
a rejected lover. He suffers from an unrequited attachment to things
in general.
It becomes increasingly apparent,
therefore, that the world is in a permanent danger of being
misjudged. That this is no fanciful or mystical idea may be tested by
simple examples. The two absolutely basic words ‘good’
and ‘bad,’ descriptive of two primal and inexplicable
sensations, are not, and never have been, used properly. Things that
are bad are not called good by any people who experience them; but
things that are good are called bad by the universal verdict of
humanity.
Let me explain a little: Certain
things are bad so far as they go, such as pain, and no one, not even
a lunatic, calls a tooth-ache good in itself; but a knife which cuts
clumsily and with difficulty is called a bad knife, which it
certainly is not. It is only not so good as other knives to which men
have grown accustomed. A knife is never bad except on such rare
occasions as that in which it is neatly and scientifically planted in
the middle of one’s back. The coarsest and bluntest knife which
ever broke a pencil into pieces instead of sharpening it is a good
thing in so far as it is a knife. It would have appeared a miracle in
the Stone Age. What we call a bad knife is a good knife not good
enough for us; what we call a bad hat is a good hat not good enough
for us; what we call bad cookery is good cookery not good enough for
us; what we call a bad civilization is a good civilization not good
enough for us. We choose to call the great mass of the history of
mankind bad, not because it is bad, but because we are better. This
is palpably an unfair principle. Ivory may not be so white as snow,
but the whole Arctic continent does not make ivory black.
Now it has appeared to me unfair that
humanity should be engaged perpetually in calling all those things
bad which have been good enough to make other things better, in
everlastingly kicking down the ladder by which it has climbed. It has
appeared to me that progress should be something else besides a
continual parricide; therefore I have investigated the dust-heaps of
humanity, and found a treasure in all of them. I have found that
humanity is not incidentally engaged, but eternally and
systematically engaged, in throwing gold into the gutter and diamonds
into the sea. I have found that every man is disposed to call the
green leaf of the tree a little less green than it is, and the snow
of Christmas a little less white than it is; therefore I have
imagined that the main business of a man, however humble, is defence.
I have conceived that a defendant is chiefly required when worldlings
despise the world–that a counsel for the defence would not have
been out of place in that terrible day when the sun was darkened over
Calvary and Man was rejected of men.
A DEFENCE OF PENNY DREADFULS
One of the strangest examples of the
degree to which ordinary life is undervalued is the example of
popular literature, the vast mass of which we contentedly describe as
vulgar. The boy’s novelette may be ignorant in a literary
sense, which is only like saying that a modern novel is ignorant in
the chemical sense, or the economic sense, or the astronomical sense;
but it is not vulgar intrinsically–it is the actual centre of a
million flaming imaginations.
In former centuries the educated
class ignored the ruck of vulgar literature. They ignored, and
therefore did not, properly speaking, despise it. Simple ignorance
and indifference does not inflate the character with pride. A man
does not walk down the street giving a haughty twirl to his
moustaches at the thought of his superiority to some variety of
deep-sea fishes. The old scholars left the whole under-world of
popular compositions in a similar darkness.
To-day, however, we have reversed
this principle. We do despise vulgar compositions, and we do not
ignore them. We are in some danger of becoming petty in our study of
pettiness; there is a terrible Circean law in the background that if
the soul stoops too ostentatiously to examine anything it never gets
up again. There is no class of vulgar publications about which there
is, to my mind, more utterly ridiculous exaggeration and
misconception than the current boys’ literature of the lowest
stratum. This class of composition has presumably always existed, and
must exist. It has no more claim to be good literature than the daily
conversation of its readers to be fine oratory, or the lodging-houses
and tenements they inhabit to be sublime architecture. But people
must have conversation, they must have houses, and they must have
stories. The simple need for some kind of ideal world in which
fictitious persons play an unhampered part is infinitely deeper and
older than the rules of good art, and much more important. Every one
of us in childhood has constructed such an invisible dramatis
personæ, but it never occurred to our nurses to correct the
composition by careful comparison with Balzac. In the East the
professional story-teller goes from village to village with a small
carpet; and I wish sincerely that anyone had the moral courage to
spread that carpet and sit on it in Ludgate Circus. But it is not
probable that all the tales of the carpet-bearer are little gems of
original artistic workmanship. Literature and fiction are two
entirely different things. Literature is a luxury; fiction is a
necessity. A work of art can hardly be too short, for its climax is
its merit. A story can never be too long, for its conclusion is
merely to be deplored, like the last halfpenny or the last pipelight.
And so, while the increase of the artistic conscience tends in more
ambitious works to brevity and impressionism, voluminous industry
still marks the producer of the true romantic trash. There was no end
to the ballads of Robin Hood; there is no end to the volumes about
Dick Deadshot and the Avenging Nine. These two heroes are
deliberately conceived as immortal.
But instead of basing all discussion
of the problem upon the common-sense recognition of this fact–that
the youth of the lower orders always has had and always must have
formless and endless romantic reading of some kind, and then going on
to make provision for its wholesomeness–we begin, generally
speaking, by fantastic abuse of this reading as a whole and indignant
surprise that the errand-boys under discussion do not read ‘The
Egoist’ and ‘The Master Builder.’ It is the custom,
particularly among magistrates, to attribute half the crimes of the
Metropolis to cheap novelettes. If some grimy urchin runs away with
an apple, the magistrate shrewdly points out that the child’s
knowledge that apples appease hunger is traceable to some curious
literary researches. The boys themselves, when penitent, frequently
accuse the novelettes with great bitterness, which is only to be
expected from young people possessed of no little native humour. If I
had forged a will, and could obtain sympathy by tracing the incident
to the influence of Mr. George Moore’s novels, I should find
the greatest entertainment in the diversion. At any rate, it is
firmly fixed in the minds of most people that gutter-boys, unlike
everybody else in the community, find their principal motives for
conduct in printed books.
Now it is quite clear that this
objection, the objection brought by magistrates, has nothing to do
with literary merit. Bad story writing is not a crime. Mr. Hall Caine
walks the streets openly, and cannot be put in prison for an
anticlimax. The objection rests upon the theory that the tone of the
mass of boys’ novelettes is criminal and degraded, appealing to
low cupidity and low cruelty. This is the magisterial theory, and
this is rubbish.
So far as I have seen them, in
connection with the dirtiest book-stalls in the poorest districts,
the facts are simply these: The whole bewildering mass of vulgar
juvenile literature is concerned with adventures, rambling,
disconnected and endless. It does not express any passion of any
sort, for there is no human character of any sort. It runs eternally
in certain grooves of local and historical type: the medieval knight,
the eighteenth-century duellist, and the modern cowboy, recur with
the same stiff simplicity as the conventional human figures in an
Oriental pattern. I can quite as easily imagine a human being
kindling wild appetites by the contemplation of his Turkey carpet as
by such dehumanized and naked narrative as this.
Among these stories there are a
certain number which deal sympathetically with the adventures of
robbers, outlaws and pirates, which present in a dignified and
romantic light thieves and murderers like Dick Turpin and Claude
Duval. That is to say, they do precisely the same thing as Scott’s
‘Ivanhoe,’ Scott’s ‘Rob Roy,’ Scott’s
‘Lady of the Lake,’ Byron’s ‘Corsair,’
Wordsworth’s ‘Rob Roy’s Grave,’ Stevenson’s
‘Macaire,’ Mr. Max Pemberton’s ‘Iron Pirate,’
and a thousand more works distributed systematically as prizes and
Christmas presents. Nobody imagines that an admiration of Locksley in
‘Ivanhoe’ will lead a boy to shoot Japanese arrows at the
deer in Richmond Park; no one thinks that the incautious opening of
Wordsworth at the poem on Rob Roy will set him up for life as a
blackmailer. In the case of our own class, we recognise that this
wild life is contemplated with pleasure by the young, not because it
is like their own life, but because it is different from it. It might
at least cross our minds that, for whatever other reason the
errand-boy reads ‘The Red Revenge,’ it really is not
because he is dripping with the gore of his own friends and
relatives.
In this matter, as in all such
matters, we lose our bearings entirely by speaking of the ‘lower
classes’ when we mean humanity minus ourselves. This trivial
romantic literature is not especially plebeian: it is simply human.
The philanthropist can never forget classes and callings. He says,
with a modest swagger, ‘I have invited twenty-five factory
hands to tea.’ If he said ‘I have invited twenty-five
chartered accountants to tea,’ everyone would see the humour of
so simple a classification. But this is what we have done with this
lumberland of foolish writing: we have probed, as if it were some
monstrous new disease, what is, in fact, nothing but the foolish and
valiant heart of man. Ordinary men will always be sentimentalists:
for a sentimentalist is simply a man who has feelings and does not
trouble to invent a new way of expressing them. These common and
current publications have nothing essentially evil about them. They
express the sanguine and heroic truisms on which civilization is
built; for it is clear that unless civilization is built on truisms,
it is not built at all. Clearly, there could be no safety for a
society in which the remark by the Chief Justice that murder was
wrong was regarded as an original and dazzling epigram.
If the authors and publishers of
‘Dick Deadshot,’ and such remarkable works, were suddenly
to make a raid upon the educated class, were to take down the names
of every man, however distinguished, who was caught at a University
Extension Lecture, were to confiscate all our novels and warn us all
to correct our lives, we should be seriously annoyed. Yet they have
far more right to do so than we; for they, with all their idiotcy,
are normal and we are abnormal. It is the modern literature of the
educated, not of the uneducated, which is avowedly and aggressively
criminal. Books recommending profligacy and pessimism, at which the
high-souled errand-boy would shudder, lie upon all our drawing-room
tables. If the dirtiest old owner of the dirtiest old bookstall in
Whitechapel dared to display works really recommending polygamy or
suicide, his stock would be seized by the police. These things are
our luxuries. And with a hypocrisy so ludicrous as to be almost
unparalleled in history, we rate the gutter-boys for their immorality
at the very time that we are discussing (with equivocal German
Professors) whether morality is valid at all. At the very instant
that we curse the Penny Dreadful for encouraging thefts upon
property, we canvass the proposition that all property is theft. At
the very instant we accuse it (quite unjustly) of lubricity and
indecency, we are cheerfully reading philosophies which glory in
lubricity and indecency. At the very instant that we charge it with
encouraging the young to destroy life, we are placidly discussing
whether life is worth preserving.
But it is we who are the morbid
exceptions; it is we who are the criminal class. This should be our
great comfort. The vast mass of humanity, with their vast mass of
idle books and idle words, have never doubted and never will doubt
that courage is splendid, that fidelity is noble, that distressed
ladies should be rescued, and vanquished enemies spared. There are a
large number of cultivated persons who doubt these maxims of daily
life, just as there are a large number of persons who believe they
are the Prince of Wales; and I am told that both classes of people
are entertaining conversationalists. But the average man or boy
writes daily in these great gaudy diaries of his soul, which we call
Penny Dreadfuls, a plainer and better gospel than any of those
iridescent ethical paradoxes that the fashionable change as often as
their bonnets. It may be a very limited aim in morality to shoot a
‘many-faced and fickle traitor,’ but at least it is a
better aim than to be a many-faced and fickle traitor, which is a
simple summary of a good many modern systems from Mr. d’Annunzio’s
downwards. So long as the coarse and thin texture of mere current
popular romance is not touched by a paltry culture it will never be
vitally immoral. It is always on the side of life. The poor–the
slaves who really stoop under the burden of life–have often
been mad, scatter-brained and cruel, but never hopeless. That is a
class privilege, like cigars. Their drivelling literature will always
be a ‘blood and thunder’ literature, as simple as the
thunder of heaven and the blood of men.
A DEFENCE OF RASH VOWS
If a prosperous modern man, with a
high hat and a frock-coat, were to solemnly pledge himself before all
his clerks and friends to count the leaves on every third tree in
Holland Walk, to hop up to the City on one leg every Thursday, to
repeat the whole of Mill’s ‘Liberty’ seventy-six
times, to collect 300 dandelions in fields belonging to anyone of the
name of Brown, to remain for thirty-one hours holding his left ear in
his right hand, to sing the names of all his aunts in order of age on
the top of an omnibus, or make any such unusual undertaking, we
should immediately conclude that the man was mad, or, as it is
sometimes expressed, was ‘an artist in life.’ Yet these
vows are not more extraordinary than the vows which in the Middle
Ages and in similar periods were made, not by fanatics merely, but by
the greatest figures in civic and national civilization–by
kings, judges, poets, and priests. One man swore to chain two
mountains together, and the great chain hung there, it was said, for
ages as a monument of that mystical folly. Another swore that he
would find his way to Jerusalem with a patch over his eyes, and died
looking for it. It is not easy to see that these two exploits, judged
from a strictly rational standpoint, are any saner than the acts
above suggested. A mountain is commonly a stationary and reliable
object which it is not necessary to chain up at night like a dog. And
it is not easy at first sight to see that a man pays a very high
compliment to the Holy City by setting out for it under conditions
which render it to the last degree improbable that he will ever get
there.
But about this there is one striking
thing to be noticed. If men behaved in that way in our time, we
should, as we have said, regard them as symbols of the ‘decadence.’
But the men who did these things were not decadent; they belonged
generally to the most robust classes of what is generally regarded as
a robust age. Again, it will be urged that if men essentially sane
performed such insanities, it was under the capricious direction of a
superstitious religious system. This, again, will not hold water; for
in the purely terrestrial and even sensual departments of life, such
as love and lust, the medieval princes show the same mad promises and
performances, the same misshapen imagination and the same monstrous
self-sacrifice. Here we have a contradiction, to explain which it is
necessary to think of the whole nature of vows from the beginning.
And if we consider seriously and correctly the nature of vows, we
shall, unless I am much mistaken, come to the conclusion that it is
perfectly sane, and even sensible, to swear to chain mountains
together, and that, if insanity is involved at all, it is a little
insane not to do so.
The man who makes a vow makes an
appointment with himself at some distant time or place. The danger of
it is that himself should not keep the appointment. And in modern
times this terror of one’s self, of the weakness and mutability
of one’s self, has perilously increased, and is the real basis
of the objection to vows of any kind. A modern man refrains from
swearing to count the leaves on every third tree in Holland Walk, not
because it is silly to do so (he does many sillier things), but
because he has a profound conviction that before he had got to the
three hundred and seventy-ninth leaf on the first tree he would be
excessively tired of the subject and want to go home to tea. In other
words, we fear that by that time he will be, in the common but
hideously significant phrase, another man. Now, it is this
horrible fairy tale of a man constantly changing into other men that
is the soul of the Decadence. That John Paterson should, with
apparent calm, look forward to being a certain General Barker on
Monday, Dr. Macgregor on Tuesday, Sir Walter Carstairs on Wednesday,
and Sam Slugg on Thursday, may seem a nightmare; but to that
nightmare we give the name of modern culture. One great decadent, who
is now dead, published a poem some time ago, in which he powerfully
summed up the whole spirit of the movement by declaring that he could
stand in the prison yard and entirely comprehend the feelings of a
man about to be hanged:
‘For
he that lives more lives than one More deaths than one must die.’
And the end of all this is that
maddening horror of unreality which descends upon the decadents, and
compared with which physical pain itself would have the freshness of
a youthful thing. The one hell which imagination must conceive as
most hellish is to be eternally acting a play without even the
narrowest and dirtiest greenroom in which to be human. And this is
the condition of the decadent, of the aesthete, of the free-lover. To
be everlastingly passing through dangers which we know cannot scathe
us, to be taking oaths which we know cannot bind us, to be defying
enemies who we know cannot conquer us–this is the grinning
tyranny of decadence which is called freedom.
Let us turn, on the other hand, to
the maker of vows. The man who made a vow, however wild, gave a
healthy and natural expression to the greatness of a great moment. He
vowed, for example, to chain two mountains together, perhaps a symbol
of some great relief, or love, or aspiration. Short as the moment of
his resolve might be, it was, like all great moments, a moment of
immortality, and the desire to say of it exegi monumentum oere
perennius was the only sentiment that would satisfy his mind. The
modern aesthetic man would, of course, easily see the emotional
opportunity; he would vow to chain two mountains together. But, then,
he would quite as cheerfully vow to chain the earth to the moon. And
the withering consciousness that he did not mean what he said, that
he was, in truth, saying nothing of any great import, would take from
him exactly that sense of daring actuality which is the excitement of
a vow. For what could be more maddening than an existence in which
our mother or aunt received the information that we were going to
assassinate the King or build a temple on Ben Nevis with the genial
composure of custom?
The revolt against vows has been
carried in our day even to the extent of a revolt against the typical
vow of marriage. It is most amusing to listen to the opponents of
marriage on this subject. They appear to imagine that the ideal of
constancy was a yoke mysteriously imposed on mankind by the devil,
instead of being, as it is, a yoke consistently imposed by all lovers
on themselves. They have invented a phrase, a phrase that is a black
and white contradiction in two words–’free-love’–as
if a lover ever had been, or ever could be, free. It is the nature of
love to bind itself, and the institution of marriage merely paid the
average man the compliment of taking him at his word. Modern sages
offer to the lover, with an ill-flavoured grin, the largest liberties
and the fullest irresponsibility; but they do not respect him as the
old Church respected him; they do not write his oath upon the
heavens, as the record of his highest moment. They give him every
liberty except the liberty to sell his liberty, which is the only one
that he wants.
In Mr. Bernard Shaw’s brilliant
play ‘The Philanderer,’ we have a vivid picture of this
state of things. Charteris is a man perpetually endeavouring to be a
free-lover, which is like endeavouring to be a married bachelor or a
white negro. He is wandering in a hungry search for a certain
exhilaration which he can only have when he has the courage to cease
from wandering. Men knew better than this in old times–in the
time, for example, of Shakespeare’s heroes. When Shakespeare’s
men are really celibate they praise the undoubted advantages of
celibacy, liberty, irresponsibility, a chance of continual change.
But they were not such fools as to continue to talk of liberty when
they were in such a condition that they could be made happy or
miserable by the moving of someone else’s eyebrow. Suckling
classes love with debt in his praise of freedom.
‘And
he that’s fairly out of both Of all the world is blest. He
lives as in the golden age, When all things made were common; He
takes his pipe, he takes his glass, He fears no man or woman.’
This is a perfectly possible,
rational and manly position. But what have lovers to do with
ridiculous affectations of fearing no man or woman? They know that in
the turning of a hand the whole cosmic engine to the remotest star
may become an instrument of music or an instrument of torture. They
hear a song older than Suckling’s, that has survived a hundred
philosophies. ‘Who is this that looketh out of the window, fair
as the sun, clear as the moon, terrible as an army with banners?’
As we have said, it is exactly this
backdoor, this sense of having a retreat behind us, that is, to our
minds, the sterilizing spirit in modern pleasure. Everywhere there is
the persistent and insane attempt to obtain pleasure without paying
for it. Thus, in politics the modern Jingoes practically say, ‘Let
us have the pleasures of conquerors without the pains of soldiers:
let us sit on sofas and be a hardy race.’ Thus, in religion and
morals, the decadent mystics say: ‘Let us have the fragrance of
sacred purity without the sorrows of self-restraint; let us sing
hymns alternately to the Virgin and Priapus.’ Thus in love the
free-lovers say: ‘Let us have the splendour of offering
ourselves without the peril of committing ourselves; let us see
whether one cannot commit suicide an unlimited number of times.’
Emphatically it will not work. There
are thrilling moments, doubtless, for the spectator, the amateur, and
the aesthete; but there is one thrill that is known only to the
soldier who fights for his own flag, to the ascetic who starves
himself for his own illumination, to the lover who makes finally his
own choice. And it is this transfiguring self-discipline that makes
the vow a truly sane thing. It must have satisfied even the giant
hunger of the soul of a lover or a poet to know that in consequence
of some one instant of decision that strange chain would hang for
centuries in the Alps among the silences of stars and snows. All
around us is the city of small sins, abounding in backways and
retreats, but surely, sooner or later, the towering flame will rise
from the harbour announcing that the reign of the cowards is over and
a man is burning his ships.
A DEFENCE OF SKELETONS
Some little time ago I stood among
immemorial English trees that seemed to take hold upon the stars like
a brood of Ygdrasils. As I walked among these living pillars I became
gradually aware that the rustics who lived and died in their shadow
adopted a very curious conversational tone. They seemed to be
constantly apologizing for the trees, as if they were a very poor
show. After elaborate investigation, I discovered that their gloomy
and penitent tone was traceable to the fact that it was winter and
all the trees were bare. I assured them that I did not resent the
fact that it was winter, that I knew the thing had happened before,
and that no forethought on their part could have averted this blow of
destiny. But I could not in any way reconcile them to the fact that
it was winter. There was evidently a general feeling that I
had caught the trees in a kind of disgraceful deshabille, and that
they ought not to be seen until, like the first human sinners, they
had covered themselves with leaves. So it is quite clear that, while
very few people appear to know anything of how trees look in winter,
the actual foresters know less than anyone. So far from the line of
the tree when it is bare appearing harsh and severe, it is
luxuriantly indefinable to an unusual degree; the fringe of the
forest melts away like a vignette. The tops of two or three high
trees when they are leafless are so soft that they seem like the
gigantic brooms of that fabulous lady who was sweeping the cobwebs
off the sky. The outline of a leafy forest is in comparison hard,
gross and blotchy; the clouds of night do not more certainly obscure
the moon than those green and monstrous clouds obscure the tree; the
actual sight of the little wood, with its gray and silver sea of
life, is entirely a winter vision. So dim and delicate is the heart
of the winter woods, a kind of glittering gloaming, that a figure
stepping towards us in the chequered twilight seems as if he were
breaking through unfathomable depths of spiders’ webs.
But surely the idea that its leaves
are the chief grace of a tree is a vulgar one, on a par with the idea
that his hair is the chief grace of a pianist. When winter, that
healthy ascetic, carries his gigantic razor over hill and valley, and
shaves all the trees like monks, we feel surely that they are all the
more like trees if they are shorn, just as so many painters and
musicians would be all the more like men if they were less like mops.
But it does appear to be a deep and essential difficulty that men
have an abiding terror of their own structure, or of the structure of
things they love. This is felt dimly in the skeleton of the tree: it
is felt profoundly in the skeleton of the man.
The importance of the human skeleton
is very great, and the horror with which it is commonly regarded is
somewhat mysterious. Without claiming for the human skeleton a wholly
conventional beauty, we may assert that he is certainly not uglier
than a bull-dog, whose popularity never wanes, and that he has a
vastly more cheerful and ingratiating expression. But just as man is
mysteriously ashamed of the skeletons of the trees in winter, so he
is mysteriously ashamed of the skeleton of himself in death. It is a
singular thing altogether, this horror of the architecture of things.
One would think it would be most unwise in a man to be afraid of a
skeleton, since Nature has set curious and quite insuperable
obstacles to his running away from it.
One ground exists for this terror: a
strange idea has infected humanity that the skeleton is typical of
death. A man might as well say that a factory chimney was typical of
bankruptcy. The factory may be left naked after ruin, the skeleton
may be left naked after bodily dissolution; but both of them have had
a lively and workmanlike life of their own, all the pulleys creaking,
all the wheels turning, in the House of Livelihood as in the House of
Life. There is no reason why this creature (new, as I fancy, to art),
the living skeleton, should not become the essential symbol of life.
The truth is that man’s horror
of the skeleton is not horror of death at all. It is man’s
eccentric glory that he has not, generally speaking, any objection to
being dead, but has a very serious objection to being undignified.
And the fundamental matter which troubles him in the skeleton is the
reminder that the ground-plan of his appearance is shamelessly
grotesque. I do not know why he should object to this. He contentedly
takes his place in a world that does not pretend to be genteel–a
laughing, working, jeering world. He sees millions of animals
carrying, with quite a dandified levity, the most monstrous shapes
and appendages, the most preposterous horns, wings, and legs, when
they are necessary to utility. He sees the good temper of the frog,
the unaccountable happiness of the hippopotamus. He sees a whole
universe which is ridiculous, from the animalcule, with a head too
big for its body, up to the comet, with a tail too big for its head.
But when it comes to the delightful oddity of his own inside, his
sense of humour rather abruptly deserts him.
In the Middle Ages and in the
Renaissance (which was, in certain times and respects, a much
gloomier period) this idea of the skeleton had a vast influence in
freezing the pride out of all earthly pomps and the fragrance out of
all fleeting pleasures. But it was not, surely, the mere dread of
death that did this, for these were ages in which men went to meet
death singing; it was the idea of the degradation of man in the
grinning ugliness of his structure that withered the juvenile
insolence of beauty and pride. And in this it almost assuredly did
more good than harm. There is nothing so cold or so pitiless as
youth, and youth in aristocratic stations and ages tended to an
impeccable dignity, an endless summer of success which needed to be
very sharply reminded of the scorn of the stars. It was well that
such flamboyant prigs should be convinced that one practical joke, at
least, would bowl them over, that they would fall into one grinning
man-trap, and not rise again. That the whole structure of their
existence was as wholesomely ridiculous as that of a pig or a parrot
they could not be expected to realize; that birth was humorous,
coming of age humorous, drinking and fighting humorous, they were far
too young and solemn to know. But at least they were taught that
death was humorous.
There is a peculiar idea abroad that
the value and fascination of what we call Nature lie in her beauty.
But the fact that Nature is beautiful in the sense that a dado or a
Liberty curtain is beautiful, is only one of her charms, and almost
an accidental one. The highest and most valuable quality in Nature is
not her beauty, but her generous and defiant ugliness. A hundred
instances might be taken. The croaking noise of the rooks is, in
itself, as hideous as the whole hell of sounds in a London railway
tunnel. Yet it uplifts us like a trumpet with its coarse kindliness
and honesty, and the lover in ‘Maud’ could actually
persuade himself that this abominable noise resembled his lady-love’s
name. Has the poet, for whom Nature means only roses and lilies, ever
heard a pig grunting? It is a noise that does a man good–a
strong, snorting, imprisoned noise, breaking its way out of
unfathomable dungeons through every possible outlet and organ. It
might be the voice of the earth itself, snoring in its mighty sleep.
This is the deepest, the oldest, the most wholesome and religious
sense of the value of Nature–the value which comes from her
immense babyishness. She is as top-heavy, as grotesque, as solemn and
as happy as a child. The mood does come when we see all her shapes
like shapes that a baby scrawls upon a slate–simple,
rudimentary, a million years older and stronger than the whole
disease that is called Art. The objects of earth and heaven seem to
combine into a nursery tale, and our relation to things seems for a
moment so simple that a dancing lunatic would be needed to do justice
to its lucidity and levity. The tree above my head is flapping like
some gigantic bird standing on one leg; the moon is like the eye of a
Cyclops. And, however much my face clouds with sombre vanity, or
vulgar vengeance, or contemptible contempt, the bones of my skull
beneath it are laughing for ever.
A DEFENCE OF PUBLICITY
It is a very significant fact that
the form of art in which the modern world has certainly not improved
upon the ancient is what may roughly be called the art of the open
air. Public monuments have certainly not improved, nor has the
criticism of them improved, as is evident from the fashion of
condemning such a large number of them as pompous. An interesting
essay might be written on the enormous number of words that are used
as insults when they are really compliments. It is in itself a
singular study in that tendency which, as I have said, is always
making things out worse than they are, and necessitating a systematic
attitude of defence. Thus, for example, some dramatic critics cast
contempt upon a dramatic performance by calling it theatrical, which
simply means that it is suitable to a theatre, and is as much a
compliment as calling a poem poetical. Similarly we speak
disdainfully of a certain kind of work as sentimental, which simply
means possessing the admirable and essential quality of sentiment.
Such phrases are all parts of one peddling and cowardly philosophy,
and remind us of the days when ‘enthusiast’ was a term of
reproach. But of all this vocabulary of unconscious eulogies nothing
is more striking than the word ‘pompous.’
Properly speaking, of course, a
public monument ought to be pompous. Pomp is its very object; it
would be absurd to have columns and pyramids blushing in some coy
nook like violets in the woods of spring. And public monuments have
in this matter a great and much-needed lesson to teach. Valour and
mercy and the great enthusiasms ought to be a great deal more public
than they are at present. We are too fond nowadays of committing the
sin of fear and calling it the virtue of reverence. We have forgotten
the old and wholesome morality of the Book of Proverbs, ‘Wisdom
crieth without; her voice is heard in the streets.’ In Athens
and Florence her voice was heard in the streets. They had an outdoor
life of war and argument, and they had what modern commercial
civilization has never had–an outdoor art. Religious services,
the most sacred of all things, have always been held publicly; it is
entirely a new and debased notion that sanctity is the same as
secrecy. A great many modern poets, with the most abstruse and
delicate sensibilities, love darkness, when all is said and done,
much for the same reason that thieves love it. The mission of a great
spire or statue should be to strike the spirit with a sudden sense of
pride as with a thunderbolt. It should lift us with it into the empty
and ennobling air. Along the base of every noble monument, whatever
else may be written there, runs in invisible letters the lines of
Swinburne:
‘This
thing is God: To be man with thy might, To go straight in the
strength of thy spirit, and live out thy life in the light.’
If a public monument does not meet
this first supreme and obvious need, that it should be public and
monumental, it fails from the outset.
There has arisen lately a school of
realistic sculpture, which may perhaps be better described as a
school of sketchy sculpture. Such a movement was right and inevitable
as a reaction from the mean and dingy pomposity of English Victorian
statuary. Perhaps the most hideous and depressing object in the
universe–far more hideous and depressing than one of Mr. H.G.
Wells’s shapeless monsters of the slime (and not at all unlike
them)–is the statue of an English philanthropist. Almost as
bad, though, of course, not quite as bad, are the statues of English
politicians in Parliament Fields. Each of them is cased in a
cylindrical frock-coat, and each carries either a scroll or a
dubious-looking garment over the arm that might be either a
bathing-towel or a light great-coat. Each of them is in an oratorical
attitude, which has all the disadvantage of being affected without
even any of the advantages of being theatrical. Let no one suppose
that such abortions arise merely from technical demerit. In every
line of those leaden dolls is expressed the fact that they were not
set up with any heat of natural enthusiasm for beauty or dignity.
They were set up mechanically, because it would seem indecorous or
stingy if they were not set up. They were even set up sulkily, in a
utilitarian age which was haunted by the thought that there were a
great many more sensible ways of spending money. So long as this is
the dominant national sentiment, the land is barren, statues and
churches will not grow–for they have to grow, as much as trees
and flowers. But this moral disadvantage which lay so heavily upon
the early Victorian sculpture lies in a modified degree upon that
rough, picturesque, commonplace sculpture which has begun to arise,
and of which the statue of Darwin in the South Kensington Museum and
the statue of Gordon in Trafalgar Square are admirable examples. It
is not enough for a popular monument to be artistic, like a black
charcoal sketch; it must be striking; it must be in the highest sense
of the word sensational; it must stand for humanity; it must speak
for us to the stars; it must declare in the face of all the heavens
that when the longest and blackest catalogue has been made of all our
crimes and follies there are some things of which we men are not
ashamed.
The two modes of commemorating a
public man are a statue and a biography. They are alike in certain
respects, as, for example, in the fact that neither of them resembles
the original, and that both of them commonly tone down not only all a
man’s vices, but all the more amusing of his virtues. But they
are treated in one respect differently. We never hear anything about
biography without hearing something about the sanctity of private
life and the necessity for suppressing the whole of the most
important part of a man’s existence. The sculptor does not work
at this disadvantage. The sculptor does not leave out the nose of an
eminent philanthropist because it is too beautiful to be given to the
public; he does not depict a statesman with a sack over his head
because his smile was too sweet to be endurable in the light of day.
But in biography the thesis is popularly and solidly maintained, so
that it requires some courage even to hint a doubt of it, that the
better a man was, the more truly human life he led, the less should
be said about it.
For this idea, this modern idea that
sanctity is identical with secrecy, there is one thing at least to be
said. It is for all practical purposes an entirely new idea; it was
unknown to all the ages in which the idea of sanctity really
flourished. The record of the great spiritual movements of mankind is
dead against the idea that spirituality is a private matter. The most
awful secret of every man’s soul, its most lonely and
individual need, its most primal and psychological relationship, the
thing called worship, the communication between the soul and the last
reality–this most private matter is the most public spectacle
in the world. Anyone who chooses to walk into a large church on
Sunday morning may see a hundred men each alone with his Maker. He
stands, in truth, in the presence of one of the strangest spectacles
in the world–a mob of hermits. And in thus definitely espousing
publicity by making public the most internal mystery, Christianity
acts in accordance with its earliest origins and its terrible
beginning. It was surely by no accident that the spectacle which
darkened the sun at noonday was set upon a hill. The martyrdoms of
the early Christians were public not only by the caprice of the
oppressor, but by the whole desire and conception of the victims.
The mere grammatical meaning of the
word ‘martyr’ breaks into pieces at a blow the whole
notion of the privacy of goodness. The Christian martyrdoms were more
than demonstrations: they were advertisements. In our day the new
theory of spiritual delicacy would desire to alter all this. It would
permit Christ to be crucified if it was necessary to His Divine
nature, but it would ask in the name of good taste why He could not
be crucified in a private room. It would declare that the act of a
martyr in being torn in pieces by lions was vulgar and sensational,
though, of course, it would have no objection to being torn in pieces
by a lion in one’s own parlour before a circle of really
intimate friends.
It is, I am inclined to think, a
decadent and diseased purity which has inaugurated this notion that
the sacred object must be hidden. The stars have never lost their
sanctity, and they are more shameless and naked and numerous than
advertisements of Pears’ soap. It would be a strange world
indeed if Nature was suddenly stricken with this ethereal shame, if
the trees grew with their roots in the air and their load of leaves
and blossoms underground, if the flowers closed at dawn and opened at
sunset, if the sunflower turned towards the darkness, and the birds
flew, like bats, by night.
A DEFENCE OF NONSENSE
There are two equal and eternal ways
of looking at this twilight world of ours: we may see it as the
twilight of evening or the twilight of morning; we may think of
anything, down to a fallen acorn, as a descendant or as an ancestor.
There are times when we are almost crushed, not so much with the load
of the evil as with the load of the goodness of humanity, when we
feel that we are nothing but the inheritors of a humiliating
splendour. But there are other times when everything seems primitive,
when the ancient stars are only sparks blown from a boy’s
bonfire, when the whole earth seems so young and experimental that
even the white hair of the aged, in the fine biblical phrase, is like
almond-trees that blossom, like the white hawthorn grown in May. That
it is good for a man to realize that he is ‘the heir of all the
ages’ is pretty commonly admitted; it is a less popular but
equally important point that it is good for him sometimes to realize
that he is not only an ancestor, but an ancestor of primal antiquity;
it is good for him to wonder whether he is not a hero, and to
experience ennobling doubts as to whether he is not a solar myth.
The matters which most thoroughly
evoke this sense of the abiding childhood of the world are those
which are really fresh, abrupt and inventive in any age; and if we
were asked what was the best proof of this adventurous youth in the
nineteenth century we should say, with all respect to its portentous
sciences and philosophies, that it was to be found in the rhymes of
Mr. Edward Lear and in the literature of nonsense. ‘The Dong
with the Luminous Nose,’ at least, is original, as the first
ship and the first plough were original.
It is true in a certain sense that
some of the greatest writers the world has seen–Aristophanes,
Rabelais and Sterne–have written nonsense; but unless we are
mistaken, it is in a widely different sense. The nonsense of these
men was satiric–that is to say, symbolic; it was a kind of
exuberant capering round a discovered truth. There is all the
difference in the world between the instinct of satire, which, seeing
in the Kaiser’s moustaches something typical of him, draws them
continually larger and larger; and the instinct of nonsense which,
for no reason whatever, imagines what those moustaches would look
like on the present Archbishop of Canterbury if he grew them in a fit
of absence of mind. We incline to think that no age except our own
could have understood that the Quangle-Wangle meant absolutely
nothing, and the Lands of the Jumblies were absolutely nowhere. We
fancy that if the account of the knave’s trial in ‘Alice
in Wonderland’ had been published in the seventeenth century it
would have been bracketed with Bunyan’s ‘Trial of
Faithful’ as a parody on the State prosecutions of the time. We
fancy that if ‘The Dong with the Luminous Nose’ had
appeared in the same period everyone would have called it a dull
satire on Oliver Cromwell.
It is altogether advisedly that we
quote chiefly from Mr. Lear’s ‘Nonsense Rhymes.’ To
our mind he is both chronologically and essentially the father of
nonsense; we think him superior to Lewis Carroll. In one sense,
indeed, Lewis Carroll has a great advantage. We know what Lewis
Carroll was in daily life: he was a singularly serious and
conventional don, universally respected, but very much of a pedant
and something of a Philistine. Thus his strange double life in earth
and in dreamland emphasizes the idea that lies at the back of
nonsense–the idea of escape, of escape into a world
where things are not fixed horribly in an eternal appropriateness,
where apples grow on pear-trees, and any odd man you meet may have
three legs. Lewis Carroll, living one life in which he would have
thundered morally against any one who walked on the wrong plot of
grass, and another life in which he would cheerfully call the sun
green and the moon blue, was, by his very divided nature, his one
foot on both worlds, a perfect type of the position of modern
nonsense. His Wonderland is a country populated by insane
mathematicians. We feel the whole is an escape into a world of
masquerade; we feel that if we could pierce their disguises, we might
discover that Humpty Dumpty and the March Hare were Professors and
Doctors of Divinity enjoying a mental holiday. This sense of escape
is certainly less emphatic in Edward Lear, because of the
completeness of his citizenship in the world of unreason. We do not
know his prosaic biography as we know Lewis Carroll’s. We
accept him as a purely fabulous figure, on his own description of
himself:
‘His
body is perfectly spherical, He weareth a runcible hat.’
While Lewis Carroll’s
Wonderland is purely intellectual, Lear introduces quite another
element–the element of the poetical and even emotional. Carroll
works by the pure reason, but this is not so strong a contrast; for,
after all, mankind in the main has always regarded reason as a bit of
a joke. Lear introduces his unmeaning words and his amorphous
creatures not with the pomp of reason, but with the romantic prelude
of rich hues and haunting rhythms.
‘Far
and few, far and few, Are the lands where the Jumblies live,’
is an entirely different type of
poetry to that exhibited in ‘Jabberwocky.’ Carroll, with
a sense of mathematical neatness, makes his whole poem a mosaic of
new and mysterious words. But Edward Lear, with more subtle and
placid effrontery, is always introducing scraps of his own elvish
dialect into the middle of simple and rational statements, until we
are almost stunned into admitting that we know what they mean. There
is a genial ring of commonsense about such lines as,
‘For
his aunt Jobiska said “Every one knows That a Pobble is
better without his toes,”‘
which is beyond the reach of Carroll.
The poet seems so easy on the matter that we are almost driven to
pretend that we see his meaning, that we know the peculiar
difficulties of a Pobble, that we are as old travellers in the
‘Gromboolian Plain’ as he is.
Our claim that nonsense is a new
literature (we might almost say a new sense) would be quite
indefensible if nonsense were nothing more than a mere aesthetic
fancy. Nothing sublimely artistic has ever arisen out of mere art,
any more than anything essentially reasonable has ever arisen out of
the pure reason. There must always be a rich moral soil for any great
aesthetic growth. The principle of art for art’s sake is
a very good principle if it means that there is a vital distinction
between the earth and the tree that has its roots in the earth; but
it is a very bad principle if it means that the tree could grow just
as well with its roots in the air. Every great literature has always
been allegorical–allegorical of some view of the whole
universe. The ‘Iliad’ is only great because all life is a
battle, the ‘Odyssey’ because all life is a journey, the
Book of Job because all life is a riddle. There is one attitude in
which we think that all existence is summed up in the word ‘ghosts’;
another, and somewhat better one, in which we think it is summed up
in the words ‘A Midsummer Night’s Dream.’ Even the
vulgarest melodrama or detective story can be good if it expresses
something of the delight in sinister possibilities–the healthy
lust for darkness and terror which may come on us any night in
walking down a dark lane. If, therefore, nonsense is really to be the
literature of the future, it must have its own version of the Cosmos
to offer; the world must not only be the tragic, romantic, and
religious, it must be nonsensical also. And here we fancy that
nonsense will, in a very unexpected way, come to the aid of the
spiritual view of things. Religion has for centuries been trying to
make men exult in the ‘wonders’ of creation, but it has
forgotten that a thing cannot be completely wonderful so long as it
remains sensible. So long as we regard a tree as an obvious thing,
naturally and reasonably created for a giraffe to eat, we cannot
properly wonder at it. It is when we consider it as a prodigious wave
of the living soil sprawling up to the skies for no reason in
particular that we take off our hats, to the astonishment of the
park-keeper. Everything has in fact another side to it, like the
moon, the patroness of nonsense. Viewed from that other side, a bird
is a blossom broken loose from its chain of stalk, a man a quadruped
begging on its hind legs, a house a gigantesque hat to cover a man
from the sun, a chair an apparatus of four wooden legs for a cripple
with only two.
This is the side of things which
tends most truly to spiritual wonder. It is significant that in the
greatest religious poem existent, the Book of Job, the argument which
convinces the infidel is not (as has been represented by the merely
rational religionism of the eighteenth century) a picture of the
ordered beneficence of the Creation; but, on the contrary, a picture
of the huge and undecipherable unreason of it. ‘Hast Thou sent
the rain upon the desert where no man is?’ This simple sense of
wonder at the shapes of things, and at their exuberant independence
of our intellectual standards and our trivial definitions, is the
basis of spirituality as it is the basis of nonsense. Nonsense and
faith (strange as the conjunction may seem) are the two supreme
symbolic assertions of the truth that to draw out the soul of things
with a syllogism is as impossible as to draw out Leviathan with a
hook. The well-meaning person who, by merely studying the logical
side of things, has decided that ‘faith is nonsense,’
does not know how truly he speaks; later it may come back to him in
the form that nonsense is faith.
A DEFENCE OF PLANETS
A book has at one time come under my
notice called ‘Terra Firma: the Earth not a Planet.’ The
author was a Mr. D. Wardlaw Scott, and he quoted very seriously the
opinions of a large number of other persons, of whom we have never
heard, but who are evidently very important. Mr. Beach of Southsea,
for example, thinks that the world is flat; and in Southsea perhaps
it is. It is no part of my present intention, however, to follow Mr.
Scott’s arguments in detail. On the lines of such arguments it
may be shown that the earth is flat, and, for the matter of that,
that it is triangular. A few examples will suffice:
One of Mr. Scott’s objections
was that if a projectile is fired from a moving body there is a
difference in the distance to which it carries according to the
direction in which it is sent. But as in practice there is not the
slightest difference whichever way the thing is done, in the case of
the earth ‘we have a forcible overthrow of all fancies relative
to the motion of the earth, and a striking proof that the earth is
not a globe.’
This is altogether one of the
quaintest arguments we have ever seen. It never seems to occur to the
author, among other things, that when the firing and falling of the
shot all take place upon the moving body, there is nothing whatever
to compare them with. As a matter of fact, of course, a shot fired at
an elephant does actually often travel towards the marksman, but much
slower than the marksman travels. Mr. Scott probably would not like
to contemplate the fact that the elephant, properly speaking, swings
round and hits the bullet. To us it appears full of a rich cosmic
humour.
I will only give one other example of
the astronomical proofs:
‘If the
earth were a globe, the distance round the surface, say, at 45
degrees south latitude, could not possibly be any greater than the
same latitude north; but since it is found by navigators to be twice
the distance–to say the least of it–or double the
distance it ought to be according to the globular theory, it is a
proof that the earth is not a globe.’
This sort of thing reduces my mind to
a pulp. I can faintly resist when a man says that if the earth were a
globe cats would not have four legs; but when he says that if the
earth were a globe cats would not have five legs I am crushed.
But, as I have indicated, it is not
in the scientific aspect of this remarkable theory that I am for the
moment interested. It is rather with the difference between the flat
and the round worlds as conceptions in art and imagination that I am
concerned. It is a very remarkable thing that none of us are really
Copernicans in our actual outlook upon things. We are convinced
intellectually that we inhabit a small provincial planet, but we do
not feel in the least suburban. Men of science have quarrelled with
the Bible because it is not based upon the true astronomical system,
but it is certainly open to the orthodox to say that if it had been
it would never have convinced anybody.
If a single poem or a single story
were really transfused with the Copernican idea, the thing would be a
nightmare. Can we think of a solemn scene of mountain stillness in
which some prophet is standing in a trance, and then realize that the
whole scene is whizzing round like a zoetrope at the rate of nineteen
miles a second? Could we tolerate the notion of a mighty King
delivering a sublime fiat and then remember that for all practical
purposes he is hanging head downwards in space? A strange fable might
be written of a man who was blessed or cursed with the Copernican
eye, and saw all men on the earth like tintacks clustering round a
magnet. It would be singular to imagine how very different the speech
of an aggressive egoist, announcing the independence and divinity of
man, would sound if he were seen hanging on to the planet by his boot
soles.
For, despite Mr. Wardlaw Scott’s
horror at the Newtonian astronomy and its contradiction of the Bible,
the whole distinction is a good instance of the difference between
letter and spirit; the letter of the Old Testament is opposed to the
conception of the solar system, but the spirit has much kinship with
it. The writers of the Book of Genesis had no theory of gravitation,
which to the normal person will appear a fact of as much importance
as that they had no umbrellas. But the theory of gravitation has a
curiously Hebrew sentiment in it–a sentiment of combined
dependence and certainty, a sense of grappling unity, by which all
things hang upon one thread. ‘Thou hast hanged the world upon
nothing,’ said the author of the Book of Job, and in that
sentence wrote the whole appalling poetry of modern astronomy. The
sense of the preciousness and fragility of the universe, the sense of
being in the hollow of a hand, is one which the round and rolling
earth gives in its most thrilling form. Mr. Wardlaw Scott’s
flat earth would be the true territory for a comfortable atheist. Nor
would the old Jews have any objection to being as much upside down as
right way up. They had no foolish ideas about the dignity of man.
It would be an interesting
speculation to imagine whether the world will ever develop a
Copernican poetry and a Copernican habit of fancy; whether we shall
ever speak of ‘early earth-turn’ instead of ‘early
sunrise,’ and speak indifferently of looking up at the daisies,
or looking down on the stars. But if we ever do, there are really a
large number of big and fantastic facts awaiting us, worthy to make a
new mythology. Mr. Wardlaw Scott, for example, with genuine, if
unconscious, imagination, says that according to astronomers, ‘the
sea is a vast mountain of water miles high.’ To have discovered
that mountain of moving crystal, in which the fishes build like
birds, is like discovering Atlantis: it is enough to make the old
world young again. In the new poetry which we contemplate, athletic
young men will set out sturdily to climb up the face of the sea. If
we once realize all this earth as it is, we should find ourselves in
a land of miracles: we shall discover a new planet at the moment that
we discover our own. Among all the strange things that men have
forgotten, the most universal and catastrophic lapse of memory is
that by which they have forgotten that they are living on a star.
In the early days of the world, the
discovery of a fact of natural history was immediately followed by
the realization of it as a fact of poetry. When man awoke from the
long fit of absent-mindedness which is called the automatic animal
state, and began to notice the queer facts that the sky was blue and
the grass green, he immediately began to use those facts
symbolically. Blue, the colour of the sky, became a symbol of
celestial holiness; green passed into the language as indicating a
freshness verging upon unintelligence. If we had the good fortune to
live in a world in which the sky was green and the grass blue, the
symbolism would have been different. But for some mysterious reason
this habit of realizing poetically the facts of science has ceased
abruptly with scientific progress, and all the confounding portents
preached by Galileo and Newton have fallen on deaf ears. They painted
a picture of the universe compared with which the Apocalypse with its
falling stars was a mere idyll. They declared that we are all
careering through space, clinging to a cannon-ball, and the poets
ignore the matter as if it were a remark about the weather. They say
that an invisible force holds us in our own armchairs while the earth
hurtles like a boomerang; and men still go back to dusty records to
prove the mercy of God. They tell us that Mr. Scott’s monstrous
vision of a mountain of sea-water rising in a solid dome, like the
glass mountain in the fairy-tale, is actually a fact, and men still
go back to the fairy-tale. To what towering heights of poetic imagery
might we not have risen if only the poetizing of natural history had
continued and man’s fancy had played with the planets as
naturally as it once played with the flowers! We might have had a
planetary patriotism, in which the green leaf should be like a
cockade, and the sea an everlasting dance of drums. We might have
been proud of what our star has wrought, and worn its heraldry
haughtily in the blind tournament of the spheres. All this, indeed,
we may surely do yet; for with all the multiplicity of knowledge
there is one thing happily that no man knows: whether the world is
old or young.
A DEFENCE OF CHINA SHEPHERDESSES
There are some things of which the
world does not like to be reminded, for they are the dead loves of
the world. One of these is that great enthusiasm for the Arcadian
life which, however much it may now lie open to the sneers of
realism, did, beyond all question, hold sway for an enormous period
of the world’s history, from the times that we describe as
ancient down to times that may fairly be called recent. The
conception of the innocent and hilarious life of shepherds and
shepherdesses certainly covered and absorbed the time of Theocritus,
of Virgil, of Catullus, of Dante, of Cervantes, of Ariosto, of
Shakespeare, and of Pope. We are told that the gods of the heathen
were stone and brass, but stone and brass have never endured with the
long endurance of the China Shepherdess. The Catholic Church and the
Ideal Shepherd are indeed almost the only things that have bridged
the abyss between the ancient world and the modern. Yet, as we say,
the world does not like to be reminded of this boyish enthusiasm.
But imagination, the function of the
historian, cannot let so great an element alone. By the cheap
revolutionary it is commonly supposed that imagination is a merely
rebellious thing, that it has its chief function in devising new and
fantastic republics. But imagination has its highest use in a
retrospective realization. The trumpet of imagination, like the
trumpet of the Resurrection, calls the dead out of their graves.
Imagination sees Delphi with the eyes of a Greek, Jerusalem with the
eyes of a Crusader, Paris with the eyes of a Jacobin, and Arcadia
with the eyes of a Euphuist. The prime function of imagination is to
see our whole orderly system of life as a pile of stratified
revolutions. In spite of all revolutionaries it must be said that the
function of imagination is not to make strange things settled, so
much as to make settled things strange; not so much to make wonders
facts as to make facts wonders. To the imaginative the truisms are
all paradoxes, since they were paradoxes in the Stone Age; to them
the ordinary copy-book blazes with blasphemy.
Let us, then, consider in this light
the old pastoral or Arcadian ideal. But first certainly one thing
must be definitely recognised. This Arcadian art and literature is a
lost enthusiasm. To study it is like fumbling in the love-letters of
a dead man. To us its flowers seem as tawdry as cockades; the lambs
that dance to the shepherd’s pipe seem to dance with all the
artificiality of a ballet. Even our own prosaic toil seems to us more
joyous than that holiday. Where its ancient exuberance passed the
bounds of wisdom and even of virtue, its caperings seem frozen into
the stillness of an antique frieze. In those gray old pictures a
bacchanal seems as dull as an archdeacon. Their very sins seem colder
than our restraints.
All this may be frankly recognised:
all the barren sentimentality of the Arcadian ideal and all its
insolent optimism. But when all is said and done, something else
remains.
Through ages in which the most
arrogant and elaborate ideals of power and civilization held
otherwise undisputed sway, the ideal of the perfect and healthy
peasant did undoubtedly represent in some shape or form the
conception that there was a dignity in simplicity and a dignity in
labour. It was good for the ancient aristocrat, even if he could not
attain to innocence and the wisdom of the earth, to believe that
these things were the secrets of the priesthood of the poor. It was
good for him to believe that even if heaven was not above him, heaven
was below him. It was well that he should have amid all his
flamboyant triumphs the never-extinguished sentiment that there was
something better than his triumphs, the conception that ‘there
remaineth a rest.’
The conception of the Ideal Shepherd
seems absurd to our modern ideas. But, after all, it was perhaps the
only trade of the democracy which was equalized with the trades of
the aristocracy even by the aristocracy itself. The shepherd of
pastoral poetry was, without doubt, very different from the shepherd
of actual fact. Where one innocently piped to his lambs, the other
innocently swore at them; and their divergence in intellect and
personal cleanliness was immense. But the difference between the
ideal shepherd who danced with Amaryllis and the real shepherd who
thrashed her is not a scrap greater than the difference between the
ideal soldier who dies to capture the colours and the real soldier
who lives to clean his accoutrements, between the ideal priest who is
everlastingly by someone’s bed and the real priest who is as
glad as anyone else to get to his own. There are ideal conceptions
and real men in every calling; yet there are few who object to the
ideal conceptions, and not many, after all, who object to the real
men.
The fact, then, is this: So far from
resenting the existence in art and literature of an ideal shepherd, I
genuinely regret that the shepherd is the only democratic calling
that has ever been raised to the level of the heroic callings
conceived by an aristocratic age. So far from objecting to the Ideal
Shepherd, I wish there were an Ideal Postman, an Ideal Grocer, and an
Ideal Plumber. It is undoubtedly true that we should laugh at the
idea of an Ideal Postman; it is true, and it proves that we are not
genuine democrats.
Undoubtedly the modern grocer, if
called upon to act in an Arcadian manner, if desired to oblige with a
symbolic dance expressive of the delights of grocery, or to perform
on some simple instrument while his assistants skipped around him,
would be embarrassed, and perhaps even reluctant. But it may be
questioned whether this temporary reluctance of the grocer is a good
thing, or evidence of a good condition of poetic feeling in the
grocery business as a whole. There certainly should be an ideal image
of health and happiness in any trade, and its remoteness from the
reality is not the only important question. No one supposes that the
mass of traditional conceptions of duty and glory are always
operative, for example, in the mind of a soldier or a doctor; that
the Battle of Waterloo actually makes a private enjoy pipeclaying his
trousers, or that the ‘health of humanity’ softens the
momentary phraseology of a physician called out of bed at two o’clock
in the morning. But although no ideal obliterates the ugly drudgery
and detail of any calling, that ideal does, in the case of the
soldier or the doctor, exist definitely in the background and makes
that drudgery worth while as a whole. It is a serious calamity that
no such ideal exists in the case of the vast number of honourable
trades and crafts on which the existence of a modern city depends. It
is a pity that current thought and sentiment offer nothing
corresponding to the old conception of patron saints. If they did
there would be a Patron Saint of Plumbers, and this would alone be a
revolution, for it would force the individual craftsman to believe
that there was once a perfect being who did actually plumb.
When all is said and done, then, we
think it much open to question whether the world has not lost
something in the complete disappearance of the ideal of the happy
peasant. It is foolish enough to suppose that the rustic went about
all over ribbons, but it is better than knowing that he goes about
all over rags and being indifferent to the fact. The modern realistic
study of the poor does in reality lead the student further astray
than the old idyllic notion. For we cannot get the chiaroscuro of
humble life so long as its virtues seem to us as gross as its vices
and its joys as sullen as its sorrows. Probably at the very moment
that we can see nothing but a dull-faced man smoking and drinking
heavily with his friend in a pot-house, the man himself is on his
soul’s holiday, crowned with the flowers of a passionate
idleness, and far more like the Happy Peasant than the world will
ever know.
A DEFENCE OF USEFUL INFORMATION
It is natural and proper enough that
the masses of explosive ammunition stored up in detective stories and
the replete and solid sweet-stuff shops which are called sentimental
novelettes should be popular with the ordinary customer. It is not
difficult to realize that all of us, ignorant or cultivated, are
primarily interested in murder and love-making. The really
extraordinary thing is that the most appalling fictions are not
actually so popular as that literature which deals with the most
undisputed and depressing facts. Men are not apparently so interested
in murder and love-making as they are in the number of different
forms of latchkey which exist in London or the time that it would
take a grasshopper to jump from Cairo to the Cape. The enormous mass
of fatuous and useless truth which fills the most widely-circulated
papers, such as Tit-Bits, Science Siftings, and many of the
illustrated magazines, is certainly one of the most extraordinary
kinds of emotional and mental pabulum on which man ever fed. It is
almost incredible that these preposterous statistics should actually
be more popular than the most blood-curdling mysteries and the most
luxurious debauches of sentiment. To imagine it is like imagining the
humorous passages in Bradshaw’s Railway Guide read aloud on
winter evenings. It is like conceiving a man unable to put down an
advertisement of Mother Seigel’s Syrup because he wished to
know what eventually happened to the young man who was extremely ill
at Edinburgh. In the case of cheap detective stories and cheap
novelettes, we can most of us feel, whatever our degree of education,
that it might be possible to read them if we gave full indulgence to
a lower and more facile part of our natures; at the worst we feel
that we might enjoy them as we might enjoy bull-baiting or getting
drunk. But the literature of information is absolutely mysterious to
us. We can no more think of amusing ourselves with it than of reading
whole pages of a Surbiton local directory. To read such things would
not be a piece of vulgar indulgence; it would be a highly arduous and
meritorious enterprise. It is this fact which constitutes a profound
and almost unfathomable interest in this particular branch of popular
literature.
Primarily, at least, there is one
rather peculiar thing which must in justice be said about it. The
readers of this strange science must be allowed to be, upon the
whole, as disinterested as a prophet seeing visions or a child
reading fairy-tales. Here, again, we find, as we so often do, that
whatever view of this matter of popular literature we can trust, we
can trust least of all the comment and censure current among the
vulgar educated. The ordinary version of the ground of this
popularity for information, which would be given by a person of
greater cultivation, would be that common men are chiefly interested
in those sordid facts that surround them on every side. A very small
degree of examination will show us that whatever ground there is for
the popularity of these insane encyclopaedias, it cannot be the
ground of utility. The version of life given by a penny novelette may
be very moonstruck and unreliable, but it is at least more likely to
contain facts relevant to daily life than compilations on the subject
of the number of cows’ tails that would reach the North Pole.
There are many more people who are in love than there are people who
have any intention of counting or collecting cows’ tails. It is
evident to me that the grounds of this widespread madness of
information for information’s sake must be sought in other and
deeper parts of human nature than those daily needs which lie so near
the surface that even social philosophers have discovered them
somewhere in that profound and eternal instinct for enthusiasm and
minding other people’s business which made great popular
movements like the Crusades or the Gordon Riots.
I once had the pleasure of knowing a
man who actually talked in private life after the manner of these
papers. His conversation consisted of fragmentary statements about
height and weight and depth and time and population, and his
conversation was a nightmare of dulness. During the shortest pause he
would ask whether his interlocutors were aware how many tons of rust
were scraped every year off the Menai Bridge, and how many rival
shops Mr. Whiteley had bought up since he opened his business. The
attitude of his acquaintances towards this inexhaustible entertainer
varied according to his presence or absence between indifference and
terror. It was frightful to think of a man’s brain being
stocked with such inexpressibly profitless treasures. It was like
visiting some imposing British Museum and finding its galleries and
glass cases filled with specimens of London mud, of common mortar, of
broken walking-sticks and cheap tobacco. Years afterwards I
discovered that this intolerable prosaic bore had been, in fact, a
poet. I learnt that every item of this multitudinous information was
totally and unblushingly untrue, that for all I knew he had made it
up as he went along; that no tons of rust are scraped off the Menai
Bridge, and that the rival tradesmen and Mr. Whiteley were creatures
of the poet’s brain. Instantly I conceived consuming respect
for the man who was so circumstantial, so monotonous, so entirely
purposeless a liar. With him it must have been a case of art for
art’s sake. The joke sustained so gravely through a respected
lifetime was of that order of joke which is shared with omniscience.
But what struck me more cogently upon reflection was the fact that
these immeasurable trivialities, which had struck me as utterly
vulgar and arid when I thought they were true, immediately became
picturesque and almost brilliant when I thought they were inventions
of the human fancy. And here, as it seems to me, I laid my finger
upon a fundamental quality of the cultivated class which prevents it,
and will, perhaps, always prevent it from seeing with the eyes of
popular imagination. The merely educated can scarcely ever be brought
to believe that this world is itself an interesting place. When they
look at a work of art, good or bad, they expect to be interested, but
when they look at a newspaper advertisement or a group in the street,
they do not, properly and literally speaking, expect to be
interested. But to common and simple people this world is a work of
art, though it is, like many great works of art, anonymous. They look
to life for interest with the same kind of cheerful and uneradicable
assurance with which we look for interest at a comedy for which we
have paid money at the door. To the eyes of the ultimate school of
contemporary fastidiousness, the universe is indeed an ill-drawn and
over-coloured picture, the scrawlings in circles of a baby upon the
slate of night; its starry skies are a vulgar pattern which they
would not have for a wallpaper, its flowers and fruits have a cockney
brilliancy, like the holiday hat of a flower-girl. Hence, degraded by
art to its own level, they have lost altogether that primitive and
typical taste of man–the taste for news. By this essential
taste for news, I mean the pleasure in hearing the mere fact that a
man has died at the age of 110 in South Wales, or that the horses ran
away at a funeral in San Francisco. Large masses of the early faiths
and politics of the world, numbers of the miracles and heroic
anecdotes, are based primarily upon this love of something that has
just happened, this divine institution of gossip. When Christianity
was named the good news, it spread rapidly, not only because it was
good, but also because it was news. So it is that if any of us have
ever spoken to a navvy in a train about the daily paper, we have
generally found the navvy interested, not in those struggles of
Parliaments and trades unions which sometimes are, and are always
supposed to be, for his benefit; but in the fact that an unusually
large whale has been washed up on the coast of Orkney, or that some
leading millionaire like Mr. Harmsworth is reported to break a
hundred pipes a year. The educated classes, cloyed and demoralized
with the mere indulgence of art and mood, can no longer understand
the idle and splendid disinterestedness of the reader of Pearson’s
Weekly. He still keeps something of that feeling which should be
the birthright of men–the feeling that this planet is like a
new house into which we have just moved our baggage. Any detail of it
has a value, and, with a truly sportsmanlike instinct, the average
man takes most pleasure in the details which are most complicated,
irrelevant, and at once difficult and useless to discover. Those
parts of the newspaper which announce the giant gooseberry and the
raining frogs are really the modern representatives of the popular
tendency which produced the hydra and the werewolf and the dog-headed
men. Folk in the Middle Ages were not interested in a dragon or a
glimpse of the devil because they thought that it was a beautiful
prose idyll, but because they thought that it had really just been
seen. It was not like so much artistic literature, a refuge
indicating the dulness of the world: it was an incident pointedly
illustrating the fecund poetry of the world.
That much can be said, and is said,
against the literature of information, I do not for a moment deny. It
is shapeless, it is trivial, it may give an unreal air of knowledge,
it unquestionably lies along with the rest of popular literature
under the general indictment that it may spoil the chance of better
work, certainly by wasting time, possibly by ruining taste. But these
obvious objections are the objections which we hear so persistently
from everyone that one cannot help wondering where the papers in
question procure their myriads of readers. The natural necessity and
natural good underlying such crude institutions is far less often a
subject of speculation; yet the healthy hungers which lie at the back
of the habits of modern democracy are surely worthy of the same
sympathetic study that we give to the dogmas of the fanatics long
dethroned and the intrigues of commonwealths long obliterated from
the earth. And this is the base and consideration which I have to
offer: that perhaps the taste for shreds and patches of journalistic
science and history is not, as is continually asserted, the vulgar
and senile curiosity of a people that has grown old, but simply the
babyish and indiscriminate curiosity of a people still young and
entering history for the first time. In other words, I suggest that
they only tell each other in magazines the same kind of stories of
commonplace portents and conventional eccentricities which, in any
case, they would tell each other in taverns. Science itself is only
the exaggeration and specialization of this thirst for useless fact,
which is the mark of the youth of man. But science has become
strangely separated from the mere news and scandal of flowers and
birds; men have ceased to see that a pterodactyl was as fresh and
natural as a flower, that a flower is as monstrous as a pterodactyl.
The rebuilding of this bridge between science and human nature is one
of the greatest needs of mankind. We have all to show that before we
go on to any visions or creations we can be contented with a planet
of miracles.
A DEFENCE OF HERALDRY
The modern view of heraldry is pretty
accurately represented by the words of the famous barrister who,
after cross-examining for some time a venerable dignitary of Heralds’
College, summed up his results in the remark that ‘the silly
old man didn’t even understand his own silly old trade.’
Heraldry properly so called was, of
course, a wholly limited and aristocratic thing, but the remark needs
a kind of qualification not commonly realized. In a sense there was a
plebeian heraldry, since every shop was, like every castle,
distinguished not by a name, but a sign. The whole system dates from
a time when picture-writing still really ruled the world. In those
days few could read or write; they signed their names with a
pictorial symbol, a cross–and a cross is a great improvement on
most men’s names.
Now, there is something to be said
for the peculiar influence of pictorial symbols on men’s minds.
All letters, we learn, were originally pictorial and heraldic: thus
the letter A is the portrait of an ox, but the portrait is now
reproduced in so impressionist a manner that but little of the rural
atmosphere can be absorbed by contemplating it. But as long as some
pictorial and poetic quality remains in the symbol, the constant use
of it must do something for the aesthetic education of those
employing it. Public-houses are now almost the only shops that use
the ancient signs, and the mysterious attraction which they exercise
may be (by the optimistic) explained in this manner. There are
taverns with names so dreamlike and exquisite that even Sir Wilfrid
Lawson might waver on the threshold for a moment, suffering the poet
to struggle with the moralist. So it was with the heraldic images. It
is impossible to believe that the red lion of Scotland acted upon
those employing it merely as a naked convenience like a number or a
letter; it is impossible to believe that the Kings of Scotland would
have cheerfully accepted the substitute of a pig or a frog. There
are, as we say, certain real advantages in pictorial symbols, and one
of them is that everything that is pictorial suggests, without naming
or defining. There is a road from the eye to the heart that does not
go through the intellect. Men do not quarrel about the meaning of
sunsets; they never dispute that the hawthorn says the best and
wittiest thing about the spring.
Thus in the old aristocratic days
there existed this vast pictorial symbolism of all the colours and
degrees of aristocracy. When the great trumpet of equality was blown,
almost immediately afterwards was made one of the greatest blunders
in the history of mankind. For all this pride and vivacity, all these
towering symbols and flamboyant colours, should have been extended to
mankind. The tobacconist should have had a crest, and the
cheesemonger a war-cry. The grocer who sold margarine as butter
should have felt that there was a stain on the escutcheon of the
Higginses. Instead of doing this, the democrats made the appalling
mistake–a mistake at the root of the whole modern malady–of
decreasing the human magnificence of the past instead of increasing
it. They did not say, as they should have done, to the common
citizen, ‘You are as good as the Duke of Norfolk,’ but
used that meaner democratic formula, ‘The Duke of Norfolk is no
better than you are.’
For it cannot be denied that the
world lost something finally and most unfortunately about the
beginning of the nineteenth century. In former times the mass of the
people was conceived as mean and commonplace, but only as
comparatively mean and commonplace; they were dwarfed and eclipsed by
certain high stations and splendid callings. But with the Victorian
era came a principle which conceived men not as comparatively, but as
positively, mean and commonplace. A man of any station was
represented as being by nature a dingy and trivial person–a
person born, as it were, in a black hat. It began to be thought that
it was ridiculous for a man to wear beautiful garments, instead of it
being–as, of course, it is–ridiculous for him to
deliberately wear ugly ones. It was considered affected for a man to
speak bold and heroic words, whereas, of course, it is emotional
speech which is natural, and ordinary civil speech which is affected.
The whole relations of beauty and ugliness, of dignity and ignominy
were turned upside down. Beauty became an extravagance, as if
top-hats and umbrellas were not the real extravagance–a
landscape from the land of the goblins. Dignity became a form of
foolery and shamelessness, as if the very essence of a fool were not
a lack of dignity. And the consequence is that it is practically most
difficult to propose any decoration or public dignity for modern men
without making them laugh. They laugh at the idea of carrying crests
and coats-of-arms instead of laughing at their own boots and
neckties. We are forbidden to say that tradesmen should have a poetry
of their own, although there is nothing so poetical as trade. A
grocer should have a coat-of-arms worthy of his strange merchandise
gathered from distant and fantastic lands; a postman should have a
coat-of-arms capable of expressing the strange honour and
responsibility of the man who carries men’s souls in a bag; the
chemist should have a coat-of-arms symbolizing something of the
mysteries of the house of healing, the cavern of a merciful
witchcraft.
There were in the French Revolution a
class of people at whom everybody laughed, and at whom it was
probably difficult, as a practical matter, to refrain from laughing.
They attempted to erect, by means of huge wooden statues and
brand-new festivals, the most extraordinary new religions. They
adored the Goddess of Reason, who would appear, even when the fullest
allowance has been made for their many virtues, to be the deity who
had least smiled upon them. But these capering maniacs, disowned
alike by the old world and the new, were men who had seen a great
truth unknown alike to the new world and the old. They had seen the
thing that was hidden from the wise and understanding, from the whole
modern democratic civilization down to the present time. They
realized that democracy must have a heraldry, that it must have a
proud and high-coloured pageantry, if it is to keep always before its
own mind its own sublime mission. Unfortunately for this ideal, the
world has in this matter followed English democracy rather than
French; and those who look back to the nineteenth century will
assuredly look back to it as we look back to the reign of the
Puritans, as the time of black coats and black tempers. From the
strange life the men of that time led, they might be assisting at the
funeral of liberty instead of at its christening. The moment we
really believe in democracy, it will begin to blossom, as aristocracy
blossomed, into symbolic colours and shapes. We shall never make
anything of democracy until we make fools of ourselves. For if a man
really cannot make a fool of himself, we may be quite certain that
the effort is superfluous.
A DEFENCE OF UGLY THINGS
There are some people who state that
the exterior, sex, or physique of another person is indifferent to
them, that they care only for the communion of mind with mind; but
these people need not detain us. There are some statements that no
one ever thinks of believing, however often they are made.
But while nothing in this world would
persuade us that a great friend of Mr. Forbes Robertson, let us say,
would experience no surprise or discomfort at seeing him enter the
room in the bodily form of Mr. Chaplin, there is a confusion
constantly made between being attracted by exterior, which is natural
and universal, and being attracted by what is called physical beauty,
which is not entirely natural and not in the least universal. Or
rather, to speak more strictly, the conception of physical beauty has
been narrowed to mean a certain kind of physical beauty which no more
exhausts the possibilities of external attractiveness than the
respectability of a Clapham builder exhausts the possibilities of
moral attractiveness.
The tyrants and deceivers of mankind
in this matter have been the Greeks. All their splendid work for
civilization ought not to have wholly blinded us to the fact of their
great and terrible sin against the variety of life. It is a
remarkable fact that while the Jews have long ago been rebelled
against and accused of blighting the world with a stringent and
one-sided ethical standard, nobody has noticed that the Greeks have
committed us to an infinitely more horrible asceticism–an
asceticism of the fancy, a worship of one aesthetic type alone.
Jewish severity had at least common-sense as its basis; it recognised
that men lived in a world of fact, and that if a man married within
the degrees of blood certain consequences might follow. But they did
not starve their instinct for contrasts and combinations; their
prophets gave two wings to the ox and any number of eyes to the
cherubim with all the riotous ingenuity of Lewis Carroll. But the
Greeks carried their police regulation into elfland; they vetoed not
the actual adulteries of the earth but the wild weddings of ideas,
and forbade the banns of thought.
It is extraordinary to watch the
gradual emasculation of the monsters of Greek myth under the
pestilent influence of the Apollo Belvedere. The chimaera was a
creature of whom any healthy-minded people would have been proud; but
when we see it in Greek pictures we feel inclined to tie a ribbon
round its neck and give it a saucer of milk. Who ever feels that the
giants in Greek art and poetry were really big–big as some
folk-lore giants have been? In some Scandinavian story a hero walks
for miles along a mountain ridge, which eventually turns out to be
the bridge of the giant’s nose. That is what we should call,
with a calm conscience, a large giant. But this earthquake fancy
terrified the Greeks, and their terror has terrified all mankind out
of their natural love of size, vitality, variety, energy, ugliness.
Nature intended every human face, so long as it was forcible,
individual, and expressive, to be regarded as distinct from all
others, as a poplar is distinct from an oak, and an apple-tree from a
willow. But what the Dutch gardeners did for trees the Greeks did for
the human form; they lopped away its living and sprawling features to
give it a certain academic shape; they hacked off noses and pared
down chins with a ghastly horticultural calm. And they have really
succeeded so far as to make us call some of the most powerful and
endearing faces ugly, and some of the most silly and repulsive faces
beautiful. This disgraceful via media, this pitiful sense of
dignity, has bitten far deeper into the soul of modern civilization
than the external and practical Puritanism of Israel. The Jew at the
worst told a man to dance in fetters; the Greek put an exquisite vase
upon his head and told him not to move.
Scripture says that one star
differeth from another in glory, and the same conception applies to
noses. To insist that one type of face is ugly because it differs
from that of the Venus of Milo is to look at it entirely in a
misleading light. It is strange that we should resent people
differing from ourselves; we should resent much more violently their
resembling ourselves. This principle has made a sufficient hash of
literary criticism, in which it is always the custom to complain of
the lack of sound logic in a fairy tale, and the entire absence of
true oratorical power in a three-act farce. But to call another man’s
face ugly because it powerfully expresses another man’s soul is
like complaining that a cabbage has not two legs. If we did so, the
only course for the cabbage would be to point out with severity, but
with some show of truth, that we were not a beautiful green all over.
But this frigid theory of the
beautiful has not succeeded in conquering the art of the world,
except in name. In some quarters, indeed, it has never held sway. A
glance at Chinese dragons or Japanese gods will show how independent
are Orientals of the conventional idea of facial and bodily
regularity, and how keen and fiery is their enjoyment of real beauty,
of goggle eyes, of sprawling claws, of gaping mouths and writhing
coils. In the Middle Ages men broke away from the Greek standard of
beauty, and lifted up in adoration to heaven great towers, which
seemed alive with dancing apes and devils. In the full summer of
technical artistic perfection the revolt was carried to its real
consummation in the study of the faces of men. Rembrandt declared the
sane and manly gospel that a man was dignified, not when he was like
a Greek god, but when he had a strong, square nose like a cudgel, a
boldly-blocked head like a helmet, and a jaw like a steel trap.
This branch of art is commonly
dismissed as the grotesque. We have never been able to understand why
it should be humiliating to be laughable, since it is giving an
elevated artistic pleasure to others. If a gentleman who saw us in
the street were suddenly to burst into tears at the mere thought of
our existence, it might be considered disquieting and
uncomplimentary; but laughter is not uncomplimentary. In truth,
however, the phrase ‘grotesque’ is a misleading
description of ugliness in art. It does not follow that either the
Chinese dragons or the Gothic gargoyles or the goblinish old women of
Rembrandt were in the least intended to be comic. Their extravagance
was not the extravagance of satire, but simply the extravagance of
vitality; and here lies the whole key of the place of ugliness in
aesthetics. We like to see a crag jut out in shameless decision from
the cliff, we like to see the red pines stand up hardily upon a high
cliff, we like to see a chasm cloven from end to end of a mountain.
With equally noble enthusiasm we like to see a nose jut out
decisively, we like to see the red hair of a friend stand up hardily
in bristles upon his head, we like to see his mouth broad and clean
cut like the mountain crevasse. At least some of us like all this; it
is not a question of humour. We do not burst with amusement at the
first sight of the pines or the chasm; but we like them because they
are expressive of the dramatic stillness of Nature, her bold
experiments, her definite departures, her fearlessness and savage
pride in her children. The moment we have snapped the spell of
conventional beauty, there are a million beautiful faces waiting for
us everywhere, just as there are a million beautiful spirits.
A DEFENCE OF FARCE
I have never been able to understand
why certain forms of art should be marked off as something debased
and trivial. A comedy is spoken of as ‘degenerating into
farce’; it would be fair criticism to speak of it ‘changing
into farce’; but as for degenerating into farce, we might
equally reasonably speak of it as degenerating into tragedy. Again, a
story is spoken of as ‘melodramatic,’ and the phrase,
queerly enough, is not meant as a compliment. To speak of something
as ‘pantomimic’ or ‘sensational’ is
innocently supposed to be biting, Heaven knows why, for all works of
art are sensations, and a good pantomime (now extinct) is one of the
pleasantest sensations of all. ‘This stuff is fit for a
detective story,’ is often said, as who should say, ‘This
stuff is fit for an epic.’
Whatever may be the rights and wrongs
of this mode of classification, there can be no doubt about one most
practical and disastrous effect of it. These lighter or wilder forms
of art, having no standard set up for them, no gust of generous
artistic pride to lift them up, do actually tend to become as bad as
they are supposed to be. Neglected children of the great mother, they
grow up in darkness, dirty and unlettered, and when they are right
they are right almost by accident, because of the blood in their
veins. The common detective story of mystery and murder seems to the
intelligent reader to be little except a strange glimpse of a planet
peopled by congenital idiots, who cannot find the end of their own
noses or the character of their own wives. The common pantomime seems
like some horrible satiric picture of a world without cause or
effect, a mass of ‘jarring atoms,’ a prolonged mental
torture of irrelevancy. The ordinary farce seems a world of almost
piteous vulgarity, where a half-witted and stunted creature is afraid
when his wife comes home, and amused when she sits down on the
doorstep. All this is, in a sense, true, but it is the fault of
nothing in heaven or earth except the attitude and the phrases quoted
at the beginning of this article. We have no doubt in the world that,
if the other forms of art had been equally despised, they would have
been equally despicable. If people had spoken of ‘sonnets’
with the same accent with which they speak of ‘music-hall
songs,’ a sonnet would have been a thing so fearful and
wonderful that we almost regret we cannot have a specimen; a rowdy
sonnet is a thing to dream about. If people had said that epics were
only fit for children and nursemaids, ‘Paradise Lost’
might have been an average pantomime: it might have been called
‘Harlequin Satan, or How Adam ‘Ad ’em.’ For
who would trouble to bring to perfection a work in which even
perfection is grotesque? Why should Shakespeare write ‘Othello’
if even his triumph consisted in the eulogy, ‘Mr. Shakespeare
is fit for something better than writing tragedies’?
The case of farce, and its wilder
embodiment in harlequinade, is especially important. That these high
and legitimate forms of art, glorified by Aristophanes and Molière,
have sunk into such contempt may be due to many causes: I myself have
little doubt that it is due to the astonishing and ludicrous lack of
belief in hope and hilarity which marks modern aesthetics, to such an
extent that it has spread even to the revolutionists (once the
hopeful section of men), so that even those who ask us to fling the
stars into the sea are not quite sure that they will be any better
there than they were before. Every form of literary art must be a
symbol of some phase of the human spirit; but whereas the phase is,
in human life, sufficiently convincing in itself, in art it must have
a certain pungency and neatness of form, to compensate for its lack
of reality. Thus any set of young people round a tea-table may have
all the comedy emotions of ‘Much Ado about Nothing’ or
‘Northanger Abbey,’ but if their actual conversation were
reported, it would possibly not be a worthy addition to literature.
An old man sitting by his fire may have all the desolate grandeur of
Lear or Père Goriot, but if he comes into literature he must
do something besides sit by the fire. The artistic justification,
then, of farce and pantomime must consist in the emotions of life
which correspond to them. And these emotions are to an incredible
extent crushed out by the modern insistence on the painful side of
life only. Pain, it is said, is the dominant element of life; but
this is true only in a very special sense. If pain were for one
single instant literally the dominant element in life, every man
would be found hanging dead from his own bed-post by the morning.
Pain, as the black and catastrophic thing, attracts the youthful
artist, just as the schoolboy draws devils and skeletons and men
hanging. But joy is a far more elusive and elvish matter, since it is
our reason for existing, and a very feminine reason; it mingles with
every breath we draw and every cup of tea we drink. The literature of
joy is infinitely more difficult, more rare and more triumphant than
the black and white literature of pain. And of all the varied forms
of the literature of joy, the form most truly worthy of moral
reverence and artistic ambition is the form called ‘farce’–or
its wilder shape in pantomime. To the quietest human being, seated in
the quietest house, there will sometimes come a sudden and unmeaning
hunger for the possibilities or impossibilities of things; he will
abruptly wonder whether the teapot may not suddenly begin to pour out
honey or sea-water, the clock to point to all hours of the day at
once, the candle to burn green or crimson, the door to open upon a
lake or a potato-field instead of a London street. Upon anyone who
feels this nameless anarchism there rests for the time being the
abiding spirit of pantomime. Of the clown who cuts the policeman in
two it may be said (with no darker meaning) that he realizes one of
our visions. And it may be noted here that this internal quality in
pantomime is perfectly symbolized and preserved by that commonplace
or cockney landscape and architecture which characterizes pantomime
and farce. If the whole affair happened in some alien atmosphere, if
a pear-tree began to grow apples or a river to run with wine in some
strange fairyland, the effect would be quite different. The streets
and shops and door-knockers of the harlequinade, which to the vulgar
aesthete make it seem commonplace, are in truth the very essence of
the aesthetic departure. It must be an actual modern door which opens
and shuts, constantly disclosing different interiors; it must be a
real baker whose loaves fly up into the air without his touching
them, or else the whole internal excitement of this elvish invasion
of civilization, this abrupt entrance of Puck into Pimlico, is lost.
Some day, perhaps, when the present narrow phase of aesthetics has
ceased to monopolize the name, the glory of a farcical art may become
fashionable. Long after men have ceased to drape their houses in
green and gray and to adorn them with Japanese vases, an aesthete may
build a house on pantomime principles, in which all the doors shall
have their bells and knockers on the inside, all the staircases be
constructed to vanish on the pressing of a button, and all the
dinners (humorous dinners in themselves) come up cooked through a
trapdoor. We are very sure, at least, that it is as reasonable to
regulate one’s life and lodgings by this kind of art as by any
other.
The whole of this view of farce and
pantomime may seem insane to us; but we fear that it is we who are
insane. Nothing in this strange age of transition is so depressing as
its merriment. All the most brilliant men of the day when they set
about the writing of comic literature do it under one destructive
fallacy and disadvantage: the notion that comic literature is in some
sort of way superficial. They give us little knick-knacks of the
brittleness of which they positively boast, although two thousand
years have beaten as vainly upon the follies of the ‘Frogs’
as on the wisdom of the ‘Republic.’ It is all a mean
shame of joy. When we come out from a performance of the ‘Midsummer
Night’s Dream’ we feel as near to the stars as when we
come out from ‘King Lear.’ For the joy of these works is
older than sorrow, their extravagance is saner than wisdom, their
love is stronger than death.
The old masters of a healthy madness,
Aristophanes or Rabelais or Shakespeare, doubtless had many brushes
with the precisians or ascetics of their day, but we cannot but feel
that for honest severity and consistent self-maceration they would
always have had respect. But what abysses of scorn, inconceivable to
any modern, would they have reserved for an aesthetic type and
movement which violated morality and did not even find pleasure,
which outraged sanity and could not attain to exuberance, which
contented itself with the fool’s cap without the bells!
A DEFENCE OF HUMILITY
The act of defending any of the
cardinal virtues has to-day all the exhilaration of a vice. Moral
truisms have been so much disputed that they have begun to sparkle
like so many brilliant paradoxes. And especially (in this age of
egoistic idealism) there is about one who defends humility something
inexpressibly rakish.
It is no part of my intention to
defend humility on practical grounds. Practical grounds are
uninteresting, and, moreover, on practical grounds the case for
humility is overwhelming. We all know that the ‘divine glory of
the ego’ is socially a great nuisance; we all do actually value
our friends for modesty, freshness, and simplicity of heart. Whatever
may be the reason, we all do warmly respect humility–in other
people.
But the matter must go deeper than
this. If the grounds of humility are found only in social
convenience, they may be quite trivial and temporary. The egoists may
be the martyrs of a nobler dispensation, agonizing for a more arduous
ideal. To judge from the comparative lack of ease in their social
manner, this seems a reasonable suggestion.
There is one thing that must be seen
at the outset of the study of humility from an intrinsic and eternal
point of view. The new philosophy of self-esteem and self-assertion
declares that humility is a vice. If it be so, it is quite clear that
it is one of those vices which are an integral part of original sin.
It follows with the precision of clockwork every one of the great
joys of life. No one, for example, was ever in love without indulging
in a positive debauch of humility. All full-blooded and natural
people, such as schoolboys, enjoy humility the moment they attain
hero-worship. Humility, again, is said both by its upholders and
opponents to be the peculiar growth of Christianity. The real and
obvious reason of this is often missed. The pagans insisted upon
self-assertion because it was the essence of their creed that the
gods, though strong and just, were mystic, capricious, and even
indifferent. But the essence of Christianity was in a literal sense
the New Testament–a covenant with God which opened to men a
clear deliverance. They thought themselves secure; they claimed
palaces of pearl and silver under the oath and seal of the
Omnipotent; they believed themselves rich with an irrevocable
benediction which set them above the stars; and immediately they
discovered humility. It was only another example of the same
immutable paradox. It is always the secure who are humble.
This particular instance survives in
the evangelical revivalists of the street. They are irritating
enough, but no one who has really studied them can deny that the
irritation is occasioned by these two things, an irritating hilarity
and an irritating humility. This combination of joy and
self-prostration is a great deal too universal to be ignored. If
humility has been discredited as a virtue at the present day, it is
not wholly irrelevant to remark that this discredit has arisen at the
same time as a great collapse of joy in current literature and
philosophy. Men have revived the splendour of Greek self-assertion at
the same time that they have revived the bitterness of Greek
pessimism. A literature has arisen which commands us all to arrogate
to ourselves the liberty of self-sufficing deities at the same time
that it exhibits us to ourselves as dingy maniacs who ought to be
chained up like dogs. It is certainly a curious state of things
altogether. When we are genuinely happy, we think we are unworthy of
happiness. But when we are demanding a divine emancipation we seem to
be perfectly certain that we are unworthy of anything.
The only explanation of the matter
must be found in the conviction that humility has infinitely deeper
roots than any modern men suppose; that it is a metaphysical and, one
might almost say, a mathematical virtue. Probably this can best be
tested by a study of those who frankly disregard humility and assert
the supreme duty of perfecting and expressing one’s self. These
people tend, by a perfectly natural process, to bring their own great
human gifts of culture, intellect, or moral power to a great
perfection, successively shutting out everything that they feel to be
lower than themselves. Now shutting out things is all very well, but
it has one simple corollary–that from everything that we shut
out we are ourselves shut out. When we shut our door on the wind, it
would be equally true to say that the wind shuts its door on us.
Whatever virtues a triumphant egoism really leads to, no one can
reasonably pretend that it leads to knowledge. Turning a beggar from
the door may be right enough, but pretending to know all the stories
the beggar might have narrated is pure nonsense; and this is
practically the claim of the egoism which thinks that self-assertion
can obtain knowledge. A beetle may or may not be inferior to a
man–the matter awaits demonstration; but if he were inferior by
ten thousand fathoms, the fact remains that there is probably a
beetle view of things of which a man is entirely ignorant. If he
wishes to conceive that point of view, he will scarcely reach it by
persistently revelling in the fact that he is not a beetle. The most
brilliant exponent of the egoistic school, Nietszche, with deadly and
honourable logic, admitted that the philosophy of self-satisfaction
led to looking down upon the weak, the cowardly, and the ignorant.
Looking down on things may be a delightful experience, only there is
nothing, from a mountain to a cabbage, that is really seen
when it is seen from a balloon. The philosopher of the ego sees
everything, no doubt, from a high and rarified heaven; only he sees
everything foreshortened or deformed.
Now if we imagine that a man wished
truly, as far as possible, to see everything as it was, he would
certainly proceed on a different principle. He would seek to divest
himself for a time of those personal peculiarities which tend to
divide him from the thing he studies. It is as difficult, for
example, for a man to examine a fish without developing a certain
vanity in possessing a pair of legs, as if they were the latest
article of personal adornment. But if a fish is to be approximately
understood, this physiological dandyism must be overcome. The earnest
student of fish morality will, spiritually speaking, chop off his
legs. And similarly the student of birds will eliminate his arms; the
frog-lover will with one stroke of the imagination remove all his
teeth, and the spirit wishing to enter into all the hopes and fears
of jelly-fish will simplify his personal appearance to a really
alarming extent. It would appear, therefore, that this great body of
ours and all its natural instincts, of which we are proud, and justly
proud, is rather an encumbrance at the moment when we attempt to
appreciate things as they should be appreciated. We do actually go
through a process of mental asceticism, a castration of the entire
being, when we wish to feel the abounding good in all things. It is
good for us at certain times that ourselves should be like a mere
window–as clear, as luminous, and as invisible.
In a very entertaining work, over
which we have roared in childhood, it is stated that a point has no
parts and no magnitude. Humility is the luxurious art of reducing
ourselves to a point, not to a small thing or a large one, but to a
thing with no size at all, so that to it all the cosmic things are
what they really are–of immeasurable stature. That the trees
are high and the grasses short is a mere accident of our own
foot-rules and our own stature. But to the spirit which has stripped
off for a moment its own idle temporal standards the grass is an
everlasting forest, with dragons for denizens; the stones of the road
are as incredible mountains piled one upon the other; the dandelions
are like gigantic bonfires illuminating the lands around; and the
heath-bells on their stalks are like planets hung in heaven each
higher than the other. Between one stake of a paling and another
there are new and terrible landscapes; here a desert, with nothing
but one misshapen rock; here a miraculous forest, of which all the
trees flower above the head with the hues of sunset; here, again, a
sea full of monsters that Dante would not have dared to dream. These
are the visions of him who, like the child in the fairy tales, is not
afraid to become small. Meanwhile, the sage whose faith is in
magnitude and ambition is, like a giant, becoming larger and larger,
which only means that the stars are becoming smaller and smaller.
World after world falls from him into insignificance; the whole
passionate and intricate life of common things becomes as lost to him
as is the life of the infusoria to a man without a microscope. He
rises always through desolate eternities. He may find new systems,
and forget them; he may discover fresh universes, and learn to
despise them. But the towering and tropical vision of things as they
really are–the gigantic daisies, the heaven-consuming
dandelions, the great Odyssey of strange-coloured oceans and
strange-shaped trees, of dust like the wreck of temples, and
thistledown like the ruin of stars–all this colossal vision
shall perish with the last of the humble.
A DEFENCE OF SLANG
The aristocrats of the nineteenth
century have destroyed entirely their one solitary utility. It is
their business to be flaunting and arrogant; but they flaunt
unobtrusively, and their attempts at arrogance are depressing. Their
chief duty hitherto has been the development of variety, vivacity,
and fulness of life; oligarchy was the world’s first experiment
in liberty. But now they have adopted the opposite ideal of ‘good
form,’ which may be defined as Puritanism without religion.
Good form has sent them all into black like the stroke of a funeral
bell. They engage, like Mr. Gilbert’s curates, in a war of
mildness, a positive competition of obscurity. In old times the lords
of the earth sought above all things to be distinguished from each
other; with that object they erected outrageous images on their
helmets and painted preposterous colours on their shields. They
wished to make it entirely clear that a Norfolk was as different,
say, from an Argyll as a white lion from a black pig. But to-day
their ideal is precisely the opposite one, and if a Norfolk and an
Argyll were dressed so much alike that they were mistaken for each
other they would both go home dancing with joy.
The consequences of this are
inevitable. The aristocracy must lose their function of standing to
the world for the idea of variety, experiment, and colour, and we
must find these things in some other class. To ask whether we shall
find them in the middle class would be to jest upon sacred matters.
The only conclusion, therefore, is that it is to certain sections of
the lower class, chiefly, for example, to omnibus-conductors, with
their rich and rococo mode of thought, that we must look for guidance
towards liberty and light.
The one stream of poetry which is
continually flowing is slang. Every day a nameless poet weaves some
fairy tracery of popular language. It may be said that the
fashionable world talks slang as much as the democratic; this is
true, and it strongly supports the view under consideration. Nothing
is more startling than the contrast between the heavy, formal,
lifeless slang of the man-about-town and the light, living, and
flexible slang of the coster. The talk of the upper strata of the
educated classes is about the most shapeless, aimless, and hopeless
literary product that the world has ever seen. Clearly in this,
again, the upper classes have degenerated. We have ample evidence
that the old leaders of feudal war could speak on occasion with a
certain natural symbolism and eloquence that they had not gained from
books. When Cyrano de Bergerac, in Rostand’s play, throws
doubts on the reality of Christian’s dulness and lack of
culture, the latter replies:
‘Bah!
on trouve des mots quand on monte à l’assaut; Oui,
j’ai un certain esprit facile et militaire;’
and these two lines sum up a truth
about the old oligarchs. They could not write three legible letters,
but they could sometimes speak literature. Douglas, when he hurled
the heart of Bruce in front of him in his last battle, cried out,
‘Pass first, great heart, as thou wert ever wont.’ A
Spanish nobleman, when commanded by the King to receive a high-placed
and notorious traitor, said: ‘I will receive him in all
obedience, and burn down my house afterwards.’ This is
literature without culture; it is the speech of men convinced that
they have to assert proudly the poetry of life.
Anyone, however, who should seek for
such pearls in the conversation of a young man of modern Belgravia
would have much sorrow in his life. It is not only impossible for
aristocrats to assert proudly the poetry of life; it is more
impossible for them than for anyone else. It is positively considered
vulgar for a nobleman to boast of his ancient name, which is, when
one comes to think of it, the only rational object of his existence.
If a man in the street proclaimed, with rude feudal rhetoric, that he
was the Earl of Doncaster, he would be arrested as a lunatic; but if
it were discovered that he really was the Earl of Doncaster, he would
simply be cut as a cad. No poetical prose must be expected from Earls
as a class. The fashionable slang is hardly even a language; it is
like the formless cries of animals, dimly indicating certain broad,
well-understood states of mind. ‘Bored,’ ‘cut up,’
‘jolly,’ ‘rotten,’ and so on, are like the
words of some tribe of savages whose vocabulary has only twenty of
them. If a man of fashion wished to protest against some solecism in
another man of fashion, his utterance would be a mere string of set
phrases, as lifeless as a string of dead fish. But an omnibus
conductor (being filled with the Muse) would burst out into a solid
literary effort: ‘You’re a gen’leman, aren’t
yer . . . yer boots is a lot brighter than yer ‘ed . . .
there’s precious little of yer, and that’s clothes . . .
that’s right, put yer cigar in yer mouth ‘cos I can’t
see yer be’ind it . . . take it out again, do yer! you’re
young for smokin,’ but I’ve sent for yer mother. . . .
Goin’? oh, don’t run away: I won’t ‘arm yer.
I’ve got a good ‘art, I ‘ave. . . .”Down with
croolty to animals,” I say,’ and so on. It is evident
that this mode of speech is not only literary, but literary in a very
ornate and almost artificial sense. Keats never put into a sonnet so
many remote metaphors as a coster puts into a curse; his speech is
one long allegory, like Spenser’s ‘Faerie Queen.’
I do not imagine that it is necessary
to demonstrate that this poetic allusiveness is the characteristic of
true slang. Such an expression as ‘Keep your hair on’ is
positively Meredithian in its perverse and mysterious manner of
expressing an idea. The Americans have a well-known expression about
‘swelled-head’ as a description of self-approval, and the
other day I heard a remarkable fantasia upon this air. An American
said that after the Chinese War the Japanese wanted ‘to put on
their hats with a shoe-horn.’ This is a monument of the true
nature of slang, which consists in getting further and further away
from the original conception, in treating it more and more as an
assumption. It is rather like the literary doctrine of the
Symbolists.
The real reason of this great
development of eloquence among the lower orders again brings us back
to the case of the aristocracy in earlier times. The lower classes
live in a state of war, a war of words. Their readiness is the
product of the same fiery individualism as the readiness of the old
fighting oligarchs. Any cabman has to be ready with his tongue, as
any gentleman of the last century had to be ready with his sword. It
is unfortunate that the poetry which is developed by this process
should be purely a grotesque poetry. But as the higher orders of
society have entirely abdicated their right to speak with a heroic
eloquence, it is no wonder that the language should develop by itself
in the direction of a rowdy eloquence. The essential point is that
somebody must be at work adding new symbols and new circumlocutions
to a language.
All slang is metaphor, and all
metaphor is poetry. If we paused for a moment to examine the cheapest
cant phrases that pass our lips every day, we should find that they
were as rich and suggestive as so many sonnets. To take a single
instance: we speak of a man in English social relations ‘breaking
the ice.’ If this were expanded into a sonnet, we should have
before us a dark and sublime picture of an ocean of everlasting ice,
the sombre and baffling mirror of the Northern nature, over which men
walked and danced and skated easily, but under which the living
waters roared and toiled fathoms below. The world of slang is a kind
of topsy-turveydom of poetry, full of blue moons and white elephants,
of men losing their heads, and men whose tongues run away with them–a
whole chaos of fairy tales.
A DEFENCE OF BABY-WORSHIP
The two facts which attract almost
every normal person to children are, first, that they are very
serious, and, secondly, that they are in consequence very happy. They
are jolly with the completeness which is possible only in the absence
of humour. The most unfathomable schools and sages have never
attained to the gravity which dwells in the eyes of a baby of three
months old. It is the gravity of astonishment at the universe, and
astonishment at the universe is not mysticism, but a transcendent
common-sense. The fascination of children lies in this: that with
each of them all things are remade, and the universe is put again
upon its trial. As we walk the streets and see below us those
delightful bulbous heads, three times too big for the body, which
mark these human mushrooms, we ought always primarily to remember
that within every one of these heads there is a new universe, as new
as it was on the seventh day of creation. In each of those orbs there
is a new system of stars, new grass, new cities, a new sea.
There is always in the healthy mind
an obscure prompting that religion teaches us rather to dig than to
climb; that if we could once understand the common clay of earth we
should understand everything. Similarly, we have the sentiment that
if we could destroy custom at a blow and see the stars as a child
sees them, we should need no other apocalypse. This is the great
truth which has always lain at the back of baby-worship, and which
will support it to the end. Maturity, with its endless energies and
aspirations, may easily be convinced that it will find new things to
appreciate; but it will never be convinced, at bottom, that it has
properly appreciated what it has got. We may scale the heavens and
find new stars innumerable, but there is still the new star we have
not found–that on which we were born.
But the influence of children goes
further than its first trifling effort of remaking heaven and earth.
It forces us actually to remodel our conduct in accordance with this
revolutionary theory of the marvellousness of all things. We do (even
when we are perfectly simple or ignorant)–we do actually treat
talking in children as marvellous, walking in children as marvellous,
common intelligence in children as marvellous. The cynical
philosopher fancies he has a victory in this matter–that he can
laugh when he shows that the words or antics of the child, so much
admired by its worshippers, are common enough. The fact is that this
is precisely where baby-worship is so profoundly right. Any words and
any antics in a lump of clay are wonderful, the child’s words
and antics are wonderful, and it is only fair to say that the
philosopher’s words and antics are equally wonderful.
The truth is that it is our attitude
towards children that is right, and our attitude towards grown-up
people that is wrong. Our attitude towards our equals in age consists
in a servile solemnity, overlying a considerable degree of
indifference or disdain. Our attitude towards children consists in a
condescending indulgence, overlying an unfathomable respect. We bow
to grown people, take off our hats to them, refrain from
contradicting them flatly, but we do not appreciate them properly. We
make puppets of children, lecture them, pull their hair, and
reverence, love, and fear them. When we reverence anything in the
mature, it is their virtues or their wisdom, and this is an easy
matter. But we reverence the faults and follies of children.
We should probably come considerably
nearer to the true conception of things if we treated all grown-up
persons, of all titles and types, with precisely that dark affection
and dazed respect with which we treat the infantile limitations. A
child has a difficulty in achieving the miracle of speech,
consequently we find his blunders almost as marvellous as his
accuracy. If we only adopted the same attitude towards Premiers and
Chancellors of the Exchequer, if we genially encouraged their
stammering and delightful attempts at human speech, we should be in a
far more wise and tolerant temper. A child has a knack of making
experiments in life, generally healthy in motive, but often
intolerable in a domestic commonwealth. If we only treated all
commercial buccaneers and bumptious tyrants on the same terms, if we
gently chided their brutalities as rather quaint mistakes in the
conduct of life, if we simply told them that they would ‘understand
when they were older,’ we should probably be adopting the best
and most crushing attitude towards the weaknesses of humanity. In our
relations to children we prove that the paradox is entirely true,
that it is possible to combine an amnesty that verges on contempt
with a worship that verges upon terror. We forgive children with the
same kind of blasphemous gentleness with which Omar Khayyam forgave
the Omnipotent.
The essential rectitude of our view
of children lies in the fact that we feel them and their ways to be
supernatural while, for some mysterious reason, we do not feel
ourselves or our own ways to be supernatural. The very smallness of
children makes it possible to regard them as marvels; we seem to be
dealing with a new race, only to be seen through a microscope. I
doubt if anyone of any tenderness or imagination can see the hand of
a child and not be a little frightened of it. It is awful to think of
the essential human energy moving so tiny a thing; it is like
imagining that human nature could live in the wing of a butterfly or
the leaf of a tree. When we look upon lives so human and yet so
small, we feel as if we ourselves were enlarged to an embarrassing
bigness of stature. We feel the same kind of obligation to these
creatures that a deity might feel if he had created something that he
could not understand.
But the humorous look of children is
perhaps the most endearing of all the bonds that hold the Cosmos
together. Their top-heavy dignity is more touching than any humility;
their solemnity gives us more hope for all things than a thousand
carnivals of optimism; their large and lustrous eyes seem to hold all
the stars in their astonishment; their fascinating absence of nose
seems to give to us the most perfect hint of the humour that awaits
us in the kingdom of heaven.
A DEFENCE OF DETECTIVE STORIES
In attempting to reach the genuine
psychological reason for the popularity of detective stories, it is
necessary to rid ourselves of many mere phrases. It is not true, for
example, that the populace prefer bad literature to good, and accept
detective stories because they are bad literature. The mere absence
of artistic subtlety does not make a book popular. Bradshaw’s
Railway Guide contains few gleams of psychological comedy, yet it is
not read aloud uproariously on winter evenings. If detective stories
are read with more exuberance than railway guides, it is certainly
because they are more artistic. Many good books have fortunately been
popular; many bad books, still more fortunately, have been unpopular.
A good detective story would probably be even more popular than a bad
one. The trouble in this matter is that many people do not realize
that there is such a thing as a good detective story; it is to them
like speaking of a good devil. To write a story about a burglary is,
in their eyes, a sort of spiritual manner of committing it. To
persons of somewhat weak sensibility this is natural enough; it must
be confessed that many detective stories are as full of sensational
crime as one of Shakespeare’s plays.
There is, however, between a good
detective story and a bad detective story as much, or, rather more,
difference than there is between a good epic and a bad one. Not only
is a detective story a perfectly legitimate form of art, but it has
certain definite and real advantages as an agent of the public weal.
The first essential value of the
detective story lies in this, that it is the earliest and only form
of popular literature in which is expressed some sense of the poetry
of modern life. Men lived among mighty mountains and eternal forests
for ages before they realized that they were poetical; it may
reasonably be inferred that some of our descendants may see the
chimney-pots as rich a purple as the mountain-peaks, and find the
lamp-posts as old and natural as the trees. Of this realization of a
great city itself as something wild and obvious the detective story
is certainly the ‘Iliad.’ No one can have failed to
notice that in these stories the hero or the investigator crosses
London with something of the loneliness and liberty of a prince in a
tale of elfland, that in the course of that incalculable journey the
casual omnibus assumes the primal colours of a fairy ship. The lights
of the city begin to glow like innumerable goblin eyes, since they
are the guardians of some secret, however crude, which the writer
knows and the reader does not. Every twist of the road is like a
finger pointing to it; every fantastic skyline of chimney-pots seems
wildly and derisively signalling the meaning of the mystery.
This realization of the poetry of
London is not a small thing. A city is, properly speaking, more
poetic even than a countryside, for while Nature is a chaos of
unconscious forces, a city is a chaos of conscious ones. The crest of
the flower or the pattern of the lichen may or may not be significant
symbols. But there is no stone in the street and no brick in the wall
that is not actually a deliberate symbol–a message from some
man, as much as if it were a telegram or a post-card. The narrowest
street possesses, in every crook and twist of its intention, the soul
of the man who built it, perhaps long in his grave. Every brick has
as human a hieroglyph as if it were a graven brick of Babylon; every
slate on the roof is as educational a document as if it were a slate
covered with addition and subtraction sums. Anything which tends,
even under the fantastic form of the minutiae of Sherlock Holmes, to
assert this romance of detail in civilization, to emphasize this
unfathomably human character in flints and tiles, is a good thing. It
is good that the average man should fall into the habit of looking
imaginatively at ten men in the street even if it is only on the
chance that the eleventh might be a notorious thief. We may dream,
perhaps, that it might be possible to have another and higher romance
of London, that men’s souls have stranger adventures than their
bodies, and that it would be harder and more exciting to hunt their
virtues than to hunt their crimes. But since our great authors (with
the admirable exception of Stevenson) decline to write of that
thrilling mood and moment when the eyes of the great city, like the
eyes of a cat, begin to flame in the dark, we must give fair credit
to the popular literature which, amid a babble of pedantry and
preciosity, declines to regard the present as prosaic or the common
as commonplace. Popular art in all ages has been interested in
contemporary manners and costume; it dressed the groups around the
Crucifixion in the garb of Florentine gentlefolk or Flemish burghers.
In the last century it was the custom for distinguished actors to
present Macbeth in a powdered wig and ruffles. How far we are
ourselves in this age from such conviction of the poetry of our own
life and manners may easily be conceived by anyone who chooses to
imagine a picture of Alfred the Great toasting the cakes dressed in
tourist’s knickerbockers, or a performance of ‘Hamlet’
in which the Prince appeared in a frock-coat, with a crape band round
his hat. But this instinct of the age to look back, like Lot’s
wife, could not go on for ever. A rude, popular literature of the
romantic possibilities of the modern city was bound to arise. It has
arisen in the popular detective stories, as rough and refreshing as
the ballads of Robin Hood.
There is, however, another good work
that is done by detective stories. While it is the constant tendency
of the Old Adam to rebel against so universal and automatic a thing
as civilization, to preach departure and rebellion, the romance of
police activity keeps in some sense before the mind the fact that
civilization itself is the most sensational of departures and the
most romantic of rebellions. By dealing with the unsleeping sentinels
who guard the outposts of society, it tends to remind us that we live
in an armed camp, making war with a chaotic world, and that the
criminals, the children of chaos, are nothing but the traitors within
our gates. When the detective in a police romance stands alone, and
somewhat fatuously fearless amid the knives and fists of a thieves’
kitchen, it does certainly serve to make us remember that it is the
agent of social justice who is the original and poetic figure, while
the burglars and footpads are merely placid old cosmic conservatives,
happy in the immemorial respectability of apes and wolves. The
romance of the police force is thus the whole romance of man. It is
based on the fact that morality is the most dark and daring of
conspiracies. It reminds us that the whole noiseless and unnoticeable
police management by which we are ruled and protected is only a
successful knight-errantry.
A DEFENCE OF PATRIOTISM
The decay of patriotism in England
during the last year or two is a serious and distressing matter. Only
in consequence of such a decay could the current lust of territory be
confounded with the ancient love of country. We may imagine that if
there were no such thing as a pair of lovers left in the world, all
the vocabulary of love might without rebuke be transferred to the
lowest and most automatic desire. If no type of chivalrous and
purifying passion remained, there would be no one left to say that
lust bore none of the marks of love, that lust was rapacious and love
pitiful, that lust was blind and love vigilant, that lust sated
itself and love was insatiable. So it is with the ‘love of the
city,’ that high and ancient intellectual passion which has
been written in red blood on the same table with the primal passions
of our being. On all sides we hear to-day of the love of our country,
and yet anyone who has literally such a love must be bewildered at
the talk, like a man hearing all men say that the moon shines by day
and the sun by night. The conviction must come to him at last that
these men do not realize what the word ‘love’ means, that
they mean by the love of country, not what a mystic might mean by the
love of God, but something of what a child might mean by the love of
jam. To one who loves his fatherland, for instance, our boasted
indifference to the ethics of a national war is mere mysterious
gibberism. It is like telling a man that a boy has committed murder,
but that he need not mind because it is only his son. Here clearly
the word ‘love’ is used unmeaningly. It is the essence of
love to be sensitive, it is a part of its doom; and anyone who
objects to the one must certainly get rid of the other. This
sensitiveness, rising sometimes to an almost morbid sensitiveness,
was the mark of all great lovers like Dante and all great patriots
like Chatham. ‘My country, right or wrong,’ is a thing
that no patriot would think of saying except in a desperate case. It
is like saying, ‘My mother, drunk or sober.’ No doubt if
a decent man’s mother took to drink he would share her troubles
to the last; but to talk as if he would be in a state of gay
indifference as to whether his mother took to drink or not is
certainly not the language of men who know the great mystery.
What we really need for the
frustration and overthrow of a deaf and raucous Jingoism is a
renascence of the love of the native land. When that comes, all
shrill cries will cease suddenly. For the first of all the marks of
love is seriousness: love will not accept sham bulletins or the empty
victory of words. It will always esteem the most candid counsellor
the best. Love is drawn to truth by the unerring magnetism of agony;
it gives no pleasure to the lover to see ten doctors dancing with
vociferous optimism round a death-bed.
We have to ask, then, Why is it that
this recent movement in England, which has honestly appeared to many
a renascence of patriotism, seems to us to have none of the marks of
patriotism–at least, of patriotism in its highest form? Why has
the adoration of our patriots been given wholly to qualities and
circumstances good in themselves, but comparatively material and
trivial:–trade, physical force, a skirmish at a remote
frontier, a squabble in a remote continent? Colonies are things to be
proud of, but for a country to be only proud of its extremities is
like a man being only proud of his legs. Why is there not a high
central intellectual patriotism, a patriotism of the head and heart
of the Empire, and not merely of its fists and its boots? A rude
Athenian sailor may very likely have thought that the glory of Athens
lay in rowing with the right kind of oars, or having a good supply of
garlic; but Pericles did not think that this was the glory of Athens.
With us, on the other hand, there is no difference at all between the
patriotism preached by Mr. Chamberlain and that preached by Mr. Pat
Rafferty, who sings ‘What do you think of the Irish now?’
They are both honest, simple-minded, vulgar eulogies upon
trivialities and truisms.
I have, rightly or wrongly, a notion
of the chief cause of this pettiness in English patriotism of to-day,
and I will attempt to expound it. It may be taken generally that a
man loves his own stock and environment, and that he will find
something to praise in it; but whether it is the most praiseworthy
thing or no will depend upon the man’s enlightenment as to the
facts. If the son of Thackeray, let us say, were brought up in
ignorance of his father’s fame and genius, it is not improbable
that he would be proud of the fact that his father was over six feet
high. It seems to me that we, as a nation, are precisely in the
position of this hypothetical child of Thackeray’s. We fall
back upon gross and frivolous things for our patriotism, for a simple
reason. We are the only people in the world who are not taught in
childhood our own literature and our own history.
We are, as a nation, in the truly
extraordinary condition of not knowing our own merits. We have played
a great and splendid part in the history of universal thought and
sentiment; we have been among the foremost in that eternal and
bloodless battle in which the blows do not slay, but create. In
painting and music we are inferior to many other nations; but in
literature, science, philosophy, and political eloquence, if history
be taken as a whole, we can hold our own with any. But all this vast
heritage of intellectual glory is kept from our schoolboys like a
heresy; and they are left to live and die in the dull and infantile
type of patriotism which they learnt from a box of tin soldiers.
There is no harm in the box of tin soldiers; we do not expect
children to be equally delighted with a beautiful box of tin
philanthropists. But there is great harm in the fact that the subtler
and more civilized honour of England is not presented so as to keep
pace with the expanding mind. A French boy is taught the glory of
Molière as well as that of Turenne; a German boy is taught his
own great national philosophy before he learns the philosophy of
antiquity. The result is that, though French patriotism is often
crazy and boastful, though German patriotism is often isolated and
pedantic, they are neither of them merely dull, common, and brutal,
as is so often the strange fate of the nation of Bacon and Locke. It
is natural enough, and even righteous enough, under the
circumstances. An Englishman must love England for something;
consequently, he tends to exalt commerce or prize-fighting, just as a
German might tend to exalt music, or a Flamand to exalt painting,
because he really believes it is the chief merit of his fatherland.
It would not be in the least extraordinary if a claim of eating up
provinces and pulling down princes were the chief boast of a Zulu.
The extraordinary thing is, that it is the chief boast of a people
who have Shakespeare, Newton, Burke, and Darwin to boast of.
The peculiar lack of any generosity
or delicacy in the current English nationalism appears to have no
other possible origin but in this fact of our unique neglect in
education of the study of the national literature. An Englishman
could not be silly enough to despise other nations if he once knew
how much England had done for them. Great men of letters cannot avoid
being humane and universal. The absence of the teaching of English
literature in our schools is, when we come to think of it, an almost
amazing phenomenon. It is even more amazing when we listen to the
arguments urged by headmasters and other educational conservatives
against the direct teaching of English. It is said, for example, that
a vast amount of English grammar and literature is picked up in the
course of learning Latin and Greek. This is perfectly true, but the
topsy-turviness of the idea never seems to strike them. It is like
saying that a baby picks up the art of walking in the course of
learning to hop, or that a Frenchman may successfully be taught
German by helping a Prussian to learn Ashanti. Surely the obvious
foundation of all education is the language in which that education
is conveyed; if a boy has only time to learn one thing, he had better
learn that.
We have deliberately neglected this
great heritage of high national sentiment. We have made our public
schools the strongest walls against a whisper of the honour of
England. And we have had our punishment in this strange and perverted
fact that, while a unifying vision of patriotism can ennoble bands of
brutal savages or dingy burghers, and be the best thing in their
lives, we, who are–the world being judge–humane, honest,
and serious individually, have a patriotism that is the worst thing
in ours. What have we done, and where have we wandered, we that have
produced sages who could have spoken with Socrates and poets who
could walk with Dante, that we should talk as if we have never done
anything more intelligent than found colonies and kick niggers? We
are the children of light, and it is we that sit in darkness. If we
are judged, it will not be for the merely intellectual transgression
of failing to appreciate other nations, but for the supreme spiritual
transgression of failing to appreciate ourselves.
ILLUSTRATIONS
Illustration
1
Illustration
2
Illustration
3
Illustration
4
Illustration
5
Illustration
6
Illustration
7
Illustration
8
Illustration
9
Illustration
10
TABLE OF CONTENTS
PUBLISHER II
www.eCatholic2000.com
|