|
All
Things Considered
G.
K. Chesterton
1915, US.
This
work is published for the greater Glory of Jesus Christ through His
most Holy Mother Mary and for the sanctification of the militant
Church and her members.
PUBLISHER
www.eCatholic2000.com
INDEX
TABLE
OF CONTENTS
ALL
THINGS CONSIDERED
ILLUSTRATIONS
PUBLISHER
II
ALL THINGS CONSIDERED
THE CASE FOR THE EPHEMERAL
I cannot understand the people who
take literature seriously; but I can love them, and I do. Out of my
love I warn them to keep clear of this book. It is a collection of
crude and shapeless papers upon current or rather flying subjects;
and they must be published pretty much as they stand. They were
written, as a rule, at the last moment; they were handed in the
moment before it was too late, and I do not think that our
commonwealth would have been shaken to its foundations if they had
been handed in the moment after. They must go out now, with all their
imperfections on their head, or rather on mine; for their vices are
too vital to be improved with a blue pencil, or with anything I can
think of, except dynamite.
Their chief vice is that so many of
them are very serious; because I had no time to make them flippant.
It is so easy to be solemn; it is so hard to be frivolous. Let any
honest reader shut his eyes for a few moments, and approaching the
secret tribunal of his soul, ask himself whether he would really
rather be asked in the next two hours to write the front page of the
Times, which is full of long leading articles, or the front
page of Tit–Bits, which is full of short jokes. If the
reader is the fine conscientious fellow I take him for, he will at
once reply that he would rather on the spur of the moment write ten
Times articles than one Tit–Bits joke.
Responsibility, a heavy and cautious responsibility of speech, is the
easiest thing in the world; anybody can do it. That is why so many
tired, elderly, and wealthy men go in for politics. They are
responsible, because they have not the strength of mind left to be
irresponsible. It is more dignified to sit still than to dance the
Barn Dance. It is also easier. So in these easy pages I keep myself
on the whole on the level of the Times: it is only
occasionally that I leap upwards almost to the level of Tit–Bits.
I resume the defence of this
indefensible book. These articles have another disadvantage arising
from the scurry in which they were written; they are too long–winded
and elaborate. One of the great disadvantages of hurry is that it
takes such a long time. If I have to start for High–gate this
day week, I may perhaps go the shortest way. If I have to start this
minute, I shall almost certainly go the longest. In these essays (as
I read them over) I feel frightfully annoyed with myself for not
getting to the point more quickly; but I had not enough leisure to be
quick. There are several maddening cases in which I took two or three
pages in attempting to describe an attitude of which the essence
could be expressed in an epigram; only there was no time for
epigrams. I do not repent of one shade of opinion here expressed; but
I feel that they might have been expressed so much more briefly and
precisely. For instance, these pages contain a sort of recurring
protest against the boast of certain writers that they are merely
recent. They brag that their philosophy of the universe is the last
philosophy or the new philosophy, or the advanced and progressive
philosophy. I have said much against a mere modernism. When I use the
word “modernism,” I am not alluding specially to the
current quarrel in the Roman Catholic Church, though I am certainly
astonished at any intellectual group accepting so weak and
unphilosophical a name. It is incomprehensible to me that any thinker
can calmly call himself a modernist; he might as well call himself a
Thursdayite. But apart altogether from that particular disturbance, I
am conscious of a general irritation expressed against the people who
boast of their advancement and modernity in the discussion of
religion. But I never succeeded in saying the quite clear and obvious
thing that is really the matter with modernism. The real objection to
modernism is simply that it is a form of snobbishness. It is an
attempt to crush a rational opponent not by reason, but by some
mystery of superiority, by hinting that one is specially up to date
or particularly “in the know.” To flaunt the fact that we
have had all the last books from Germany is simply vulgar; like
flaunting the fact that we have had all the last bonnets from Paris.
To introduce into philosophical discussions a sneer at a creed’s
antiquity is like introducing a sneer at a lady’s age. It is
caddish because it is irrelevant. The pure modernist is merely a
snob; he cannot bear to be a month behind the fashion Similarly I
find that I have tried in these pages to express the real objection
to philanthropists and have not succeeded. I have not seen the quite
simple objection to the causes advocated by certain wealthy
idealists; causes of which the cause called teetotalism is the
strongest case. I have used many abusive terms about the thing,
calling it Puritanism, or superciliousness, or aristocracy; but I
have not seen and stated the quite simple objection to philanthropy;
which is that it is religious persecution. Religious persecution does
not consist in thumbscrews or fires of Smithfield; the essence of
religious persecution is this: that the man who happens to have
material power in the State, either by wealth or by official
position, should govern his fellow–citizens not according to
their religion or philosophy, but according to his own. If, for
instance, there is such a thing as a vegetarian nation; if there is a
great united mass of men who wish to live by the vegetarian morality,
then I say in the emphatic words of the arrogant French marquis
before the French Revolution, “Let them eat grass.”
Perhaps that French oligarch was a humanitarian; most oligarchs are.
Perhaps when he told the peasants to eat grass he was recommending to
them the hygienic simplicity of a vegetarian restaurant. But that is
an irrelevant, though most fascinating, speculation. The point here
is that if a nation is really vegetarian let its government force
upon it the whole horrible weight of vegetarianism. Let its
government give the national guests a State vegetarian banquet. Let
its government, in the most literal and awful sense of the words,
give them beans. That sort of tyranny is all very well; for it is the
people tyrannising over all the persons. But “temperance
reformers” are like a small group of vegetarians who should
silently and systematically act on an ethical assumption entirely
unfamiliar to the mass of the people. They would always be giving
peerages to greengrocers. They would always be appointing
Parliamentary Commissions to enquire into the private life of
butchers. Whenever they found a man quite at their mercy, as a pauper
or a convict or a lunatic, they would force him to add the final
touch to his inhuman isolation by becoming a vegetarian. All the
meals for school children will be vegetarian meals. All the State
public houses will be vegetarian public houses. There is a very
strong case for vegetarianism as compared with teetotalism. Drinking
one glass of beer cannot by any philosophy be drunkenness; but
killing one animal can, by this philosophy, be murder. The objection
to both processes is not that the two creeds, teetotal and
vegetarian, are not admissible; it is simply that they are not
admitted. The thing is religious persecution because it is not based
on the existing religion of the democracy. These people ask the poor
to accept in practice what they know perfectly well that the poor
would not accept in theory. That is the very definition of religious
persecution. I was against the Tory attempt to force upon ordinary
Englishmen a Catholic theology in which they do not believe. I am
even more against the attempt to force upon them a Mohamedan morality
which they actively deny.
Again, in the case of anonymous
journalism I seem to have said a great deal without getting out the
point very clearly. Anonymous journalism is dangerous, and is
poisonous in our existing life simply because it is so rapidly
becoming an anonymous life. That is the horrible thing about our
contemporary atmosphere. Society is becoming a secret society. The
modern tyrant is evil because of his elusiveness. He is more nameless
than his slave. He is not more of a bully than the tyrants of the
past; but he is more of a coward. The rich publisher may treat the
poor poet better or worse than the old master workman treated the old
apprentice. But the apprentice ran away and the master ran after him.
Nowadays it is the poet who pursues and tries in vain to fix the fact
of responsibility. It is the publisher who runs away. The clerk of
Mr. Solomon gets the sack: the beautiful Greek slave of the Sultan
Suliman also gets the sack; or the sack gets her. But though she is
concealed under the black waves of the Bosphorus, at least her
destroyer is not concealed. He goes behind golden trumpets riding on
a white elephant. But in the case of the clerk it is almost as
difficult to know where the dismissal comes from as to know where the
clerk goes to. It may be Mr. Solomon or Mr. Solomon’s manager,
or Mr. Solomon’s rich aunt in Cheltenham, or Mr. Soloman’s
rich creditor in Berlin. The elaborate machinery which was once used
to make men responsible is now used solely in order to shift the
responsibility. People talk about the pride of tyrants; but we in
this age are not suffering from the pride of tyrants. We are
suffering from the shyness of tyrants; from the shrinking modesty of
tyrants. Therefore we must not encourage leader–writers to be
shy; we must not inflame their already exaggerated modesty. Rather we
must attempt to lure them to be vain and ostentatious; so that
through ostentation they may at last find their way to honesty.
The last indictment against this book
is the worst of all. It is simply this: that if all goes well this
book will be unintelligible gibberish. For it is mostly concerned
with attacking attitudes which are in their nature accidental and
incapable of enduring. Brief as is the career of such a book as this,
it may last just twenty minutes longer than most of the philosophies
that it attacks. In the end it will not matter to us whether we wrote
well or ill; whether we fought with flails or reeds. It will matter
to us greatly on what side we fought.
COCKNEYS AND THEIR JOKES
A writer in the Yorkshire Evening
Post is very angry indeed with my performances in this column.
His precise terms of reproach are, “Mr. G. K. Chesterton is not
a humourist: not even a Cockney humourist.” I do not mind his
saying that I am not a humourist–in which (to tell the truth) I
think he is quite right. But I do resent his saying that I am not a
Cockney. That envenomed arrow, I admit, went home. If a French writer
said of me, “He is no metaphysician: not even an English
metaphysician,” I could swallow the insult to my metaphysics,
but I should feel angry about the insult to my country. So I do not
urge that I am a humourist; but I do insist that I am a Cockney. If I
were a humourist, I should certainly be a Cockney humourist; if I
were a saint, I should certainly be a Cockney saint. I need not
recite the splendid catalogue of Cockney saints who have written
their names on our noble old City churches. I need not trouble you
with the long list of the Cockney humourists who have discharged
their bills (or failed to discharge them) in our noble old City
taverns. We can weep together over the pathos of the poor
Yorkshireman, whose county has never produced some humour not
intelligible to the rest of the world. And we can smile together when
he says that somebody or other is “not even” a Cockney
humourist like Samuel Johnson or Charles Lamb. It is surely
sufficiently obvious that all the best humour that exists in our
language is Cockney humour. Chaucer was a Cockney; he had his house
close to the Abbey. Dickens was a Cockney; he said he could not think
without the London streets. The London taverns heard always the
quaintest conversation, whether it was Ben Johnson’s at the
Mermaid or Sam Johnson’s at the Cock. Even in our own time it
may be noted that the most vital and genuine humour is still written
about London. Of this type is the mild and humane irony which marks
Mr. Pett Ridge’s studies of the small grey streets. Of this
type is the simple but smashing laughter of the best tales of Mr. W.
W. Jacobs, telling of the smoke and sparkle of the Thames. No; I
concede that I am not a Cockney humourist. No; I am not worthy to be.
Some time, after sad and strenuous after–lives; some time,
after fierce and apocalyptic incarnations; in some strange world
beyond the stars, I may become at last a Cockney humourist. In that
potential paradise I may walk among the Cockney humourists, if not an
equal, at least a companion. I may feel for a moment on my shoulder
the hearty hand of Dryden and thread the labyrinths of the sweet
insanity of Lamb. But that could only be if I were not only much
cleverer, but much better than I am. Before I reach that sphere I
shall have left behind, perhaps, the sphere that is inhabited by
angels, and even passed that which is appropriated exclusively to the
use of Yorkshiremen.
No; London is in this matter attacked
upon its strongest ground. London is the largest of the bloated
modern cities; London is the smokiest; London is the dirtiest; London
is, if you will, the most sombre; London is, if you will, the most
miserable. But London is certainly the most amusing and the most
amused. You may prove that we have the most tragedy; the fact remains
that we have the most comedy, that we have the most farce. We have at
the very worst a splendid hypocrisy of humour. We conceal our sorrow
behind a screaming derision. You speak of people who laugh through
their tears; it is our boast that we only weep through our laughter.
There remains always this great boast, perhaps the greatest boast
that is possible to human nature. I mean the great boast that the
most unhappy part of our population is also the most hilarious part.
The poor can forget that social problem which we (the moderately
rich) ought never to forget. Blessed are the poor; for they alone
have not the poor always with them. The honest poor can sometimes
forget poverty. The honest rich can never forget it.
I believe firmly in the value of all
vulgar notions, especially of vulgar jokes. When once you have got
hold of a vulgar joke, you may be certain that you have got hold of a
subtle and spiritual idea. The men who made the joke saw something
deep which they could not express except by something silly and
emphatic. They saw something delicate which they could only express
by something indelicate. I remember that Mr. Max Beerbohm (who has
every merit except democracy) attempted to analyse the jokes at which
the mob laughs. He divided them into three sections: jokes about
bodily humiliation, jokes about things alien, such as foreigners, and
jokes about bad cheese. Mr. Max Beerbohm thought he understood the
first two forms; but I am not sure that he did. In order to
understand vulgar humour it is not enough to be humorous. One must
also be vulgar, as I am. And in the first case it is surely obvious
that it is not merely at the fact of something being hurt that we
laugh (as I trust we do) when a Prime Minister sits down on his hat.
If that were so we should laugh whenever we saw a funeral. We do not
laugh at the mere fact of something falling down; there is nothing
humorous about leaves falling or the sun going down. When our house
falls down we do not laugh. All the birds of the air might drop
around us in a perpetual shower like a hailstorm without arousing a
smile. If you really ask yourself why we laugh at a man sitting down
suddenly in the street you will discover that the reason is not only
recondite, but ultimately religious. All the jokes about men sitting
down on their hats are really theological jokes; they are concerned
with the Dual Nature of Man. They refer to the primary paradox that
man is superior to all the things around him and yet is at their
mercy.
Quite equally subtle and spiritual is
the idea at the back of laughing at foreigners. It concerns the
almost torturing truth of a thing being like oneself and yet not like
oneself. Nobody laughs at what is entirely foreign; nobody laughs at
a palm tree. But it is funny to see the familiar image of God
disguised behind the black beard of a Frenchman or the black face of
a Negro. There is nothing funny in the sounds that are wholly
inhuman, the howling of wild beasts or of the wind. But if a man
begins to talk like oneself, but all the syllables come out
different, then if one is a man one feels inclined to laugh, though
if one is a gentleman one resists the inclination.
Mr. Max Beerbohm, I remember,
professed to understand the first two forms of popular wit, but said
that the third quite stumped him. He could not see why there should
be anything funny about bad cheese. I can tell him at once. He has
missed the idea because it is subtle and philosophical, and he was
looking for something ignorant and foolish. Bad cheese is funny
because it is (like the foreigner or the man fallen on the pavement)
the type of the transition or transgression across a great mystical
boundary. Bad cheese symbolises the change from the inorganic to the
organic. Bad cheese symbolises the startling prodigy of matter taking
on vitality. It symbolises the origin of life itself. And it is only
about such solemn matters as the origin of life that the democracy
condescends to joke. Thus, for instance, the democracy jokes about
marriage, because marriage is a part of mankind. But the democracy
would never deign to joke about Free Love, because Free Love is a
piece of priggishness.
As a matter of fact, it will be
generally found that the popular joke is not true to the letter, but
is true to the spirit. The vulgar joke is generally in the oddest way
the truth and yet not the fact. For instance, it is not in the least
true that mothers–in–law are as a class oppressive and
intolerable; most of them are both devoted and useful. All the
mothers–in–law I have ever had were admirable. Yet the
legend of the comic papers is profoundly true. It draws attention to
the fact that it is much harder to be a nice mother–in–law
than to be nice in any other conceivable relation of life. The
caricatures have drawn the worst mother–in–law a monster,
by way of expressing the fact that the best mother–in–law
is a problem. The same is true of the perpetual jokes in comic papers
about shrewish wives and henpecked husbands. It is all a frantic
exaggeration, but it is an exaggeration of a truth; whereas all the
modern mouthings about oppressed women are the exaggerations of a
falsehood. If you read even the best of the intellectuals of to–day
you will find them saying that in the mass of the democracy the woman
is the chattel of her lord, like his bath or his bed. But if you read
the comic literature of the democracy you will find that the lord
hides under the bed to escape from the wrath of his chattel. This is
not the fact, but it is much nearer the truth. Every man who is
married knows quite well, not only that he does not regard his wife
as a chattel, but that no man can conceivably ever have done so. The
joke stands for an ultimate truth, and that is a subtle truth. It is
one not very easy to state correctly. It can, perhaps, be most
correctly stated by saying that, even if the man is the head of the
house, he knows he is the figurehead.
But the vulgar comic papers are so
subtle and true that they are even prophetic. If you really want to
know what is going to happen to the future of our democracy, do not
read the modern sociological prophecies, do not read even Mr. Wells’s
Utopias for this purpose, though you should certainly read them if
you are fond of good honesty and good English. If you want to know
what will happen, study the pages of Snaps or Patchy Bits
as if they were the dark tablets graven with the oracles of the gods.
For, mean and gross as they are, in all seriousness, they contain
what is entirely absent from all Utopias and all the sociological
conjectures of our time: they contain some hint of the actual habits
and manifest desires of the English people. If we are really to find
out what the democracy will ultimately do with itself, we shall
surely find it, not in the literature which studies the people, but
in the literature which the people studies.
I can give two chance cases in which
the common or Cockney joke was a much better prophecy than the
careful observations of the most cultured observer. When England was
agitated, previous to the last General Election, about the existence
of Chinese labour, there was a distinct difference between the tone
of the politicians and the tone of the populace. The politicians who
disapproved of Chinese labour were most careful to explain that they
did not in any sense disapprove of Chinese. According to them, it was
a pure question of legal propriety, of whether certain clauses in the
contract of indenture were not inconsistent with our constitutional
traditions: according to them, the case would have been the same if
the people had been Kaffirs or Englishmen. It all sounded wonderfully
enlightened and lucid; and in comparison the popular joke looked, of
course, very poor. For the popular joke against the Chinese labourers
was simply that they were Chinese; it was an objection to an alien
type; the popular papers were full of gibes about pigtails and yellow
faces. It seemed that the Liberal politicians were raising an
intellectual objection to a doubtful document of State; while it
seemed that the Radical populace were merely roaring with idiotic
laughter at the sight of a Chinaman’s clothes. But the popular
instinct was justified, for the vices revealed were Chinese vices.
But there is another case more
pleasant and more up to date. The popular papers always persisted in
representing the New Woman or the Suffragette as an ugly woman, fat,
in spectacles, with bulging clothes, and generally falling off a
bicycle. As a matter of plain external fact, there was not a word of
truth in this. The leaders of the movement of female emancipation are
not at all ugly; most of them are extraordinarily good–looking.
Nor are they at all indifferent to art or decorative costume; many of
them are alarmingly attached to these things. Yet the popular
instinct was right. For the popular instinct was that in this
movement, rightly or wrongly, there was an element of indifference to
female dignity, of a quite new willingness of women to be grotesque.
These women did truly despise the pontifical quality of woman. And in
our streets and around our Parliament we have seen the stately woman
of art and culture turn into the comic woman of Comic Bits.
And whether we think the exhibition justifiable or not, the prophecy
of the comic papers is justified: the healthy and vulgar masses were
conscious of a hidden enemy to their traditions who has now come out
into the daylight, that the scriptures might be fulfilled. For the
two things that a healthy person hates most between heaven and hell
are a woman who is not dignified and a man who is.
THE FALLACY OF SUCCESS
There has appeared in our time a
particular class of books and articles which I sincerely and solemnly
think may be called the silliest ever known among men. They are much
more wild than the wildest romances of chivalry and much more dull
than the dullest religious tract. Moreover, the romances of chivalry
were at least about chivalry; the religious tracts are about
religion. But these things are about nothing; they are about what is
called Success. On every bookstall, in every magazine, you may find
works telling people how to succeed. They are books showing men how
to succeed in everything; they are written by men who cannot even
succeed in writing books. To begin with, of course, there is no such
thing as Success. Or, if you like to put it so, there is nothing that
is not successful. That a thing is successful merely means that it
is; a millionaire is successful in being a millionaire and a donkey
in being a donkey. Any live man has succeeded in living; any dead man
may have succeeded in committing suicide. But, passing over the bad
logic and bad philosophy in the phrase, we may take it, as these
writers do, in the ordinary sense of success in obtaining money or
worldly position. These writers profess to tell the ordinary man how
he may succeed in his trade or speculation–how, if he is a
builder, he may succeed as a builder; how, if he is a stockbroker, he
may succeed as a stockbroker. They profess to show him how, if he is
a grocer, he may become a sporting yachtsman; how, if he is a
tenth–rate journalist, he may become a peer; and how, if he is
a German Jew, he may become an Anglo–Saxon. This is a definite
and business–like proposal, and I really think that the people
who buy these books (if any people do buy them) have a moral, if not
a legal, right to ask for their money back. Nobody would dare to
publish a book about electricity which literally told one nothing
about electricity; no one would dare to publish an article on botany
which showed that the writer did not know which end of a plant grew
in the earth. Yet our modern world is full of books about Success and
successful people which literally contain no kind of idea, and
scarcely any kind of verbal sense.
It is perfectly obvious that in any
decent occupation (such as bricklaying or writing books) there are
only two ways (in any special sense) of succeeding. One is by doing
very good work, the other is by cheating. Both are much too simple to
require any literary explanation. If you are in for the high jump,
either jump higher than any one else, or manage somehow to pretend
that you have done so. If you want to succeed at whist, either be a
good whist–player, or play with marked cards. You may want a
book about jumping; you may want a book about whist; you may want a
book about cheating at whist. But you cannot want a book about
Success. Especially you cannot want a book about Success such as
those which you can now find scattered by the hundred about the
book–market. You may want to jump or to play cards; but you do
not want to read wandering statements to the effect that jumping is
jumping, or that games are won by winners. If these writers, for
instance, said anything about success in jumping it would be
something like this: “The jumper must have a clear aim before
him. He must desire definitely to jump higher than the other men who
are in for the same competition. He must let no feeble feelings of
mercy (sneaked from the sickening Little Englanders and Pro–Boers)
prevent him from trying to do his best. He must remember that
a competition in jumping is distinctly competitive, and that, as
Darwin has gloriously demonstrated, THE WEAKEST GO TO THE WALL.”
That is the kind of thing the book would say, and very useful it
would be, no doubt, if read out in a low and tense voice to a young
man just about to take the high jump. Or suppose that in the course
of his intellectual rambles the philosopher of Success dropped upon
our other case, that of playing cards, his bracing advice would
run–”In playing cards it is very necessary to avoid the
mistake (commonly made by maudlin humanitarians and Free Traders) of
permitting your opponent to win the game. You must have grit and snap
and go in to win. The days of idealism and superstition are
over. We live in a time of science and hard common sense, and it has
now been definitely proved that in any game where two are playing IF
ONE DOES NOT WIN THE OTHER WILL.” It is all very stirring, of
course; but I confess that if I were playing cards I would rather
have some decent little book which told me the rules of the game.
Beyond the rules of the game it is all a question either of talent or
dishonesty; and I will undertake to provide either one or the
other–which, it is not for me to say.
Turning over a popular magazine, I
find a queer and amusing example. There is an article called “The
Instinct that Makes People Rich.” It is decorated in front with
a formidable portrait of Lord Rothschild. There are many definite
methods, honest and dishonest, which make people rich; the only
“instinct” I know of which does it is that instinct which
theological Christianity crudely describes as “the sin of
avarice.” That, however, is beside the present point. I wish to
quote the following exquisite paragraphs as a piece of typical advice
as to how to succeed. It is so practical; it leaves so little doubt
about what should be our next step—“The name of
Vanderbilt is synonymous with wealth gained by modern enterprise.
‘Cornelius,’ the founder of the family, was the first of
the great American magnates of commerce. He started as the son of a
poor farmer; he ended as a millionaire twenty times over.
“He had the
money–making instinct. He seized his opportunities, the
opportunities that were given by the application of the steam–engine
to ocean traffic, and by the birth of railway locomotion in the
wealthy but undeveloped United States of America, and consequently he
amassed an immense fortune.
“Now it is,
of course, obvious that we cannot all follow exactly in the footsteps
of this great railway monarch. The precise opportunities that fell to
him do not occur to us. Circumstances have changed. But, although
this is so, still, in our own sphere and in our own circumstances, we
can follow
his general methods; we can seize those opportunities that are given
us, and give ourselves a very fair chance of attaining riches.”
In such strange utterances we see
quite clearly what is really at the bottom of all these articles and
books. It is not mere business; it is not even mere cynicism. It is
mysticism; the horrible mysticism of money. The writer of that
passage did not really have the remotest notion of how Vanderbilt
made his money, or of how anybody else is to make his. He does,
indeed, conclude his remarks by advocating some scheme; but it has
nothing in the world to do with Vanderbilt. He merely wished to
prostrate himself before the mystery of a millionaire. For when we
really worship anything, we love not only its clearness but its
obscurity. We exult in its very invisibility. Thus, for instance,
when a man is in love with a woman he takes special pleasure in the
fact that a woman is unreasonable. Thus, again, the very pious poet,
celebrating his Creator, takes pleasure in saying that God moves in a
mysterious way. Now, the writer of the paragraph which I have quoted
does not seem to have had anything to do with a god, and I should not
think (judging by his extreme unpracticality) that he had ever been
really in love with a woman. But the thing he does
worship–Vanderbilt–he treats in exactly this mystical
manner. He really revels in the fact his deity Vanderbilt is keeping
a secret from him. And it fills his soul with a sort of transport of
cunning, an ecstasy of priestcraft, that he should pretend to be
telling to the multitude that terrible secret which he does not know.
Speaking about the instinct that
makes people rich, the same writer remarks—“In olden days
its existence was fully understood. The Greeks enshrined it in the
story of Midas, of the ‘Golden Touch.’ Here was a man who
turned everything he laid his hands upon into gold. His life was a
progress amidst riches. Out of everything that came in his way he
created the precious metal. ‘A foolish legend,’ said the
wiseacres of the Victorian age. ‘A truth,’ say we of
to–day. We all know of such men. We are ever meeting or reading
about such persons who turn everything they touch into gold. Success
dogs their very footsteps. Their life’s pathway leads
unerringly upwards. They cannot fail.”
Unfortunately, however, Midas could
fail; he did. His path did not lead unerringly upward. He starved
because whenever he touched a biscuit or a ham sandwich it turned to
gold. That was the whole point of the story, though the writer has to
suppress it delicately, writing so near to a portrait of Lord
Rothschild. The old fables of mankind are, indeed, unfathomably wise;
but we must not have them expurgated in the interests of Mr.
Vanderbilt. We must not have King Midas represented as an example of
success; he was a failure of an unusually painful kind. Also, he had
the ears of an ass. Also (like most other prominent and wealthy
persons) he endeavoured to conceal the fact. It was his barber (if I
remember right) who had to be treated on a confidential footing with
regard to this peculiarity; and his barber, instead of behaving like
a go–ahead person of the Succeed–at–all–costs
school and trying to blackmail King Midas, went away and whispered
this splendid piece of society scandal to the reeds, who enjoyed it
enormously. It is said that they also whispered it as the winds
swayed them to and fro. I look reverently at the portrait of Lord
Rothschild; I read reverently about the exploits of Mr. Vanderbilt. I
know that I cannot turn everything I touch to gold; but then I also
know that I have never tried, having a preference for other
substances, such as grass, and good wine. I know that these people
have certainly succeeded in something; that they have certainly
overcome somebody; I know that they are kings in a sense that no men
were ever kings before; that they create markets and bestride
continents. Yet it always seems to me that there is some small
domestic fact that they are hiding, and I have sometimes thought I
heard upon the wind the laughter and whisper of the reeds.
At least, let us hope that we shall
all live to see these absurd books about Success covered with a
proper derision and neglect. They do not teach people to be
successful, but they do teach people to be snobbish; they do spread a
sort of evil poetry of worldliness. The Puritans are always
denouncing books that inflame lust; what shall we say of books that
inflame the viler passions of avarice and pride? A hundred years ago
we had the ideal of the Industrious Apprentice; boys were told that
by thrift and work they would all become Lord Mayors. This was
fallacious, but it was manly, and had a minimum of moral truth. In
our society, temperance will not help a poor man to enrich himself,
but it may help him to respect himself. Good work will not make him a
rich man, but good work may make him a good workman. The Industrious
Apprentice rose by virtues few and narrow indeed, but still virtues.
But what shall we say of the gospel preached to the new Industrious
Apprentice; the Apprentice who rises not by his virtues, but avowedly
by his vices?
ON RUNNING AFTER ONE’S HAT
I feel an almost savage envy on
hearing that London has been flooded in my absence, while I am in the
mere country. My own Battersea has been, I understand, particularly
favoured as a meeting of the waters. Battersea was already, as I need
hardly say, the most beautiful of human localities. Now that it has
the additional splendour of great sheets of water, there must be
something quite incomparable in the landscape (or waterscape) of my
own romantic town. Battersea must be a vision of Venice. The boat
that brought the meat from the butcher’s must have shot along
those lanes of rippling silver with the strange smoothness of the
gondola. The greengrocer who brought cabbages to the corner of the
Latchmere Road must have leant upon the oar with the unearthly grace
of the gondolier. There is nothing so perfectly poetical as an
island; and when a district is flooded it becomes an archipelago.
Some consider such romantic views of
flood or fire slightly lacking in reality. But really this romantic
view of such inconveniences is quite as practical as the other. The
true optimist who sees in such things an opportunity for enjoyment is
quite as logical and much more sensible than the ordinary “Indignant
Ratepayer” who sees in them an opportunity for grumbling. Real
pain, as in the case of being burnt at Smithfield or having a
toothache, is a positive thing; it can be supported, but scarcely
enjoyed. But, after all, our toothaches are the exception, and as for
being burnt at Smithfield, it only happens to us at the very longest
intervals. And most of the inconveniences that make men swear or
women cry are really sentimental or imaginative inconveniences–things
altogether of the mind. For instance, we often hear grown–up
people complaining of having to hang about a railway station and wait
for a train. Did you ever hear a small boy complain of having to hang
about a railway station and wait for a train? No; for to him to be
inside a railway station is to be inside a cavern of wonder and a
palace of poetical pleasures. Because to him the red light and the
green light on the signal are like a new sun and a new moon. Because
to him when the wooden arm of the signal falls down suddenly, it is
as if a great king had thrown down his staff as a signal and started
a shrieking tournament of trains. I myself am of little boys’
habit in this matter. They also serve who only stand and wait for the
two fifteen. Their meditations may be full of rich and fruitful
things. Many of the most purple hours of my life have been passed at
Clapham Junction, which is now, I suppose, under water. I have been
there in many moods so fixed and mystical that the water might well
have come up to my waist before I noticed it particularly. But in the
case of all such annoyances, as I have said, everything depends upon
the emotional point of view. You can safely apply the test to almost
every one of the things that are currently talked of as the typical
nuisance of daily life.
For instance, there is a current
impression that it is unpleasant to have to run after one’s
hat. Why should it be unpleasant to the well–ordered and pious
mind? Not merely because it is running, and running exhausts one. The
same people run much faster in games and sports. The same people run
much more eagerly after an uninteresting; little leather ball than
they will after a nice silk hat. There is an idea that it is
humiliating to run after one’s hat; and when people say it is
humiliating they mean that it is comic. It certainly is comic; but
man is a very comic creature, and most of the things he does are
comic–eating, for instance. And the most comic things of all
are exactly the things that are most worth doing–such as making
love. A man running after a hat is not half so ridiculous as a man
running after a wife.
Now a man could, if he felt rightly
in the matter, run after his hat with the manliest ardour and the
most sacred joy. He might regard himself as a jolly huntsman pursuing
a wild animal, for certainly no animal could be wilder. In fact, I am
inclined to believe that hat–hunting on windy days will be the
sport of the upper classes in the future. There will be a meet of
ladies and gentlemen on some high ground on a gusty morning. They
will be told that the professional attendants have started a hat in
such–and–such a thicket, or whatever be the technical
term. Notice that this employment will in the fullest degree combine
sport with humanitarianism. The hunters would feel that they were not
inflicting pain. Nay, they would feel that they were inflicting
pleasure, rich, almost riotous pleasure, upon the people who were
looking on. When last I saw an old gentleman running after his hat in
Hyde Park, I told him that a heart so benevolent as his ought to be
filled with peace and thanks at the thought of how much unaffected
pleasure his every gesture and bodily attitude were at that moment
giving to the crowd.
The same principle can be applied to
every other typical domestic worry. A gentleman trying to get a fly
out of the milk or a piece of cork out of his glass of wine often
imagines himself to be irritated. Let him think for a moment of the
patience of anglers sitting by dark pools, and let his soul be
immediately irradiated with gratification and repose. Again, I have
known some people of very modern views driven by their distress to
the use of theological terms to which they attached no doctrinal
significance, merely because a drawer was jammed tight and they could
not pull it out. A friend of mine was particularly afflicted in this
way. Every day his drawer was jammed, and every day in consequence it
was something else that rhymes to it. But I pointed out to him that
this sense of wrong was really subjective and relative; it rested
entirely upon the assumption that the drawer could, should, and would
come out easily. “But if,” I said, “you picture to
yourself that you are pulling against some powerful and oppressive
enemy, the struggle will become merely exciting and not exasperating.
Imagine that you are tugging up a lifeboat out of the sea. Imagine
that you are roping up a fellow–creature out of an Alpine
crevass. Imagine even that you are a boy again and engaged in a
tug–of–war between French and English.” Shortly
after saying this I left him; but I have no doubt at all that my
words bore the best possible fruit. I have no doubt that every day of
his life he hangs on to the handle of that drawer with a flushed face
and eyes bright with battle, uttering encouraging shouts to himself,
and seeming to hear all round him the roar of an applauding ring.
So I do not think that it is
altogether fanciful or incredible to suppose that even the floods in
London may be accepted and enjoyed poetically. Nothing beyond
inconvenience seems really to have been caused by them; and
inconvenience, as I have said, is only one aspect, and that the most
unimaginative and accidental aspect of a really romantic situation.
An adventure is only an inconvenience rightly considered. An
inconvenience is only an adventure wrongly considered. The water that
girdled the houses and shops of London must, if anything, have only
increased their previous witchery and wonder. For as the Roman
Catholic priest in the story said: “Wine is good with
everything except water,” and on a similar principle, water is
good with everything except wine.
THE VOTE AND THE HOUSE
Most of us will be canvassed soon, I
suppose; some of us may even canvass. Upon which side, of course,
nothing will induce me to state, beyond saying that by a remarkable
coincidence it will in every case be the only side in which a
high–minded, public–spirited, and patriotic citizen can
take even a momentary interest. But the general question of
canvassing itself, being a non–party question, is one which we
may be permitted to approach. The rules for canvassers are fairly
familiar to any one who has ever canvassed. They are printed on the
little card which you carry about with you and lose. There is a
statement, I think, that you must not offer a voter food or drink.
However hospitable you may feel towards him in his own house, you
must not carry his lunch about with you. You must not produce a veal
cutlet from your tail–coat pocket. You must not conceal poached
eggs about your person. You must not, like a kind of conjurer,
produce baked potatoes from your hat. In short, the canvasser must
not feed the voter in any way. Whether the voter is allowed to feed
the canvasser, whether the voter may give the canvasser veal cutlets
and baked potatoes, is a point of law on which I have never been able
to inform myself. When I found myself canvassing a gentleman, I have
sometimes felt tempted to ask him if there was any rule against his
giving me food and drink; but the matter seemed a delicate one to
approach. His attitude to me also sometimes suggested a doubt as to
whether he would, even if he could. But there are voters who might
find it worth while to discover if there is any law against bribing a
canvasser. They might bribe him to go away.
The second veto for canvassers which
was printed on the little card said that you must not persuade any
one to personate a voter. I have no idea what it means. To dress up
as an average voter seems a little vague. There is no well–recognised
uniform, as far as I know, with civic waistcoat and patriotic
whiskers. The enterprise resolves itself into one somewhat similar to
the enterprise of a rich friend of mine who went to a fancy–dress
ball dressed up as a gentleman. Perhaps it means that there is a
practice of personating some individual voter. The canvasser creeps
to the house of his fellow–conspirator carrying a make–up
in a bag. He produces from it a pair of white moustaches and a single
eyeglass, which are sufficient to give the most common–place
person a startling resemblance to the Colonel at No. 80. Or he
hurriedly affixes to his friend that large nose and that bald head
which are all that is essential to an illusion of the presence of
Professor Budger. I do not undertake to unravel these knots. I can
only say that when I was a canvasser I was told by the little card,
with every circumstance of seriousness and authority, that I was not
to persuade anybody to personate a voter: and I can lay my hand upon
my heart and affirm that I never did.
The third injunction on the card was
one which seemed to me, if interpreted exactly and according to its
words, to undermine the very foundations of our politics. It told me
that I must not “threaten a voter with any consequence
whatever.” No doubt this was intended to apply to threats of a
personal and illegitimate character; as, for instance, if a wealthy
candidate were to threaten to raise all the rents, or to put up a
statue of himself. But as verbally and grammatically expressed, it
certainly would cover those general threats of disaster to the whole
community which are the main matter of political discussion. When a
canvasser says that if the opposition candidate gets in the country
will be ruined, he is threatening the voters with certain
consequences. When the Free Trader says that if Tariffs are adopted
the people in Brompton or Bayswater will crawl about eating grass, he
is threatening them with consequences. When the Tariff Reformer says
that if Free Trade exists for another year St. Paul’s Cathedral
will be a ruin and Ludgate Hill as deserted as Stonehenge, he is also
threatening. And what is the good of being a Tariff Reformer if you
can’t say that? What is the use of being a politician or a
Parliamentary candidate at all if one cannot tell the people that if
the other man gets in, England will be instantly invaded and
enslaved, blood be pouring down the Strand, and all the English
ladies carried off into harems. But these things are, after all,
consequences, so to speak.
The majority of refined persons in
our day may generally be heard abusing the practice of canvassing. In
the same way the majority of refined persons (commonly the same
refined persons) may be heard abusing the practice of interviewing
celebrities. It seems a very singular thing to me that this refined
world reserves all its indignation for the comparatively open and
innocent element in both walks of life. There is really a vast amount
of corruption and hypocrisy in our election politics; about the most
honest thing in the whole mess is the canvassing. A man has not got a
right to “nurse” a constituency with aggressive
charities, to buy it with great presents of parks and libraries, to
open vague vistas of future benevolence; all this, which goes on
unrebuked, is bribery and nothing else. But a man has got the right
to go to another free man and ask him with civility whether he will
vote for him. The information can be asked, granted, or refused
without any loss of dignity on either side, which is more than can be
said of a park. It is the same with the place of interviewing in
journalism. In a trade where there are labyrinths of insincerity,
interviewing is about the most simple and the most sincere thing
there is. The canvasser, when he wants to know a man’s
opinions, goes and asks him. It may be a bore; but it is about as
plain and straight a thing as he could do. So the interviewer, when
he wants to know a man’s opinions, goes and asks him. Again, it
may be a bore; but again, it is about as plain and straight as
anything could be. But all the other real and systematic cynicisms of
our journalism pass without being vituperated and even without being
known–the financial motives of policy, the misleading posters,
the suppression of just letters of complaint. A statement about a man
may be infamously untrue, but it is read calmly. But a statement by a
man to an interviewer is felt as indefensibly vulgar. That the paper
should misrepresent him is nothing; that he should represent himself
is bad taste. The whole error in both cases lies in the fact that the
refined persons are attacking politics and journalism on the ground
of vulgarity. Of course, politics and journalism are, as it happens,
very vulgar. But their vulgarity is not the worst thing about them.
Things are so bad with both that by this time their vulgarity is the
best thing about them. Their vulgarity is at least a noisy thing; and
their great danger is that silence that always comes before decay.
The conversational persuasion at elections is perfectly human and
rational; it is the silent persuasions that are utterly damnable.
If it is true that the Commons’
House will not hold all the Commons, it is a very good example of
what we call the anomalies of the English Constitution. It is also, I
think, a very good example of how highly undesirable those anomalies
really are. Most Englishmen say that these anomalies do not matter;
they are not ashamed of being illogical; they are proud of being
illogical. Lord Macaulay (a very typical Englishman, romantic,
prejudiced, poetical), Lord Macaulay said that he would not lift his
hand to get rid of an anomaly that was not also a grievance. Many
other sturdy romantic Englishmen say the same. They boast of our
anomalies; they boast of our illogicality; they say it shows what a
practical people we are. They are utterly wrong. Lord Macaulay was in
this matter, as in a few others, utterly wrong. Anomalies do matter
very much, and do a great deal of harm; abstract illogicalities do
matter a great deal, and do a great deal of harm. And this for a
reason that any one at all acquainted with human nature can see for
himself. All injustice begins in the mind. And anomalies accustom the
mind to the idea of unreason and untruth. Suppose I had by some
prehistoric law the power of forcing every man in Battersea to nod
his head three times before he got out of bed. The practical
politicians might say that this power was a harmless anomaly; that it
was not a grievance. It could do my subjects no harm; it could do me
no good. The people of Battersea, they would say, might safely submit
to it. But the people of Battersea could not safely submit to it, for
all that. If I had nodded their heads for them for fifty years I
could cut off their heads for them at the end of it with immeasurably
greater ease. For there would have permanently sunk into every man’s
mind the notion that it was a natural thing for me to have a
fantastic and irrational power. They would have grown accustomed to
insanity.
For, in order that men should resist
injustice, something more is necessary than that they should think
injustice unpleasant. They must think injustice absurd; above
all, they must think it startling. They must retain the violence of a
virgin astonishment. That is the explanation of the singular fact
which must have struck many people in the relations of philosophy and
reform. It is the fact (I mean) that optimists are more practical
reformers than pessimists. Superficially, one would imagine that the
railer would be the reformer; that the man who thought that
everything was wrong would be the man to put everything right. In
historical practice the thing is quite the other way; curiously
enough, it is the man who likes things as they are who really makes
them better. The optimist Dickens has achieved more reforms than the
pessimist Gissing. A man like Rousseau has far too rosy a theory of
human nature; but he produces a revolution. A man like David Hume
thinks that almost all things are depressing; but he is a
Conservative, and wishes to keep them as they are. A man like Godwin
believes existence to be kindly; but he is a rebel. A man like
Carlyle believes existence to be cruel; but he is a Tory. Everywhere
the man who alters things begins by liking things. And the real
explanation of this success of the optimistic reformer, of this
failure of the pessimistic reformer, is, after all, an explanation of
sufficient simplicity. It is because the optimist can look at wrong
not only with indignation, but with a startled indignation. When the
pessimist looks at any infamy, it is to him, after all, only a
repetition of the infamy of existence. The Court of Chancery is
indefensible–like mankind. The Inquisition is abominable–like
the universe. But the optimist sees injustice as something discordant
and unexpected, and it stings him into action. The pessimist can be
enraged at wrong; but only the optimist can be surprised at it.
And it is the same with the relations
of an anomaly to the logical mind. The pessimist resents evil (like
Lord Macaulay) solely because it is a grievance. The optimist resents
it also, because it is an anomaly; a contradiction to his conception
of the course of things. And it is not at all unimportant, but on the
contrary most important, that this course of things in politics and
elsewhere should be lucid, explicable and defensible. When people
have got used to unreason they can no longer be startled at
injustice. When people have grown familiar with an anomaly, they are
prepared to that extent for a grievance; they may think the grievance
grievous, but they can no longer think it strange. Take, if only as
an excellent example, the very matter alluded to before; I mean the
seats, or rather the lack of seats, in the House of Commons. Perhaps
it is true that under the best conditions it would never happen that
every member turned up. Perhaps a complete attendance would never
actually be. But who can tell how much influence in keeping members
away may have been exerted by this calm assumption that they would
stop away? How can any man be expected to help to make a full
attendance when he knows that a full attendance is actually
forbidden? How can the men who make up the Chamber do their duty
reasonably when the very men who built the House have not done theirs
reasonably? If the trumpet give an uncertain sound, who shall prepare
himself for the battle? And what if the remarks of the trumpet take
this form, “I charge you as you love your King and country to
come to this Council. And I know you won’t.”
CONCEIT AND CARICATURE
If a man must needs be conceited, it
is certainly better that he should be conceited about some merits or
talents that he does not really possess. For then his vanity remains
more or less superficial; it remains a mere mistake of fact, like
that of a man who thinks he inherits the royal blood or thinks he has
an infallible system for Monte Carlo. Because the merit is an unreal
merit, it does not corrupt or sophisticate his real merits. He is
vain about the virtue he has not got; but he may be humble about the
virtues that he has got. His truly honourable qualities remain in
their primordial innocence; he cannot see them and he cannot spoil
them. If a man’s mind is erroneously possessed with the idea
that he is a great violinist, that need not prevent his being a
gentleman and an honest man. But if once his mind is possessed in any
strong degree with the knowledge that he is a gentleman, he will soon
cease to be one.
But there is a third kind of
satisfaction of which I have noticed one or two examples
lately–another kind of satisfaction which is neither a pleasure
in the virtues that we do possess nor a pleasure in the virtues we do
not possess. It is the pleasure which a man takes in the presence or
absence of certain things in himself without ever adequately asking
himself whether in his case they constitute virtues at all. A man
will plume himself because he is not bad in some particular way, when
the truth is that he is not good enough to be bad in that particular
way. Some priggish little clerk will say, “I have reason to
congratulate myself that I am a civilised person, and not so
bloodthirsty as the Mad Mullah.” Somebody ought to say to him,
“A really good man would be less bloodthirsty than the Mullah.
But you are less bloodthirsty, not because you are more of a good
man, but because you are a great deal less of a man. You are not
bloodthirsty, not because you would spare your enemy, but because you
would run away from him.” Or again, some Puritan with a sullen
type of piety would say, “I have reason to congratulate myself
that I do not worship graven images like the old heathen Greeks.”
And again somebody ought to say to him, “The best religion may
not worship graven images, because it may see beyond them. But if you
do not worship graven images, it is only because you are mentally and
morally quite incapable of graving them. True religion, perhaps, is
above idolatry. But you are below idolatry. You are not holy enough
yet to worship a lump of stone.”
Mr. F. C. Gould, the brilliant and
felicitous caricaturist, recently delivered a most interesting speech
upon the nature and atmosphere of our modern English caricature. I
think there is really very little to congratulate oneself about in
the condition of English caricature. There are few causes for pride;
probably the greatest cause for pride is Mr. F. C. Gould. But Mr. F.
C. Gould, forbidden by modesty to adduce this excellent ground for
optimism, fell back upon saying a thing which is said by numbers of
other people, but has not perhaps been said lately with the full
authority of an eminent cartoonist. He said that he thought “that
they might congratulate themselves that the style of caricature which
found acceptation nowadays was very different from the lampoon of the
old days.” Continuing, he said, according to the newspaper
report, “On looking back to the political lampoons of
Rowlandson’s and Gilray’s time they would find them
coarse and brutal. In some countries abroad still, ‘even in
America,’ the method of political caricature was of the
bludgeon kind. The fact was we had passed the bludgeon stage. If they
were brutal in attacking a man, even for political reasons, they
roused sympathy for the man who was attacked. What they had to do was
to rub in the point they wanted to emphasise as gently as they
could.” (Laughter and applause.)
Anybody reading these words, and
anybody who heard them, will certainly feel that there is in them a
great deal of truth, as well as a great deal of geniality. But along
with that truth and with that geniality there is a streak of that
erroneous type of optimism which is founded on the fallacy of which I
have spoken above. Before we congratulate ourselves upon the absence
of certain faults from our nation or society, we ought to ask
ourselves why it is that these faults are absent. Are we without the
fault because we have the opposite virtue? Or are we without the
fault because we have the opposite fault? It is a good thing
assuredly, to be innocent of any excess; but let us be sure that we
are not innocent of excess merely by being guilty of defect. Is it
really true that our English political satire is so moderate because
it is so magnanimous, so forgiving, so saintly? Is it penetrated
through and through with a mystical charity, with a psychological
tenderness? Do we spare the feelings of the Cabinet Minister because
we pierce through all his apparent crimes and follies down to the
dark virtues of which his own soul is unaware? Do we temper the wind
to the Leader of the Opposition because in our all–embracing
heart we pity and cherish the struggling spirit of the Leader of the
Opposition? Briefly, have we left off being brutal because we are too
grand and generous to be brutal? Is it really true that we are better
than brutality? Is it really true that we have passed the
bludgeon stage?
I fear that there is, to say the
least of it, another side to the matter. Is it not only too probable
that the mildness of our political satire, when compared with the
political satire of our fathers, arises simply from the profound
unreality of our current politics? Rowlandson and Gilray did not
fight merely because they were naturally pothouse pugilists; they
fought because they had something to fight about. It is easy enough
to be refined about things that do not matter; but men kicked and
plunged a little in that portentous wrestle in which swung to and
fro, alike dizzy with danger, the independence of England, the
independence of Ireland, the independence of France. If we wish for a
proof of this fact that the lack of refinement did not come from mere
brutality, the proof is easy. The proof is that in that struggle no
personalities were more brutal than the really refined personalities.
None were more violent and intolerant than those who were by nature
polished and sensitive. Nelson, for instance, had the nerves and good
manners of a woman: nobody in his senses, I suppose, would call
Nelson “brutal.” But when he was touched upon the
national matter, there sprang out of him a spout of oaths, and he
could only tell men to “Kill! kill! kill the d–d
Frenchmen.” It would be as easy to take examples on the other
side. Camille Desmoulins was a man of much the same type, not only
elegant and sweet in temper, but almost tremulously tender and
humanitarian. But he was ready, he said, “to embrace Liberty
upon a pile of corpses.” In Ireland there were even more
instances. Robert Emmet was only one famous example of a whole family
of men at once sensitive and savage. I think that Mr. F.C. Gould is
altogether wrong in talking of this political ferocity as if it were
some sort of survival from ruder conditions, like a flint axe or a
hairy man. Cruelty is, perhaps, the worst kind of sin. Intellectual
cruelty is certainly the worst kind of cruelty. But there is nothing
in the least barbaric or ignorant about intellectual cruelty. The
great Renaissance artists who mixed colours exquisitely mixed poisons
equally exquisitely; the great Renaissance princes who designed
instruments of music also designed instruments of torture. Barbarity,
malignity, the desire to hurt men, are the evil things generated in
atmospheres of intense reality when great nations or great causes are
at war. We may, perhaps, be glad that we have not got them: but it is
somewhat dangerous to be proud that we have not got them. Perhaps we
are hardly great enough to have them. Perhaps some great virtues have
to be generated, as in men like Nelson or Emmet, before we can have
these vices at all, even as temptations. I, for one, believe that if
our caricaturists do not hate their enemies, it is not because they
are too big to hate them, but because their enemies are not big
enough to hate. I do not think we have passed the bludgeon stage. I
believe we have not come to the bludgeon stage. We must be better,
braver, and purer men than we are before we come to the bludgeon
stage.
Let us then, by all means, be proud
of the virtues that we have not got; but let us not be too arrogant
about the virtues that we cannot help having. It may be that a man
living on a desert island has a right to congratulate himself upon
the fact that he can meditate at his ease. But he must not
congratulate himself on the fact that he is on a desert island, and
at the same time congratulate himself on the self–restraint he
shows in not going to a ball every night. Similarly our England may
have a right to congratulate itself upon the fact that her politics
are very quiet, amicable, and humdrum. But she must not congratulate
herself upon that fact and also congratulate herself upon the
self–restraint she shows in not tearing herself and her
citizens into rags. Between two English Privy Councillors polite
language is a mark of civilisation, but really not a mark of
magnanimity.
Allied to this question is the
kindred question on which we so often hear an innocent British
boast–the fact that our statesmen are privately on very
friendly relations, although in Parliament they sit on opposite sides
of the House. Here, again, it is as well to have no illusions. Our
statesmen are not monsters of mystical generosity or insane logic,
who are really able to hate a man from three to twelve and to love
him from twelve to three. If our social relations are more peaceful
than those of France or America or the England of a hundred years
ago, it is simply because our politics are more peaceful; not
improbably because our politics are more fictitious. If our statesmen
agree more in private, it is for the very simple reason that they
agree more in public. And the reason they agree so much in both cases
is really that they belong to one social class; and therefore the
dining life is the real life. Tory and Liberal statesmen like each
other, but it is not because they are both expansive; it is because
they are both exclusive.
PATRIOTISM AND SPORT
I notice that some papers, especially
papers that call themselves patriotic, have fallen into quite a panic
over the fact that we have been twice beaten in the world of sport,
that a Frenchman has beaten us at golf, and that Belgians have beaten
us at rowing. I suppose that the incidents are important to any
people who ever believed in the self–satisfied English legend
on this subject. I suppose that there are men who vaguely believe
that we could never be beaten by a Frenchman, despite the fact that
we have often been beaten by Frenchmen, and once by a Frenchwoman. In
the old pictures in Punch you will find a recurring piece of
satire. The English caricaturists always assumed that a Frenchman
could not ride to hounds or enjoy English hunting. It did not seem to
occur to them that all the people who founded English hunting were
Frenchmen. All the Kings and nobles who originally rode to hounds
spoke French. Large numbers of those Englishmen who still ride to
hounds have French names. I suppose that the thing is important to
any one who is ignorant of such evident matters as these. I suppose
that if a man has ever believed that we English have some sacred and
separate right to be athletic, such reverses do appear quite enormous
and shocking. They feel as if, while the proper sun was rising in the
east, some other and unexpected sun had begun to rise in the
north–north–west by north. For the benefit, the moral and
intellectual benefit of such people, it may be worth while to point
out that the Anglo–Saxon has in these cases been defeated
precisely by those competitors whom he has always regarded as being
out of the running; by Latins, and by Latins of the most easy and
unstrenuous type; not only by Frenchman, but by Belgians. All this, I
say, is worth telling to any intelligent person who believes in the
haughty theory of Anglo–Saxon superiority. But, then, no
intelligent person does believe in the haughty theory of Anglo–Saxon
superiority. No quite genuine Englishman ever did believe in it. And
the genuine Englishman these defeats will in no respect dismay.
The genuine English patriot will know
that the strength of England has never depended upon any of these
things; that the glory of England has never had anything to do with
them, except in the opinion of a large section of the rich and a
loose section of the poor which copies the idleness of the rich.
These people will, of course, think too much of our failure, just as
they thought too much of our success. The typical Jingoes who have
admired their countrymen too much for being conquerors will,
doubtless, despise their countrymen too much for being conquered. But
the Englishman with any feeling for England will know that athletic
failures do not prove that England is weak, any more than athletic
successes proved that England was strong. The truth is that
athletics, like all other things, especially modern, are insanely
individualistic. The Englishmen who win sporting prizes are
exceptional among Englishmen, for the simple reason that they are
exceptional even among men. English athletes represent England just
about as much as Mr. Barnum’s freaks represent America. There
are so few of such people in the whole world that it is almost a
toss–up whether they are found in this or that country.
If any one wants a simple proof of
this, it is easy to find. When the great English athletes are not
exceptional Englishmen they are generally not Englishmen at all. Nay,
they are often representatives of races of which the average tone is
specially incompatible with athletics. For instance, the English are
supposed to rule the natives of India in virtue of their superior
hardiness, superior activity, superior health of body and mind. The
Hindus are supposed to be our subjects because they are less fond of
action, less fond of openness and the open air. In a word, less fond
of cricket. And, substantially, this is probably true, that the
Indians are less fond of cricket. All the same, if you ask among
Englishmen for the very best cricket–player, you will find that
he is an Indian. Or, to take another case: it is, broadly speaking,
true that the Jews are, as a race, pacific, intellectual, indifferent
to war, like the Indians, or, perhaps, contemptuous of war, like the
Chinese: nevertheless, of the very good prize–fighters, one or
two have been Jews.
This is one of the strongest
instances of the particular kind of evil that arises from our English
form of the worship of athletics. It concentrates too much upon the
success of individuals. It began, quite naturally and rightly, with
wanting England to win. The second stage was that it wanted some
Englishmen to win. The third stage was (in the ecstasy and agony of
some special competition) that it wanted one particular Englishman to
win. And the fourth stage was that when he had won, it discovered
that he was not even an Englishman.
This is one of the points, I think,
on which something might really be said for Lord Roberts and his
rather vague ideas which vary between rifle clubs and conscription.
Whatever may be the advantages or disadvantages otherwise of the
idea, it is at least an idea of procuring equality and a sort of
average in the athletic capacity of the people; it might conceivably
act as a corrective to our mere tendency to see ourselves in certain
exceptional athletes. As it is, there are millions of Englishmen who
really think that they are a muscular race because C.B. Fry is an
Englishman. And there are many of them who think vaguely that
athletics must belong to England because Ranjitsinhji is an Indian.
But the real historic strength of
England, physical and moral, has never had anything to do with this
athletic specialism; it has been rather hindered by it. Somebody said
that the Battle of Waterloo was won on Eton playing–fields. It
was a particularly unfortunate remark, for the English contribution
to the victory of Waterloo depended very much more than is common in
victories upon the steadiness of the rank and file in an almost
desperate situation. The Battle of Waterloo was won by the
stubbornness of the common soldier–that is to say, it was won
by the man who had never been to Eton. It was absurd to say that
Waterloo was won on Eton cricket–fields. But it might have been
fairly said that Waterloo was won on the village green, where clumsy
boys played a very clumsy cricket. In a word, it was the average of
the nation that was strong, and athletic glories do not indicate much
about the average of a nation. Waterloo was not won by good
cricket–players. But Waterloo was won by bad cricket–players,
by a mass of men who had some minimum of athletic instincts and
habits.
It is a good sign in a nation when
such things are done badly. It shows that all the people are doing
them. And it is a bad sign in a nation when such things are done very
well, for it shows that only a few experts and eccentrics are doing
them, and that the nation is merely looking on. Suppose that whenever
we heard of walking in England it always meant walking forty–five
miles a day without fatigue. We should be perfectly certain that only
a few men were walking at all, and that all the other British
subjects were being wheeled about in Bath–chairs. But if when
we hear of walking it means slow walking, painful walking, and
frequent fatigue, then we know that the mass of the nation still is
walking. We know that England is still literally on its feet.
The difficulty is therefore that the
actual raising of the standard of athletics has probably been bad for
national athleticism. Instead of the tournament being a healthy mêlée
into which any ordinary man would rush and take his chance, it has
become a fenced and guarded tilting–yard for the collision of
particular champions against whom no ordinary man would pit himself
or even be permitted to pit himself. If Waterloo was won on Eton
cricket–fields it was because Eton cricket was probably much
more careless then than it is now. As long as the game was a game,
everybody wanted to join in it. When it becomes an art, every one
wants to look at it. When it was frivolous it may have won Waterloo:
when it was serious and efficient it lost Magersfontein.
In the Waterloo period there was a
general rough–and–tumble athleticism among average
Englishmen. It cannot be re–created by cricket, or by
conscription, or by any artificial means. It was a thing of the soul.
It came out of laughter, religion, and the spirit of the place. But
it was like the modern French duel in this–that it might happen
to anybody. If I were a French journalist it might really happen that
Monsieur Clemenceau might challenge me to meet him with pistols. But
I do not think that it is at all likely that Mr. C. B. Fry will ever
challenge me to meet him with cricket–bats.
AN ESSAY ON TWO CITIES
A little while ago I fell out of
England into the town of Paris. If a man fell out of the moon into
the town of Paris he would know that it was the capital of a great
nation. If, however, he fell (perhaps off some other side of the
moon) so as to hit the city of London, he would not know so well that
it was the capital of a great nation; at any rate, he would not know
that the nation was so great as it is. This would be so even on the
assumption that the man from the moon could not read our alphabet, as
presumably he could not, unless elementary education in that planet
has gone to rather unsuspected lengths. But it is true that a great
part of the distinctive quality which separates Paris from London may
be even seen in the names. Real democrats always insist that England
is an aristocratic country. Real aristocrats always insist (for some
mysterious reason) that it is a democratic country. But if any one
has any real doubt about the matter let him consider simply the names
of the streets. Nearly all the streets out of the Strand, for
instance, are named after the first name, second name, third name,
fourth, fifth, and sixth names of some particular noble family; after
their relations, connections, or places of residence–Arundel
Street, Norfolk Street, Villiers Street, Bedford Street, Southampton
Street, and any number of others. The names are varied, so as to
introduce the same family under all sorts of different surnames. Thus
we have Arundel Street and also Norfolk Street; thus we have
Buckingham Street and also Villiers Street. To say that this is not
aristocracy is simply intellectual impudence. I am an ordinary
citizen, and my name is Gilbert Keith Chesterton; and I confess that
if I found three streets in a row in the Strand, the first called
Gilbert Street, the second Keith Street, and the third Chesterton
Street, I should consider that I had become a somewhat more important
person in the commonwealth than was altogether good for its health.
If Frenchmen ran London (which God forbid!), they would think it
quite as ludicrous that those streets should be named after the Duke
of Buckingham as that they should be named after me. They are streets
out of one of the main thoroughfares of London. If French methods
were adopted, one of them would be called Shakspere Street, another
Cromwell Street, another Wordsworth Street; there would be statues of
each of these persons at the end of each of these streets, and any
streets left over would be named after the date on which the Reform
Bill was passed or the Penny Postage established.
Suppose a man tried to find people in
London by the names of the places. It would make a fine farce,
illustrating our illogicality. Our hero having once realised that
Buckingham Street was named after the Buckingham family, would
naturally walk into Buckingham Palace in search of the Duke of
Buckingham. To his astonishment he would meet somebody quite
different. His simple lunar logic would lead him to suppose that if
he wanted the Duke of Marlborough (which seems unlikely) he would
find him at Marlborough House. He would find the Prince of Wales.
When at last he understood that the Marlboroughs live at Blenheim,
named after the great Marlborough’s victory, he would, no
doubt, go there. But he would again find himself in error if, acting
upon this principle, he tried to find the Duke of Wellington, and
told the cabman to drive to Waterloo. I wonder that no one has
written a wild romance about the adventures of such an alien, seeking
the great English aristocrats, and only guided by the names; looking
for the Duke of Bedford in the town of that name, seeking for some
trace of the Duke of Norfolk in Norfolk. He might sail for Wellington
in New Zealand to find the ancient seat of the Wellingtons. The last
scene might show him trying to learn Welsh in order to converse with
the Prince of Wales.
But even if the imaginary traveller
knew no alphabet of this earth at all, I think it would still be
possible to suppose him seeing a difference between London and Paris,
and, upon the whole, the real difference. He would not be able to
read the words “Quai Voltaire;” but he would see the
sneering statue and the hard, straight roads; without having heard of
Voltaire he would understand that the city was Voltairean. He would
not know that Fleet Street was named after the Fleet Prison. But the
same national spirit which kept the Fleet Prison closed and narrow
still keeps Fleet Street closed and narrow. Or, if you will, you may
call Fleet Street cosy, and the Fleet Prison cosy. I think I could be
more comfortable in the Fleet Prison, in an English way of comfort,
than just under the statue of Voltaire. I think that the man from the
moon would know France without knowing French; I think that he would
know England without having heard the word. For in the last resort
all men talk by signs. To talk by statues is to talk by signs; to
talk by cities is to talk by signs. Pillars, palaces, cathedrals,
temples, pyramids, are an enormous dumb alphabet: as if some giant
held up his fingers of stone. The most important things at the last
are always said by signs, even if, like the Cross on St. Paul’s,
they are signs in heaven. If men do not understand signs, they will
never understand words.
For my part, I should be inclined to
suggest that the chief object of education should be to restore
simplicity. If you like to put it so, the chief object of education
is not to learn things; nay, the chief object of education is to
unlearn things. The chief object of education is to unlearn all the
weariness and wickedness of the world and to get back into that state
of exhilaration we all instinctively celebrate when we write by
preference of children and of boys. If I were an examiner appointed
to examine all examiners (which does not at present appear probable),
I would not only ask the teachers how much knowledge they had
imparted; I would ask them how much splendid and scornful ignorance
they had erected, like some royal tower in arms. But, in any case, I
would insist that people should have so much simplicity as would
enable them to see things suddenly and to see things as they are. I
do not care so much whether they can read the names over the shops. I
do care very much whether they can read the shops. I do not feel
deeply troubled as to whether they can tell where London is on the
map so long as they can tell where Brixton is on the way home. I do
not even mind whether they can put two and two together in the
mathematical sense; I am content if they can put two and two together
in the metaphorical sense. But all this longer statement of an
obvious view comes back to the metaphor I have employed. I do not
care a dump whether they know the alphabet, so long as they know the
dumb alphabet.
Unfortunately, I have noticed in many
aspects of our popular education that this is not done at all. One
teaches our London children to see London with abrupt and simple
eyes. And London is far more difficult to see properly than any other
place. London is a riddle. Paris is an explanation. The education of
the Parisian child is something corresponding to the clear avenues
and the exact squares of Paris. When the Parisian boy has done
learning about the French reason and the Roman order he can go out
and see the thing repeated in the shapes of many shining public
places, in the angles of many streets. But when the English boy goes
out, after learning about a vague progress and idealism, he cannot
see it anywhere. He cannot see anything anywhere, except Sapolio and
the Daily Mail. We must either alter London to suit the ideals
of our education, or else alter our education to suit the great
beauty of London.
FRENCH AND ENGLISH
It is obvious that there is a great
deal of difference between being international and being
cosmopolitan. All good men are international. Nearly all bad men are
cosmopolitan. If we are to be international we must be national. And
it is largely because those who call themselves the friends of peace
have not dwelt sufficiently on this distinction that they do not
impress the bulk of any of the nations to which they belong.
International peace means a peace between nations, not a peace after
the destruction of nations, like the Buddhist peace after the
destruction of personality. The golden age of the good European is
like the heaven of the Christian: it is a place where people will
love each other; not like the heaven of the Hindu, a place where they
will be each other. And in the case of national character this can be
seen in a curious way. It will generally be found, I think, that the
more a man really appreciates and admires the soul of another people
the less he will attempt to imitate it; he will be conscious that
there is something in it too deep and too unmanageable to imitate.
The Englishman who has a fancy for France will try to be French; the
Englishman who admires France will remain obstinately English. This
is to be particularly noticed in the case of our relations with the
French, because it is one of the outstanding peculiarities of the
French that their vices are all on the surface, and their
extraordinary virtues concealed. One might almost say that their
vices are the flower of their virtues.
Thus their obscenity is the
expression of their passionate love of dragging all things into the
light. The avarice of their peasants means the independence of their
peasants. What the English call their rudeness in the streets is a
phase of their social equality. The worried look of their women is
connected with the responsibility of their women; and a certain
unconscious brutality of hurry and gesture in the men is related to
their inexhaustible and extraordinary military courage. Of all
countries, therefore, France is the worst country for a superficial
fool to admire. Let a fool hate France: if the fool loves it he will
soon be a knave. He will certainly admire it, not only for the things
that are not creditable, but actually for the things that are not
there. He will admire the grace and indolence of the most industrious
people in the world. He will admire the romance and fantasy of the
most determinedly respectable and commonplace people in the world.
This mistake the Englishman will make if he admires France too
hastily; but the mistake that he makes about France will be slight
compared with the mistake that he makes about himself. An Englishman
who professes really to like French realistic novels, really to be at
home in a French modern theatre, really to experience no shock on
first seeing the savage French caricatures, is making a mistake very
dangerous for his own sincerity. He is admiring something he does not
understand. He is reaping where he has not sown, and taking up where
he has not laid down; he is trying to taste the fruit when he has
never toiled over the tree. He is trying to pluck the exquisite fruit
of French cynicism, when he has never tilled the rude but rich soil
of French virtue.
The thing can only be made clear to
Englishmen by turning it round. Suppose a Frenchman came out of
democratic France to live in England, where the shadow of the great
houses still falls everywhere, and where even freedom was, in its
origin, aristocratic. If the Frenchman saw our aristocracy and liked
it, if he saw our snobbishness and liked it, if he set himself to
imitate it, we all know what we should feel. We all know that we
should feel that that particular Frenchman was a repulsive little
gnat. He would be imitating English aristocracy; he would be
imitating the English vice. But he would not even understand the vice
he plagiarised: especially he would not understand that the vice is
partly a virtue. He would not understand those elements in the
English which balance snobbishness and make it human: the great
kindness of the English, their hospitality, their unconscious poetry,
their sentimental conservatism, which really admires the gentry. The
French Royalist sees that the English like their King. But he does
not grasp that while it is base to worship a King, it is almost noble
to worship a powerless King. The impotence of the Hanoverian
Sovereigns has raised the English loyal subject almost to the
chivalry and dignity of a Jacobite. The Frenchman sees that the
English servant is respectful: he does not realise that he is also
disrespectful; that there is an English legend of the humorous and
faithful servant, who is as much a personality as his master; the
Caleb Balderstone, the Sam Weller. He sees that the English do admire
a nobleman; he does not allow for the fact that they admire a
nobleman most when he does not behave like one. They like a noble to
be unconscious and amiable: the slave may be humble, but the master
must not be proud. The master is Life, as they would like to enjoy
it; and among the joys they desire in him there is none which they
desire more sincerely than that of generosity, of throwing money
about among mankind, or, to use the noble mediæval word,
largesse–the joy of largeness. That is why a cabman tells you
are no gentleman if you give him his correct fare. Not only his
pocket, but his soul is hurt. You have wounded his ideal. You have
defaced his vision of the perfect aristocrat. All this is really very
subtle and elusive; it is very difficult to separate what is mere
slavishness from what is a sort of vicarious nobility in the English
love of a lord. And no Frenchman could easily grasp it at all. He
would think it was mere slavishness; and if he liked it, he would be
a slave. So every Englishman must (at first) feel French candour to
be mere brutality. And if he likes it, he is a brute. These national
merits must not be understood so easily. It requires long years of
plenitude and quiet, the slow growth of great parks, the seasoning of
oaken beams, the dark enrichment of red wine in cellars and in inns,
all the leisure and the life of England through many centuries, to
produce at last the generous and genial fruit of English
snobbishness. And it requires battery and barricade, songs in the
streets, and ragged men dead for an idea, to produce and justify the
terrible flower of French indecency.
When I was in Paris a short time ago,
I went with an English friend of mine to an extremely brilliant and
rapid succession of French plays, each occupying about twenty
minutes. They were all astonishingly effective; but there was one of
them which was so effective that my friend and I fought about it
outside, and had almost to be separated by the police. It was
intended to indicate how men really behaved in a wreck or naval
disaster, how they break down, how they scream, how they fight each
other without object and in a mere hatred of everything. And then
there was added, with all that horrible irony which Voltaire began, a
scene in which a great statesman made a speech over their bodies,
saying that they were all heroes and had died in a fraternal embrace.
My friend and I came out of this theatre, and as he had lived long in
Paris, he said, like a Frenchman: “What admirable artistic
arrangement! Is it not exquisite?” “No,” I replied,
assuming as far as possible the traditional attitude of John Bull in
the pictures in Punch–”No, it is not exquisite.
Perhaps it is unmeaning; if it is unmeaning I do not mind. But if it
has a meaning I know what the meaning is; it is that under all their
pageant of chivalry men are not only beasts, but even hunted beasts.
I do not know much of humanity, especially when humanity talks in
French. But I know when a thing is meant to uplift the human soul,
and when it is meant to depress it. I know that ‘Cyrano de
Bergerac’ (where the actors talked even quicker) was meant to
encourage man. And I know that this was meant to discourage him.”
“These sentimental and moral views of art,” began my
friend, but I broke into his words as a light broke into my mind.
“Let me say to you,” I said, “what Jaurès
said to Liebknecht at the Socialist Conference: ‘You have not
died on the barricades.’ You are an Englishman, as I am, and
you ought to be as amiable as I am. These people have some right to
be terrible in art, for they have been terrible in politics. They may
endure mock tortures on the stage; they have seen real tortures in
the streets. They have been hurt for the idea of Democracy. They have
been hurt for the idea of Catholicism. It is not so utterly unnatural
to them that they should be hurt for the idea of literature. But, by
blazes, it is altogether unnatural to me! And the worst thing of all
is that I, who am an Englishman, loving comfort, should find comfort
in such things as this. The French do not seek comfort here, but
rather unrest. This restless people seeks to keep itself in a
perpetual agony of the revolutionary mood. Frenchmen, seeking
revolution, may find the humiliation of humanity inspiring. But God
forbid that two pleasure–seeking Englishmen should ever find it
pleasant!”
THE ZOLA CONTROVERSY
The difference between two great
nations can be illustrated by the coincidence that at this moment
both France and England are engaged in discussing the memorial of a
literary man. France is considering the celebration of the late Zola,
England is considering that of the recently deceased Shakspere. There
is some national significance, it may be, in the time that has
elapsed. Some will find impatience and indelicacy in this early
attack on Zola or deification of him; but the nation which has sat
still for three hundred years after Shakspere’s funeral may be
considered, perhaps, to have carried delicacy too far. But much
deeper things are involved than the mere matter of time. The point of
the contrast is that the French are discussing whether there shall be
any monument, while the English are discussing only what the monument
shall be. In other words, the French are discussing a living
question, while we are discussing a dead one. Or rather, not a dead
one, but a settled one, which is quite a different thing.
When a thing of the intellect is
settled it is not dead: rather it is immortal. The multiplication
table is immortal, and so is the fame of Shakspere. But the fame of
Zola is not dead or not immortal; it is at its crisis, it is in the
balance; and may be found wanting. The French, therefore, are quite
right in considering it a living question. It is still living as a
question, because it is not yet solved. But Shakspere is not a living
question: he is a living answer.
For my part, therefore, I think the
French Zola controversy much more practical and exciting than the
English Shakspere one. The admission of Zola to the Pantheon may be
regarded as defining Zola’s position. But nobody could say that
a statue of Shakspere, even fifty feet high, on the top of St. Paul’s
Cathedral, could define Shakspere’s position. It only defines
our position towards Shakspere. It is he who is fixed; it is we who
are unstable. The nearest approach to an English parallel to the Zola
case would be furnished if it were proposed to put some savagely
controversial and largely repulsive author among the ashes of the
greatest English poets. Suppose, for instance, it were proposed to
bury Mr. Rudyard Kipling in Westminster Abbey. I should be against
burying him in Westminster Abbey; first, because he is still alive
(and here I think even he himself might admit the justice of my
protest); and second, because I should like to reserve that rapidly
narrowing space for the great permanent examples, not for the
interesting foreign interruptions, of English literature. I would not
have either Mr. Kipling or Mr. George Moore in Westminster Abbey,
though Mr. Kipling has certainly caught even more cleverly than Mr.
Moore the lucid and cool cruelty of the French short story. I am very
sure that Geoffrey Chaucer and Joseph Addison get on very well
together in the Poets’ Corner, despite the centuries that
sunder them. But I feel that Mr. George Moore would be much happier
in Pere–la–Chaise, with a riotous statue by Rodin on the
top of him; and Mr. Kipling much happier under some huge Asiatic
monument, carved with all the cruelties of the gods.
As to the affair of the English
monument to Shakspere, every people has its own mode of
commemoration, and I think there is a great deal to be said for ours.
There is the French monumental style, which consists in erecting very
pompous statues, very well done. There is the German monumental
style, which consists in erecting very pompous statues, badly done.
And there is the English monumental method, the great English way
with statues, which consists in not erecting them at all. A statue
may be dignified; but the absence of a statue is always dignified.
For my part, I feel there is something national, something
wholesomely symbolic, in the fact that there is no statue of
Shakspere. There is, of course, one in Leicester Square; but the very
place where it stands shows that it was put up by a foreigner for
foreigners. There is surely something modest and manly about not
attempting to express our greatest poet in the plastic arts in which
we do not excel. We honour Shakspere as the Jews honour God–by
not daring to make of him a graven image. Our sculpture, our statues,
are good enough for bankers and philanthropists, who are our curse:
not good enough for him, who is our benediction. Why should we
celebrate the very art in which we triumph by the very art in which
we fail?
England is most easily understood as
the country of amateurs. It is especially the country of amateur
soldiers (that is, of Volunteers), of amateur statesmen (that is, of
aristocrats), and it is not unreasonable or out of keeping that it
should be rather specially the country of a careless and lounging
view of literature. Shakspere has no academic monument for the same
reason that he had no academic education. He had small Latin and less
Greek, and (in the same spirit) he has never been commemorated in
Latin epitaphs or Greek marble. If there is nothing clear and fixed
about the emblems of his fame, it is because there was nothing clear
and fixed about the origins of it. Those great schools and
Universities which watch a man in his youth may record him in his
death; but Shakspere had no such unifying traditions. We can only say
of him what we can say of Dickens. We can only say that he came from
nowhere and that he went everywhere. For him a monument in any place
is out of place. A cold statue in a certain square is unsuitable to
him as it would be unsuitable to Dickens. If we put up a statue of
Dickens in Portland Place to–morrow we should feel the
stiffness as unnatural. We should fear that the statue might stroll
about the street at night.
But in France the question of whether
Zola shall go to the Panthéon when he is dead is quite as
practicable as the question whether he should go to prison when he
was alive. It is the problem of whether the nation shall take one
turn of thought or another. In raising a monument to Zola they do not
raise merely a trophy, but a finger–post. The question is one
which will have to be settled in most European countries; but like
all such questions, it has come first to a head in France; because
France is the battlefield of Christendom. That question is, of
course, roughly this: whether in that ill–defined area of
verbal licence on certain dangerous topics it is an extenuation of
indelicacy or an aggravation of it that the indelicacy was deliberate
and solemn. Is indecency more indecent if it is grave, or more
indecent if it is gay? For my part, I belong to an old school in this
matter. When a book or a play strikes me as a crime, I am not
disarmed by being told that it is a serious crime. If a man has
written something vile, I am not comforted by the explanation that he
quite meant to do it. I know all the evils of flippancy; I do not
like the man who laughs at the sight of virtue. But I prefer him to
the man who weeps at the sight of virtue and complains bitterly of
there being any such thing. I am not reassured, when ethics are as
wild as cannibalism, by the fact that they are also as grave and
sincere as suicide. And I think there is an obvious fallacy in the
bitter contrasts drawn by some moderns between the aversion to
Ibsen’s “Ghosts” and the popularity of some such
joke as “Dear Old Charlie.” Surely there is nothing
mysterious or unphilosophic in the popular preference. The joke of
“Dear Old Charlie” is passed–because it is a joke.
“Ghosts” are exorcised–because they are ghosts.
This is, of course, the whole
question of Zola. I am grown up, and I do not worry myself much about
Zola’s immorality. The thing I cannot stand is his morality. If
ever a man on this earth lived to embody the tremendous text, “But
if the light in your body be darkness, how great is the darkness,”
it was certainly he. Great men like Ariosto, Rabelais, and Shakspere
fall in foul places, flounder in violent but venial sin, sprawl for
pages, exposing their gigantic weakness, are dirty, are indefensible;
and then they struggle up again and can still speak with a convincing
kindness and an unbroken honour of the best things in the world:
Rabelais, of the instruction of ardent and austere youth; Ariosto, of
holy chivalry; Shakspere, of the splendid stillness of mercy. But in
Zola even the ideals are undesirable; Zola’s mercy is colder
than justice–nay, Zola’s mercy is more bitter in the
mouth than injustice. When Zola shows us an ideal training he does
not take us, like Rabelais, into the happy fields of humanist
learning. He takes us into the schools of inhumanist learning, where
there are neither books nor flowers, nor wine nor wisdom, but only
deformities in glass bottles, and where the rule is taught from the
exceptions. Zola’s truth answers the exact description of the
skeleton in the cupboard; that is, it is something of which a
domestic custom forbids the discovery, but which is quite dead, even
when it is discovered. Macaulay said that the Puritans hated
bear–baiting, not because it gave pain to the bear, but because
it gave pleasure to the spectators. Of such substance also was this
Puritan who had lost his God. A Puritan of this type is worse than
the Puritan who hates pleasure because there is evil in it. This man
actually hates evil because there is pleasure in it. Zola was worse
than a pornographer, he was a pessimist. He did worse than encourage
sin: he encouraged discouragement. He made lust loathsome because to
him lust meant life.
OXFORD FROM WITHOUT
Some time ago I ventured to defend
that race of hunted and persecuted outlaws, the Bishops; but until
this week I had no idea of how much persecuted they were. For
instance, the Bishop of Birmingham made some extremely sensible
remarks in the House of Lords, to the effect that Oxford and
Cambridge were (as everybody knows they are) far too much merely
plutocratic playgrounds. One would have thought that an Anglican
Bishop might be allowed to know something about the English
University system, and even to have, if anything, some bias in its
favour. But (as I pointed out) the rollicking Radicalism of Bishops
has to be restrained. The man who writes the notes in the weekly
paper called the Outlook feels that it is his business to
restrain it. The passage has such simple sublimity that I must quote
it—“Dr. Gore talked unworthily of his reputation when he
spoke of the older Universities as playgrounds for the rich and idle.
In the first place, the rich men there are not idle. Some of the rich
men are, and so are some of the poor men. On the whole, the sons of
noble and wealthy families keep up the best traditions of academic
life.”
So far this seems all very nice. It
is a part of the universal principle on which Englishmen have acted
in recent years. As you will not try to make the best people the most
powerful people, persuade yourselves that the most powerful people
are the best people. Mad Frenchmen and Irishmen try to realise the
ideal. To you belongs the nobler (and much easier) task of idealising
the real. First give your Universities entirely into the power of the
rich; then let the rich start traditions; and then congratulate
yourselves on the fact that the sons of the rich keep up these
traditions. All that is quite simple and jolly. But then this critic,
who crushes Dr. Gore from the high throne of the Outlook, goes
on in a way that is really perplexing. “It is distinctly
advantageous,” he says, “that rich and poor–i.
e., young men with a smooth path in life before them, and those
who have to hew out a road for themselves–should be brought
into association. Each class learns a great deal from the other. On
the one side, social conceit and exclusiveness give way to the free
spirit of competition amongst all classes; on the other side,
angularities and prejudices are rubbed away.” Even this I might
have swallowed. But the paragraph concludes with this extraordinary
sentence: “We get the net result in such careers as those of
Lord Milner, Lord Curzon, and Mr. Asquith.”
Those three names lay my intellect
prostrate. The rest of the argument I understand quite well. The
social exclusiveness of aristocrats at Oxford and Cambridge gives way
before the free spirit of competition amongst all classes. That is to
say, there is at Oxford so hot and keen a struggle, consisting of
coal–heavers, London clerks, gypsies, navvies, drapers’
assistants, grocers’ assistants–in short, all the classes
that make up the bulk of England–there is such a fierce
competition at Oxford among all these people that in its presence
aristocratic exclusiveness gives way. That is all quite clear. I am
not quite sure about the facts, but I quite understand the argument.
But then, having been called upon to contemplate this bracing picture
of a boisterous turmoil of all the classes of England, I am suddenly
asked to accept as example of it, Lord Milner, Lord Curzon, and the
present Chancellor of the Exchequer. What part do these gentlemen
play in the mental process? Is Lord Curzon one of the rugged and
ragged poor men whose angularities have been rubbed away? Or is he
one of those whom Oxford immediately deprived of all kind of social
exclusiveness? His Oxford reputation does not seem to bear out either
account of him. To regard Lord Milner as a typical product of Oxford
would surely be unfair. It would be to deprive the educational
tradition of Germany of one of its most typical products. English
aristocrats have their faults, but they are not at all like Lord
Milner. What Mr. Asquith was meant to prove, whether he was a rich
man who lost his exclusiveness, or a poor man who lost his angles, I
am utterly unable to conceive.
There
is, however, one mild but very evident truth that might perhaps be
mentioned. And it is this: that none of those three excellent persons
is, or ever has been, a poor man in the sense that that word is
understood by the overwhelming majority of the English nation. There
are no poor men at Oxford in the sense that the majority of men in
the street are poor. The very fact that the writer in the Outlook
can talk about such people as poor shows that he does not understand
what the modern problem is. His kind of poor man rather reminds me of
the Earl in the ballad by that great English satirist, Sir W.S.
Gilbert, whose angles (very acute angles) had, I fear, never been
rubbed down by an old English University. The reader will remember
that when the Periwinkle–girl was adored by two Dukes, the poet
added—“A third adorer had the girl, A man of lowly
station; A miserable grovelling Earl Besought her approbation.”
Perhaps,
indeed, some allusion to our University system, and to the universal
clash in it of all the classes of the community, may be found in the
verse a little farther on, which says—“He’d had, it
happily befell, A decent education; His views would have
befitted well A far superior station.”
Possibly there was as simple a chasm
between Lord Curzon and Lord Milner. But I am afraid that the chasm
will become almost imperceptible, a microscopic crack, if we compare
it with the chasm that separates either or both of them from the
people of this country.
Of course the truth is exactly as the
Bishop of Birmingham put it. I am sure that he did not put it in any
unkindly or contemptuous spirit towards those old English seats of
learning, which whether they are or are not seats of learning, are,
at any rate, old and English, and those are two very good things to
be. The Old English University is a playground for the governing
class. That does not prove that it is a bad thing; it might prove
that it was a very good thing. Certainly if there is a governing
class, let there be a playground for the governing class. I would
much rather be ruled by men who know how to play than by men who do
not know how to play. Granted that we are to be governed by a rich
section of the community, it is certainly very important that that
section should be kept tolerably genial and jolly. If the sensitive
man on the Outlook does not like the phrase, “Playground
of the rich,” I can suggest a phrase that describes such a
place as Oxford perhaps with more precision. It is a place for
humanising those who might otherwise be tyrants, or even experts.
To pretend that the aristocrat meets
all classes at Oxford is too ludicrous to be worth discussion. But it
may be true that he meets more different kinds of men than he would
meet under a strictly aristocratic regime of private tutors
and small schools. It all comes back to the fact that the English, if
they were resolved to have an aristocracy, were at least resolved to
have a good–natured aristocracy. And it is due to them to say
that almost alone among the peoples of the world, they have succeeded
in getting one. One could almost tolerate the thing, if it were not
for the praise of it. One might endure Oxford, but not the Outlook.
When the poor man at Oxford loses his
angles (which means, I suppose, his independence), he may perhaps,
even if his poverty is of that highly relative type possible at
Oxford, gain a certain amount of worldly advantage from the surrender
of those angles. I must confess, however, that I can imagine nothing
nastier than to lose one’s angles. It seems to me that a desire
to retain some angles about one’s person is a desire common to
all those human beings who do not set their ultimate hopes upon
looking like Humpty–Dumpty. Our angles are simply our shapes. I
cannot imagine any phrase more full of the subtle and exquisite
vileness which is poisoning and weakening our country than such a
phrase as this, about the desirability of rubbing down the
angularities of poor men. Reduced to permanent and practical human
speech, it means nothing whatever except the corrupting of that first
human sense of justice which is the critic of all human institutions.
It is not in any such spirit of
facile and reckless reassurance that we should approach the really
difficult problem of the delicate virtues and the deep dangers of our
two historic seats of learning. A good son does not easily admit that
his sick mother is dying; but neither does a good son cheerily assert
that she is “all right.” There are many good arguments
for leaving the two historic Universities exactly as they are. There
are many good arguments for smashing them or altering them entirely.
But in either case the plain truth told by the Bishop of Birmingham
remains. If these Universities were destroyed, they would not be
destroyed as Universities. If they are preserved, they will not be
preserved as Universities. They will be preserved strictly and
literally as playgrounds; places valued for their hours of leisure
more than for their hours of work. I do not say that this is
unreasonable; as a matter of private temperament I find it
attractive. It is not only possible to say a great deal in praise of
play; it is really possible to say the highest things in praise of
it. It might reasonably be maintained that the true object of all
human life is play. Earth is a task garden; heaven is a playground.
To be at last in such secure innocence that one can juggle with the
universe and the stars, to be so good that one can treat everything
as a joke–that may be, perhaps, the real end and final holiday
of human souls. When we are really holy we may regard the Universe as
a lark; so perhaps it is not essentially wrong to regard the
University as a lark. But the plain and present fact is that our
upper classes do regard the University as a lark, and do not regard
it as a University. It also happens very often that through some
oversight they neglect to provide themselves with that extreme degree
of holiness which I have postulated as a necessary preliminary to
such indulgence in the higher frivolity.
Humanity, always dreaming of a happy
race, free, fantastic, and at ease, has sometimes pictured them in
some mystical island, sometimes in some celestial city, sometimes as
fairies, gods, or citizens of Atlantis. But one method in which it
has often indulged is to picture them as aristocrats, as a special
human class that could actually be seen hunting in the woods or
driving about the streets. And this never was (as some silly Germans
say) a worship of pride and scorn; mankind never really admired
pride; mankind never had any thing but a scorn for scorn. It was a
worship of the spectacle of happiness; especially of the spectacle of
youth. This is what the old Universities in their noblest aspect
really are; and this is why there is always something to be said for
keeping them as they are. Aristocracy is not a tyranny; it is not
even merely a spell. It is a vision. It is a deliberate indulgence in
a certain picture of pleasure painted for the purpose; every Duchess
is (in an innocent sense) painted, like Gainsborough’s “Duchess
of Devonshire.” She is only beautiful because, at the back of
all, the English people wanted her to be beautiful. In the same way,
the lads at Oxford and Cambridge are only larking because England, in
the depths of its solemn soul, really wishes them to lark. All this
is very human and pardonable, and would be even harmless if there
were no such things in the world as danger and honour and
intellectual responsibility. But if aristocracy is a vision, it is
perhaps the most unpractical of all visions. It is not a working way
of doing things to put all your happiest people on a lighted platform
and stare only at them. It is not a working way of managing education
to be entirely content with the mere fact that you have (to a degree
unexampled in the world) given the luckiest boys the jolliest time.
It would be easy enough, like the writer in the Outlook, to
enjoy the pleasures and deny the perils. Oh what a happy place
England would be to live in if only one did not love it!
WOMAN
A correspondent has written me an
able and interesting letter in the matter of some allusions of mine
to the subject of communal kitchens. He defends communal kitchens
very lucidly from the standpoint of the calculating collectivist;
but, like many of his school, he cannot apparently grasp that there
is another test of the whole matter, with which such calculation has
nothing at all to do. He knows it would be cheaper if a number of us
ate at the same time, so as to use the same table. So it would. It
would also be cheaper if a number of us slept at different times, so
as to use the same pair of trousers. But the question is not how
cheap are we buying a thing, but what are we buying? It is cheap to
own a slave. And it is cheaper still to be a slave.
My correspondent also says that the
habit of dining out in restaurants, etc., is growing. So, I believe,
is the habit of committing suicide. I do not desire to connect the
two facts together. It seems fairly clear that a man could not dine
at a restaurant because he had just committed suicide; and it would
be extreme, perhaps, to suggest that he commits suicide because he
has just dined at a restaurant. But the two cases, when put side by
side, are enough to indicate the falsity and poltroonery of this
eternal modern argument from what is in fashion. The question for
brave men is not whether a certain thing is increasing; the question
is whether we are increasing it. I dine very often in restaurants
because the nature of my trade makes it convenient: but if I thought
that by dining in restaurants I was working for the creation of
communal meals, I would never enter a restaurant again; I would carry
bread and cheese in my pocket or eat chocolate out of automatic
machines. For the personal element in some things is sacred. I heard
Mr. Will Crooks put it perfectly the other day: “The most
sacred thing is to be able to shut your own door.”
My correspondent says, “Would
not our women be spared the drudgery of cooking and all its attendant
worries, leaving them free for higher culture?” The first thing
that occurs to me to say about this is very simple, and is, I
imagine, a part of all our experience. If my correspondent can find
any way of preventing women from worrying, he will indeed be a
remarkable man. I think the matter is a much deeper one. First of
all, my correspondent overlooks a distinction which is elementary in
our human nature. Theoretically, I suppose, every one would like to
be freed from worries. But nobody in the world would always like to
be freed from worrying occupations. I should very much like (as far
as my feelings at the moment go) to be free from the consuming
nuisance of writing this article. But it does not follow that I
should like to be free from the consuming nuisance of being a
journalist. Because we are worried about a thing, it does not follow
that we are not interested in it. The truth is the other way. If we
are not interested, why on earth should we be worried? Women are
worried about housekeeping, but those that are most interested are
the most worried. Women are still more worried about their husbands
and their children. And I suppose if we strangled the children and
poleaxed the husbands it would leave women free for higher culture.
That is, it would leave them free to begin to worry about that. For
women would worry about higher culture as much as they worry about
everything else.
I believe this way of talking about
women and their higher culture is almost entirely a growth of the
classes which (unlike the journalistic class to which I belong) have
always a reasonable amount of money. One odd thing I specially
notice. Those who write like this seem entirely to forget the
existence of the working and wage–earning classes. They say
eternally, like my correspondent, that the ordinary woman is always a
drudge. And what, in the name of the Nine Gods, is the ordinary man?
These people seem to think that the ordinary man is a Cabinet
Minister. They are always talking about man going forth to wield
power, to carve his own way, to stamp his individuality on the world,
to command and to be obeyed. This may be true of a certain class.
Dukes, perhaps, are not drudges; but, then, neither are Duchesses.
The Ladies and Gentlemen of the Smart Set are quite free for the
higher culture, which consists chiefly of motoring and Bridge. But
the ordinary man who typifies and constitutes the millions that make
up our civilisation is no more free for the higher culture than his
wife is.
Indeed, he is not so free. Of the two
sexes the woman is in the more powerful position. For the average
woman is at the head of something with which she can do as she likes;
the average man has to obey orders and do nothing else. He has to put
one dull brick on another dull brick, and do nothing else; he has to
add one dull figure to another dull figure, and do nothing else. The
woman’s world is a small one, perhaps, but she can alter it.
The woman can tell the tradesman with whom she deals some realistic
things about himself. The clerk who does this to the manager
generally gets the sack, or shall we say (to avoid the vulgarism),
finds himself free for higher culture. Above all, as I said in my
previous article, the woman does work which is in some small degree
creative and individual. She can put the flowers or the furniture in
fancy arrangements of her own. I fear the bricklayer cannot put the
bricks in fancy arrangements of his own, without disaster to himself
and others. If the woman is only putting a patch into a carpet, she
can choose the thing with regard to colour. I fear it would not do
for the office boy dispatching a parcel to choose his stamps with a
view to colour; to prefer the tender mauve of the sixpenny to the
crude scarlet of the penny stamp. A woman cooking may not always cook
artistically; still she can cook artistically. She can introduce a
personal and imperceptible alteration into the composition of a soup.
The clerk is not encouraged to introduce a personal and imperceptible
alteration into the figures in a ledger.
The trouble is that the real question
I raised is not discussed. It is argued as a problem in pennies, not
as a problem in people. It is not the proposals of these reformers
that I feel to be false so much as their temper and their arguments.
I am not nearly so certain that communal kitchens are wrong as I am
that the defenders of communal kitchens are wrong. Of course, for one
thing, there is a vast difference between the communal kitchens of
which I spoke and the communal meal (monstrum horrendum, informe)
which the darker and wilder mind of my correspondent diabolically
calls up. But in both the trouble is that their defenders will not
defend them humanly as human institutions. They will not interest
themselves in the staring psychological fact that there are some
things that a man or a woman, as the case may be, wishes to do for
himself or herself. He or she must do it inventively, creatively,
artistically, individually–in a word, badly. Choosing your wife
(say) is one of these things. Is choosing your husband’s dinner
one of these things? That is the whole question: it is never asked.
And then the higher culture. I know
that culture. I would not set any man free for it if I could help it.
The effect of it on the rich men who are free for it is so horrible
that it is worse than any of the other amusements of the
millionaire–worse than gambling, worse even than philanthropy.
It means thinking the smallest poet in Belgium greater than the
greatest poet of England. It means losing every democratic sympathy.
It means being unable to talk to a navvy about sport, or about beer,
or about the Bible, or about the Derby, or about patriotism, or about
anything whatever that he, the navvy, wants to talk about. It means
taking literature seriously, a very amateurish thing to do. It means
pardoning indecency only when it is gloomy indecency. Its disciples
will call a spade a spade; but only when it is a grave–digger’s
spade. The higher culture is sad, cheap, impudent, unkind, without
honesty and without ease. In short, it is “high.” That
abominable word (also applied to game) admirably describes it.
No; if you were setting women free
for something else, I might be more melted. If you can assure me,
privately and gravely, that you are setting women free to dance on
the mountains like mænads, or to worship some monstrous
goddess, I will make a note of your request. If you are quite sure
that the ladies in Brixton, the moment they give up cooking, will
beat great gongs and blow horns to Mumbo–Jumbo, then I will
agree that the occupation is at least human and is more or less
entertaining. Women have been set free to be Bacchantes; they have
been set free to be Virgin Martyrs; they have been set free to be
Witches. Do not ask them now to sink so low as the higher culture.
I have my own little notions of the
possible emancipation of women; but I suppose I should not be taken
very seriously if I propounded them. I should favour anything that
would increase the present enormous authority of women and their
creative action in their own homes. The average woman, as I have
said, is a despot; the average man is a serf. I am for any scheme
that any one can suggest that will make the average woman more of a
despot. So far from wishing her to get her cooked meals from outside,
I should like her to cook more wildly and at her own will than she
does. So far from getting always the same meals from the same place,
let her invent, if she likes, a new dish every day of her life. Let
woman be more of a maker, not less. We are right to talk about
“Woman;” only blackguards talk about women. Yet all men
talk about men, and that is the whole difference. Men represent the
deliberative and democratic element in life. Woman represents the
despotic.
THE MODERN MARTYR
The incident of the Suffragettes who
chained themselves with iron chains to the railings of Downing Street
is a good ironical allegory of most modern martyrdom. It generally
consists of a man chaining himself up and then complaining that he is
not free. Some say that such larks retard the cause of female
suffrage, others say that such larks alone can advance it; as a
matter of fact, I do not believe that they have the smallest effect
one way or the other.
The modern notion of impressing the
public by a mere demonstration of unpopularity, by being thrown out
of meetings or thrown into jail is largely a mistake. It rests on a
fallacy touching the true popular value of martyrdom. People look at
human history and see that it has often happened that persecutions
have not only advertised but even advanced a persecuted creed, and
given to its validity the public and dreadful witness of dying men.
The paradox was pictorially expressed in Christian art, in which
saints were shown brandishing as weapons the very tools that had
slain them. And because his martyrdom is thus a power to the martyr,
modern people think that any one who makes himself slightly
uncomfortable in public will immediately be uproariously popular.
This element of inadequate martyrdom is not true only of the
Suffragettes; it is true of many movements I respect and some that I
agree with. It was true, for instance, of the Passive Resisters, who
had pieces of their furniture sold up. The assumption is that if you
show your ordinary sincerity (or even your political ambition) by
being a nuisance to yourself as well as to other people, you will
have the strength of the great saints who passed through the fire.
Any one who can be hustled in a hall for five minutes, or put in a
cell for five days, has achieved what was meant by martyrdom, and has
a halo in the Christian art of the future. Miss Pankhurst will be
represented holding a policeman in each hand–the instruments of
her martyrdom. The Passive Resister will be shown symbolically
carrying the teapot that was torn from him by tyrannical auctioneers.
But there is a fallacy in this
analogy of martyrdom. The truth is that the special impressiveness
which does come from being persecuted only happens in the case of
extreme persecution. For the fact that the modern enthusiast will
undergo some inconvenience for the creed he holds only proves that he
does hold it, which no one ever doubted. No one doubts that the
Nonconformist minister cares more for Nonconformity than he does for
his teapot. No one doubts that Miss Pankhurst wants a vote more than
she wants a quiet afternoon and an armchair. All our ordinary
intellectual opinions are worth a bit of a row: I remember during the
Boer War fighting an Imperialist clerk outside the Queen’s
Hall, and giving and receiving a bloody nose; but I did not think it
one of the incidents that produce the psychological effect of the
Roman amphitheatre or the stake at Smithfield. For in that impression
there is something more than the mere fact that a man is sincere
enough to give his time or his comfort. Pagans were not impressed by
the torture of Christians merely because it showed that they honestly
held their opinion; they knew that millions of people honestly held
all sorts of opinions. The point of such extreme martyrdom is much
more subtle. It is that it gives an appearance of a man having
something quite specially strong to back him up, of his drawing upon
some power. And this can only be proved when all his physical
contentment is destroyed; when all the current of his bodily being is
reversed and turned to pain. If a man is seen to be roaring with
laughter all the time that he is skinned alive, it would not be
unreasonable to deduce that somewhere in the recesses of his mind he
had thought of a rather good joke. Similarly, if men smiled and sang
(as they did) while they were being boiled or torn in pieces, the
spectators felt the presence of something more than mere mental
honesty: they felt the presence of some new and unintelligible kind
of pleasure, which, presumably, came from somewhere. It might be a
strength of madness, or a lying spirit from Hell; but it was
something quite positive and extraordinary; as positive as brandy and
as extraordinary as conjuring. The Pagan said to himself: “If
Christianity makes a man happy while his legs are being eaten by a
lion, might it not make me happy while my legs are still attached to
me and walking down the street?” The Secularists laboriously
explain that martyrdoms do not prove a faith to be true, as if
anybody was ever such a fool as to suppose that they did. What they
did prove, or, rather, strongly suggest, was that something had
entered human psychology which was stronger than strong pain. If a
young girl, scourged and bleeding to death, saw nothing but a crown
descending on her from God, the first mental step was not that her
philosophy was correct, but that she was certainly feeding on
something. But this particular point of psychology does not arise at
all in the modern cases of mere public discomfort or inconvenience.
The causes of Miss Pankhurst’s cheerfulness require no mystical
explanations. If she were being burned alive as a witch, if she then
looked up in unmixed rapture and saw a ballot–box descending
out of heaven, then I should say that the incident, though not
conclusive, was frightfully impressive. It would not prove logically
that she ought to have the vote, or that anybody ought to have the
vote. But it would prove this: that there was, for some reason, a
sacramental reality in the vote, that the soul could take the vote
and feed on it; that it was in itself a positive and overpowering
pleasure, capable of being pitted against positive and overpowering
pain.
I should advise modern agitators,
therefore, to give up this particular method: the method of making
very big efforts to get a very small punishment. It does not really
go down at all; the punishment is too small, and the efforts are too
obvious. It has not any of the effectiveness of the old savage
martyrdom, because it does not leave the victim absolutely alone with
his cause, so that his cause alone can support him. At the same time
it has about it that element of the pantomimic and the absurd, which
was the cruellest part of the slaying and the mocking of the real
prophets. St. Peter was crucified upside down as a huge inhuman joke;
but his human seriousness survived the inhuman joke, because, in
whatever posture, he had died for his faith. The modern martyr of the
Pankhurst type courts the absurdity without making the suffering
strong enough to eclipse the absurdity. She is like a St. Peter who
should deliberately stand on his head for ten seconds and then expect
to be canonised for it.
Or, again, the matter might be put in
this way. Modern martyrdoms fail even as demonstrations, because they
do not prove even that the martyrs are completely serious. I think,
as a fact, that the modern martyrs generally are serious, perhaps a
trifle too serious. But their martyrdom does not prove it; and the
public does not always believe it. Undoubtedly, as a fact, Dr.
Clifford is quite honourably indignant with what he considers to be
clericalism, but he does not prove it by having his teapot sold; for
a man might easily have his teapot sold as an actress has her
diamonds stolen–as a personal advertisement. As a matter of
fact, Miss Pankhurst is quite in earnest about votes for women. But
she does not prove it by being chucked out of meetings. A person
might be chucked out of meetings just as young men are chucked out of
music–halls–for fun. But no man has himself eaten by a
lion as a personal advertisement. No woman is broiled on a gridiron
for fun. That is where the testimony of St. Perpetua and St. Faith
comes in. Doubtless it is no fault of these enthusiasts that they are
not subjected to the old and searching penalties; very likely they
would pass through them as triumphantly as St. Agatha. I am simply
advising them upon a point of policy, things being as they are. And I
say that the average man is not impressed with their sacrifices
simply because they are not and cannot be more decisive than the
sacrifices which the average man himself would make for mere fun if
he were drunk. Drunkards would interrupt meetings and take the
consequences. And as for selling a teapot, it is an act, I imagine,
in which any properly constituted drunkard would take a positive
pleasure. The advertisement is not good enough; it does not tell. If
I were really martyred for an opinion (which is more improbable than
words can say), it would certainly only be for one or two of my most
central and sacred opinions. I might, perhaps, be shot for England,
but certainly not for the British Empire. I might conceivably die for
political freedom, but I certainly wouldn’t die for Free Trade.
But as for kicking up the particular kind of shindy that the
Suffragettes are kicking up, I would as soon do it for my shallowest
opinion as for my deepest one. It never could be anything worse than
an inconvenience; it never could be anything better than a spree.
Hence the British public, and especially the working classes, regard
the whole demonstration with fundamental indifference; for, while it
is a demonstration that probably is adopted from the most fanatical
motives, it is a demonstration which might be adopted from the most
frivolous.
ON POLITICAL SECRECY
Generally, instinctively, in the
absence of any special reason, humanity hates the idea of anything
being hidden–that is, it hates the idea of anything being
successfully hidden. Hide–and–seek is a popular pastime;
but it assumes the truth of the text, “Seek and ye shall find.”
Ordinary mankind (gigantic and unconquerable in its power of joy) can
get a great deal of pleasure out of a game called “hide the
thimble,” but that is only because it is really a game of “see
the thimble.” Suppose that at the end of such a game the
thimble had not been found at all; suppose its place was unknown for
ever: the result on the players would not be playful, it would be
tragic. That thimble would hag–ride all their dreams. They
would all die in asylums. The pleasure is all in the poignant moment
of passing from not knowing to knowing. Mystery stories are very
popular, especially when sold at sixpence; but that is because the
author of a mystery story reveals. He is enjoyed not because he
creates mystery, but because he destroys mystery. Nobody would have
the courage to publish a detective–story which left the problem
exactly where it found it. That would rouse even the London public to
revolution. No one dare publish a detective–story that did not
detect.
There are three broad classes of the
special things in which human wisdom does permit privacy. The first
is the case I have mentioned–that of hide–and–seek,
or the police novel, in which it permits privacy only in order to
explode and smash privacy. The author makes first a fastidious secret
of how the Bishop was murdered, only in order that he may at last
declare, as from a high tower, to the whole democracy the great glad
news that he was murdered by the governess. In that case, ignorance
is only valued because being ignorant is the best and purest
preparation for receiving the horrible revelations of high life.
Somewhat in the same way being an agnostic is the best and purest
preparation for receiving the happy revelations of St. John.
This first sort of secrecy we may
dismiss, for its whole ultimate object is not to keep the secret, but
to tell it. Then there is a second and far more important class of
things which humanity does agree to hide. They are so important that
they cannot possibly be discussed here. But every one will know the
kind of things I mean. In connection with these, I wish to remark
that though they are, in one sense, a secret, they are also always a
“sécret de Polichinelle.” Upon sex and such
matters we are in a human freemasonry; the freemasonry is
disciplined, but the freemasonry is free. We are asked to be silent
about these things, but we are not asked to be ignorant about them.
On the contrary, the fundamental human argument is entirely the other
way. It is the thing most common to humanity that is most veiled by
humanity. It is exactly because we all know that it is there that we
need not say that it is there.
Then there is a third class of things
on which the best civilisation does permit privacy, does resent all
inquiry or explanation. This is in the case of things which need not
be explained, because they cannot be explained, things too airy,
instinctive, or intangible–caprices, sudden impulses, and the
more innocent kind of prejudice. A man must not be asked why he is
talkative or silent, for the simple reason that he does not know. A
man is not asked (even in Germany) why he walks slow or quick, simply
because he could not answer. A man must take his own road through a
wood, and make his own use of a holiday. And the reason is this: not
because he has a strong reason, but actually because he has a weak
reason; because he has a slight and fleeting feeling about the matter
which he could not explain to a policeman, which perhaps the very
appearance of a policeman out of the bushes might destroy. He must
act on the impulse, because the impulse is unimportant, and he may
never have the same impulse again. If you like to put it so he must
act on the impulse because the impulse is not worth a moment’s
thought. All these fancies men feel should be private; and even
Fabians have never proposed to interfere with them.
Now, for the last fortnight the
newspapers have been full of very varied comments upon the problem of
the secrecy of certain parts of our political finance, and especially
of the problem of the party funds. Some papers have failed entirely
to understand what the quarrel is about. They have urged that Irish
members and Labour members are also under the shadow, or, as some
have said, even more under it. The ground of this frantic statement
seems, when patiently considered, to be simply this: that Irish and
Labour members receive money for what they do. All persons, as far as
I know, on this earth receive money for what they do; the only
difference is that some people, like the Irish members, do it.
I cannot imagine that any human being
could think any other human being capable of maintaining the
proposition that men ought not to receive money. The simple point is
that, as we know that some money is given rightly and some wrongly,
an elementary common–sense leads us to look with indifference
at the money that is given in the middle of Ludgate Circus, and to
look with particular suspicion at the money which a man will not give
unless he is shut up in a box or a bathing–machine. In short,
it is too silly to suppose that anybody could ever have discussed the
desirability of funds. The only thing that even idiots could ever
have discussed is the concealment of funds. Therefore, the whole
question that we have to consider is whether the concealment of
political money–transactions, the purchase of peerages, the
payment of election expenses, is a kind of concealment that falls
under any of the three classes I have mentioned as those in which
human custom and instinct does permit us to conceal. I have suggested
three kinds of secrecy which are human and defensible. Can this
institution be defended by means of any of them?
Now the question is whether this
political secrecy is of any of the kinds that can be called
legitimate. We have roughly divided legitimate secrets into three
classes. First comes the secret that is only kept in order to be
revealed, as in the detective stories; secondly, the secret which is
kept because everybody knows it, as in sex; and third, the secret
which is kept because it is too delicate and vague to be explained at
all, as in the choice of a country walk. Do any of these broad human
divisions cover such a case as that of secrecy of the political and
party finances? It would be absurd, and even delightfully absurd, to
pretend that any of them did. It would be a wild and charming fancy
to suggest that our politicians keep political secrets only that they
may make political revelations. A modern peer only pretends that he
has earned his peerage in order that he may more dramatically
declare, with a scream of scorn and joy, that he really bought it.
The Baronet pretends that he deserved his title only in order to make
more exquisite and startling the grand historical fact that he did
not deserve it. Surely this sounds improbable. Surely all our
statesmen cannot be saving themselves up for the excitement of a
death–bed repentance. The writer of detective tales makes a man
a duke solely in order to blast him with a charge of burglary. But
surely the Prime Minister does not make a man a duke solely in order
to blast him with a charge of bribery. No; the detective–tale
theory of the secrecy of political funds must (with a sigh) be given
up.
Neither can we say that the thing is
explained by that second case of human secrecy which is so secret
that it is hard to discuss it in public. A decency is preserved about
certain primary human matters precisely because every one knows all
about them. But the decency touching contributions, purchases, and
peerages is not kept up because most ordinary men know what is
happening; it is kept up precisely because most ordinary men do not
know what is happening. The ordinary curtain of decorum covers normal
proceedings. But no one will say that being bribed is a normal
proceeding.
And if we apply the third test to
this problem of political secrecy, the case is even clearer and even
more funny. Surely no one will say that the purchase of peerages and
such things are kept secret because they are so light and impulsive
and unimportant that they must be matters of individual fancy. A
child sees a flower and for the first time feels inclined to pick it.
But surely no one will say that a brewer sees a coronet and for the
first time suddenly thinks that he would like to be a peer. The
child’s impulse need not be explained to the police, for the
simple reason that it could not be explained to anybody. But does any
one believe that the laborious political ambitions of modern
commercial men ever have this airy and incommunicable character? A
man lying on the beach may throw stones into the sea without any
particular reason. But does any one believe that the brewer throws
bags of gold into the party funds without any particular reason? This
theory of the secrecy of political money must also be regretfully
abandoned; and with it the two other possible excuses as well. This
secrecy is one which cannot be justified as a sensational joke nor as
a common human freemasonry, nor as an indescribable personal whim.
Strangely enough, indeed, it violates all three conditions and
classes at once. It is not hidden in order to be revealed: it is
hidden in order to be hidden. It is not kept secret because it is a
common secret of mankind, but because mankind must not get hold of
it. And it is not kept secret because it is too unimportant to be
told, but because it is much too important to bear telling. In short,
the thing we have is the real and perhaps rare political phenomenon
of an occult government. We have an exoteric and an esoteric
doctrine. England is really ruled by priestcraft, but not by priests.
We have in this country all that has ever been alleged against the
evil side of religion; the peculiar class with privileges, the sacred
words that are unpronounceable; the important things known only to
the few. In fact we lack nothing except the religion.
EDWARD VII. AND SCOTLAND
I have received a serious, and to me,
at any rate, an impressive remonstrance from the Scottish Patriotic
Association. It appears that I recently referred to Edward VII. of
Great Britain and Ireland, King, Defender of the Faith, under the
horrible description of the King of England. The Scottish Patriotic
Association draws my attention to the fact that by the provisions of
the Act of Union, and the tradition of nationality, the monarch
should be referred to as the King of Britain. The blow thus struck at
me is particularly wounding because it is particularly unjust. I
believe in the reality of the independent nationalities under the
British Crown much more passionately and positively than any other
educated Englishman of my acquaintance believes in it. I am quite
certain that Scotland is a nation; I am quite certain that
nationality is the key of Scotland; I am quite certain that all our
success with Scotland has been due to the fact that we have in spirit
treated it as a nation. I am quite certain that Ireland is a nation;
I am quite certain that nationality is the key to Ireland; I am quite
certain that all our failure in Ireland arose from the fact that we
would not in spirit treat it as a nation. It would be difficult to
find, even among the innumerable examples that exist, a stronger
example of the immensely superior importance of sentiment to what is
called practicality than this case of the two sister nations. It is
not that we have encouraged a Scotchman to be rich; it is not that we
have encouraged a Scotchman to be active; it is not that we have
encouraged a Scotchman to be free. It is that we have quite
definitely encouraged a Scotchman to be Scotch.
A vague, but vivid impression was
received from all our writers of history, philosophy, and rhetoric
that the Scottish element was something really valuable in itself,
was something which even Englishmen were forced to recognise and
respect. If we ever admitted the beauty of Ireland, it was as
something which might be loved by an Englishman but which could
hardly be respected even by an Irishman. A Scotchman might be proud
of Scotland; it was enough for an Irishman that he could be fond of
Ireland. Our success with the two nations has been exactly
proportioned to our encouragement of their independent national
emotion; the one that we would not treat nationally has alone
produced Nationalists. The one nation that we would not recognise as
a nation in theory is the one that we have been forced to recognise
as a nation in arms. The Scottish Patriotic Association has no need
to draw my attention to the importance of the separate national
sentiment or the need of keeping the Border as a sacred line. The
case is quite sufficiently proved by the positive history of
Scotland. The place of Scottish loyalty to England has been taken by
English admiration of Scotland. They do not need to envy us our
titular leadership, when we seem to envy them their separation.
I wish to make very clear my entire
sympathy with the national sentiment of the Scottish Patriotic
Association. But I wish also to make clear this very enlightening
comparison between the fate of Scotch and of Irish patriotism. In
life it is always the little facts that express the large emotions,
and if the English once respected Ireland as they respect Scotland,
it would come out in a hundred small ways. For instance, there are
crack regiments in the British Army which wear the kilt–the
kilt which, as Macaulay says with perfect truth, was regarded by nine
Scotchmen out of ten as the dress of a thief. The Highland officers
carry a silver–hilted version of the old barbarous Gaelic
broadsword with a basket–hilt, which split the skulls of so
many English soldiers at Killiecrankie and Prestonpans. When you have
a regiment of men in the British Army carrying ornamental silver
shillelaghs you will have done the same thing for Ireland, and not
before–or when you mention Brian Boru with the same intonation
as Bruce.
Let me be considered therefore to
have made quite clear that I believe with a quite special intensity
in the independent consideration of Scotland and Ireland as apart
from England. I believe that, in the proper sense of the words,
Scotland is an independent nation, even if Edward VII. is the King of
Scotland. I believe that, in the proper sense of words, Ireland is an
independent nation, even if Edward VII. is King of Ireland. But the
fact is that I have an even bolder and wilder belief than either of
these. I believe that England is an independent nation. I believe
that England also has its independent colour and history, and
meaning. I believe that England could produce costumes quite as queer
as the kilt; I believe that England has heroes fully as
untranslateable as Brian Boru, and consequently I believe that Edward
VII. is, among his innumerable other functions, really King of
England. If my Scotch friends insist, let us call it one of his quite
obscure, unpopular, and minor titles; one of his relaxations. A
little while ago he was Duke of Cornwall; but for a family accident
he might still have been King of Hanover. Nor do I think that we
should blame the simple Cornishmen if they spoke of him in a
rhetorical moment by his Cornish title, nor the well–meaning
Hanoverians if they classed him with Hanoverian Princes.
Now it so happens that in the passage
complained of I said the King of England merely because I meant the
King of England. I was speaking strictly and especially of English
Kings, of Kings in the tradition of the old Kings of England. I wrote
as an English nationalist keenly conscious of the sacred boundary of
the Tweed that keeps (or used to keep) our ancient enemies at bay. I
wrote as an English nationalist resolved for one wild moment to throw
off the tyranny of the Scotch and Irish who govern and oppress my
country. I felt that England was at least spiritually guarded against
these surrounding nationalities. I dreamed that the Tweed was guarded
by the ghosts of Scropes and Percys; I dreamed that St. George’s
Channel was guarded by St. George. And in this insular security I
spoke deliberately and specifically of the King of England, of the
representative of the Tudors and Plantagenets. It is true that the
two Kings of England, of whom I especially spoke, Charles II. and
George III., had both an alien origin, not very recent and not very
remote. Charles II. came of a family originally Scotch. George III.
came of a family originally German. But the same, so far as that
goes, could be said of the English royal houses when England stood
quite alone. The Plantagenets were originally a French family. The
Tudors were originally a Welsh family. But I was not talking of the
amount of English sentiment in the English Kings. I was talking of
the amount of English sentiment in the English treatment and
popularity of the English Kings. With that Ireland and Scotland have
nothing whatever to do.
Charles II. may, for all I know, have
not only been King of Scotland; he may, by virtue of his temper and
ancestry, have been a Scotch King of Scotland. There was something
Scotch about his combination of clear–headedness with
sensuality. There was something Scotch about his combination of doing
what he liked with knowing what he was doing. But I was not talking
of the personality of Charles, which may have been Scotch. I was
talking of the popularity of Charles, which was certainly English.
One thing is quite certain: whether or no he ever ceased to be a
Scotch man, he ceased as soon as he conveniently could to be a Scotch
King. He had actually tried the experiment of being a national ruler
north of the Tweed, and his people liked him as little as he liked
them. Of Presbyterianism, of the Scottish religion, he left on record
the exquisitely English judgment that it was “no religion for a
gentleman.” His popularity then was purely English; his royalty
was purely English; and I was using the words with the utmost
narrowness and deliberation when I spoke of this particular
popularity and royalty as the popularity and royalty of a King of
England. I said of the English people specially that they like to
pick up the King’s crown when he has dropped it. I do not feel
at all sure that this does apply to the Scotch or the Irish. I think
that the Irish would knock his crown off for him. I think that the
Scotch would keep it for him after they had picked it up.
For my part, I should be inclined to
adopt quite the opposite method of asserting nationality. Why should
good Scotch nationalists call Edward VII. the King of Britain? They
ought to call him King Edward I. of Scotland. What is Britain? Where
is Britain? There is no such place. There never was a nation of
Britain; there never was a King of Britain; unless perhaps Vortigern
or Uther Pendragon had a taste for the title. If we are to develop
our Monarchy, I should be altogether in favour of developing it along
the line of local patriotism and of local proprietorship in the King.
I think that the Londoners ought to call him the King of London, and
the Liverpudlians ought to call him the King of Liverpool. I do not
go so far as to say that the people of Birmingham ought to call
Edward VII. the King of Birmingham; for that would be high treason to
a holier and more established power. But I think we might read in the
papers: “The King of Brighton left Brighton at half–past
two this afternoon,” and then immediately afterwards, “The
King of Worthing entered Worthing at ten minutes past three.”
Or, “The people of Margate bade a reluctant farewell to the
popular King of Margate this morning,” and then, “His
Majesty the King of Ramsgate returned to his country and capital this
afternoon after his long sojourn in strange lands.” It might be
pointed out that by a curious coincidence the departure of the King
of Oxford occurred a very short time before the triumphal arrival of
the King of Reading. I cannot imagine any method which would more
increase the kindly and normal relations between the Sovereign and
his people. Nor do I think that such a method would be in any sense a
depreciation of the royal dignity; for, as a matter of fact, it would
put the King upon the same platform with the gods. The saints, the
most exalted of human figures, were also the most local. It was
exactly the men whom we most easily connected with heaven whom we
also most easily connected with earth.
THOUGHTS AROUND KOEPENICK
A famous and epigrammatic author said
that life copied literature; it seems clear that life really
caricatures it. I suggested recently that the Germans submitted to,
and even admired, a solemn and theatrical assertion of authority. A
few hours after I had sent up my “copy,” I saw the first
announcement of the affair of the comic Captain at Koepenick. The
most absurd part of this absurd fraud (at least, to English eyes) is
one which, oddly enough, has received comparatively little comment. I
mean the point at which the Mayor asked for a warrant, and the
Captain pointed to the bayonets of his soldiery and said. “These
are my authority.” One would have thought any one would have
known that no soldier would talk like that. The dupes were blamed for
not knowing that the man wore the wrong cap or the wrong sash, or had
his sword buckled on the wrong way; but these are technicalities
which they might surely be excused for not knowing. I certainly
should not know if a soldier’s sash were on inside out or his
cap on behind before. But I should know uncommonly well that genuine
professional soldiers do not talk like Adelphi villains and utter
theatrical epigrams in praise of abstract violence.
We can see this more clearly,
perhaps, if we suppose it to be the case of any other dignified and
clearly distinguishable profession. Suppose a Bishop called upon me.
My great modesty and my rather distant reverence for the higher
clergy might lead me certainly to a strong suspicion that any Bishop
who called on me was a bogus Bishop. But if I wished to test his
genuineness I should not dream of attempting to do so by examining
the shape of his apron or the way his gaiters were done up. I have
not the remotest idea of the way his gaiters ought to be done up. A
very vague approximation to an apron would probably take me in; and
if he behaved like an approximately Christian gentleman he would be
safe enough from my detection. But suppose the Bishop, the moment he
entered the room, fell on his knees on the mat, clasped his hands,
and poured out a flood of passionate and somewhat hysterical
extempore prayer, I should say at once and without the smallest
hesitation, “Whatever else this man is, he is not an elderly
and wealthy cleric of the Church of England. They don’t do such
things.” Or suppose a man came to me pretending to be a
qualified doctor, and flourished a stethoscope, or what he said was a
stethoscope. I am glad to say that I have not even the remotest
notion of what a stethoscope looks like; so that if he flourished a
musical–box or a coffee–mill it would be all one to me.
But I do think that I am not exaggerating my own sagacity if I say
that I should begin to suspect the doctor if on entering my room he
flung his legs and arms about, crying wildly, “Health! Health!
priceless gift of Nature! I possess it! I overflow with it! I yearn
to impart it! Oh, the sacred rapture of imparting health!” In
that case I should suspect him of being rather in a position to
receive than to offer medical superintendence.
Now, it is no exaggeration at all to
say that any one who has ever known any soldiers (I can only answer
for English and Irish and Scotch soldiers) would find it just as easy
to believe that a real Bishop would grovel on the carpet in a
religious ecstasy, or that a real doctor would dance about the
drawing–room to show the invigorating effects of his own
medicine, as to believe that a soldier, when asked for his authority,
would point to a lot of shining weapons and declare symbolically that
might was right. Of course, a real soldier would go rather red in the
face and huskily repeat the proper formula, whatever it was, as that
he came in the King’s name.
Soldiers have many faults, but they
have one redeeming merit; they are never worshippers of force.
Soldiers more than any other men are taught severely and
systematically that might is not right. The fact is obvious. The
might is in the hundred men who obey. The right (or what is held to
be right) is in the one man who commands them. They learn to obey
symbols, arbitrary things, stripes on an arm, buttons on a coat, a
title, a flag. These may be artificial things; they may be
unreasonable things; they may, if you will, be wicked things; but
they are weak things. They are not Force, and they do not look like
Force. They are parts of an idea: of the idea of discipline; if you
will, of the idea of tyranny; but still an idea. No soldier could
possibly say that his own bayonets were his authority. No soldier
could possibly say that he came in the name of his own bayonets. It
would be as absurd as if a postman said that he came inside his bag.
I do not, as I have said, underrate the evils that really do arise
from militarism and the military ethic. It tends to give people
wooden faces and sometimes wooden heads. It tends moreover (both
through its specialisation and through its constant obedience) to a
certain loss of real independence and strength of character. This has
almost always been found when people made the mistake of turning the
soldier into a statesman, under the mistaken impression that he was a
strong man. The Duke of Wellington, for instance, was a strong
soldier and therefore a weak statesman. But the soldier is always, by
the nature of things, loyal to something. And as long as one is loyal
to something one can never be a worshipper of mere force. For mere
force, violence in the abstract, is the enemy of anything we love. To
love anything is to see it at once under lowering skies of danger.
Loyalty implies loyalty in misfortune; and when a soldier has
accepted any nation’s uniform he has already accepted its
defeat.
Nevertheless, it does appear to be
possible in Germany for a man to point to fixed bayonets and say,
“These are my authority,” and yet to convince ordinarily
sane men that he is a soldier. If this is so, it does really seem to
point to some habit of high–faultin’ in the German
nation, such as that of which I spoke previously. It almost looks as
if the advisers, and even the officials, of the German Army had
become infected in some degree with the false and feeble doctrine
that might is right. As this doctrine is invariably preached by
physical weaklings like Nietzsche it is a very serious thing even to
entertain the supposition that it is affecting men who have really to
do military work It would be the end of German soldiers to be
affected by German philosophy. Energetic people use energy as a
means, but only very tired people ever use energy as a reason.
Athletes go in for games, because athletes desire glory. Invalids go
in for calisthenics; for invalids (alone of all human beings) desire
strength. So long as the German Army points to its heraldic eagle and
says, “I come in the name of this fierce but fabulous animal,”
the German Army will be all right. If ever it says, “I come in
the name of bayonets,” the bayonets will break like glass, for
only the weak exhibit strength without an aim.
At the same time, as I said before,
do not let us forged our own faults. Do not let us forget them any
the more easily because they are the opposite to the German faults.
Modern England is too prone to present the spectacle of a person who
is enormously delighted because he has not got the contrary
disadvantages to his own. The Englishman is always saying “My
house is not damp” at the moment when his house is on fire. The
Englishman is always saying, “I have thrown off all traces of
anæmia” in the middle of a fit of apoplexy. Let us always
remember that if an Englishman wants to swindle English people, he
does not dress up in the uniform of a soldier. If an Englishman wants
to swindle English people he would as soon think of dressing up in
the uniform of a messenger boy. Everything in England is done
unofficially, casually, by conversations and cliques. The one
Parliament that really does rule England is a secret Parliament; the
debates of which must not be published–the Cabinet. The debates
of the Commons are sometimes important; but only the debates in the
Lobby, never the debates in the House. Journalists do control public
opinion; but it is not controlled by the arguments they publish–it
is controlled by the arguments between the editor and sub–editor,
which they do not publish. This casualness is our English vice. It is
at once casual and secret. Our public life is conducted privately.
Hence it follows that if an English swindler wished to impress us,
the last thing he would think of doing would be to put on a uniform.
He would put on a polite slouching air and a careless, expensive suit
of clothes; he would stroll up to the Mayor, be so awfully sorry to
disturb him, find he had forgotten his card–case, mention, as
if he were ashamed of it, that he was the Duke of Mercia, and carry
the whole thing through with the air of a man who could get two
hundred witnesses and two thousand retainers, but who was too tired
to call any of them. And if he did it very well I strongly suspect
that he would be as successful as the indefensible Captain at
Koepenick.
Our tendency for many centuries past
has been, not so much towards creating an aristocracy (which may or
may not be a good thing in itself), as towards substituting an
aristocracy for everything else. In England we have an aristocracy
instead of a religion. The nobility are to the English poor what the
saints and the fairies are to the Irish poor, what the large devil
with a black face was to the Scotch poor–the poetry of life. In
the same way in England we have an aristocracy instead of a
Government. We rely on a certain good humour and education in the
upper class to interpret to us our contradictory Constitution. No
educated man born of woman will be quite so absurd as the system that
he has to administer. In short, we do not get good laws to restrain
bad people. We get good people to restrain bad laws. And last of all
we in England have an aristocracy instead of an Army. We have an Army
of which the officers are proud of their families and ashamed of
their uniforms. If I were a king of any country whatever, and one of
my officers were ashamed of my uniform, I should be ashamed of my
officer. Beware, then, of the really well–bred and apologetic
gentleman whose clothes are at once quiet and fashionable, whose
manner is at once diffident and frank. Beware how you admit him into
your domestic secrets, for he may be a bogus Earl. Or, worse still, a
real one.
THE BOY
I have no sympathy with international
aggression when it is taken seriously, but I have a certain dark and
wild sympathy with it when it is quite absurd. Raids are all wrong as
practical politics, but they are human and imaginable as practical
jokes. In fact, almost any act of ragging or violence can be forgiven
on this strict condition–that it is of no use at all to
anybody. If the aggressor gets anything out of it, then it is quite
unpardonable. It is damned by the least hint of utility or profit. A
man of spirit and breeding may brawl, but he does not steal. A
gentleman knocks off his friend’s hat; but he does not annex
his friend’s hat. For this reason (as Mr. Belloc has pointed
out somewhere), the very militant French people have always returned
after their immense raids–the raids of Godfrey the Crusader,
the raids of Napoleon; “they are sucked back, having
accomplished nothing but an epic.”
Sometimes I see small fragments of
information in the newspapers which make my heart leap with an
irrational patriotic sympathy. I have had the misfortune to be left
comparatively cold by many of the enterprises and proclamations of my
country in recent times. But the other day I found in the Tribune
the following paragraph, which I may be permitted to set down as an
example of the kind of international outrage with which I have by far
the most instinctive sympathy. There is something attractive, too, in
the austere simplicity with which the affair is set forth—“Geneva,
Oct. 31.
“The English
schoolboy Allen, who was arrested at Lausanne railway station on
Saturday, for having painted red the statue of General Jomini of
Payerne, was liberated yesterday, after paying a fine of £24.
Allen has proceeded to Germany, where he will continue his studies.
The people of Payerne are indignant, and clamoured for his detention
in prison.”
Now I have no doubt that ethics and
social necessity require a contrary attitude, but I will freely
confess that my first emotions on reading of this exploit were those
of profound and elemental pleasure. There is something so large and
simple about the operation of painting a whole stone General a bright
red. Of course I can understand that the people of Payerne were
indignant. They had passed to their homes at twilight through the
streets of that beautiful city (or is it a province?), and they had
seen against the silver ending of the sunset the grand grey figure of
the hero of that land remaining to guard the town under the stars. It
certainly must have been a shock to come out in the broad white
morning and find a large vermilion General staring under the staring
sun. I do not blame them at all for clamouring for the schoolboy’s
detention in prison; I dare say a little detention in prison would do
him no harm. Still, I think the immense act has something about it
human and excusable; and when I endeavour to analyse the reason of
this feeling I find it to lie, not in the fact that the thing was big
or bold or successful, but in the fact that the thing was perfectly
useless to everybody, including the person who did it. The raid ends
in itself; and so Master Allen is sucked back again, having
accomplished nothing but an epic.
There is one thing which, in the
presence of average modern journalism, is perhaps worth saying in
connection with such an idle matter as this. The morals of a matter
like this are exactly like the morals of anything else; they are
concerned with mutual contract, or with the rights of independent
human lives. But the whole modern world, or at any rate the whole
modern Press, has a perpetual and consuming terror of plain morals.
Men always attempt to avoid condemning a thing upon merely moral
grounds. If I beat my grandmother to death to–morrow in the
middle of Battersea Park, you may be perfectly certain that people
will say everything about it except the simple and fairly obvious
fact that it is wrong. Some will call it insane; that is, will accuse
it of a deficiency of intelligence. This is not necessarily true at
all. You could not tell whether the act was unintelligent or not
unless you knew my grandmother. Some will call it vulgar, disgusting,
and the rest of it; that is, they will accuse it of a lack of
manners. Perhaps it does show a lack of manners; but this is scarcely
its most serious disadvantage. Others will talk about the loathsome
spectacle and the revolting scene; that is, they will accuse it of a
deficiency of art, or æsthetic beauty. This again depends on
the circumstances: in order to be quite certain that the appearance
of the old lady has definitely deteriorated under the process of
being beaten to death, it is necessary for the philosophical critic
to be quite certain how ugly she was before. Another school of
thinkers will say that the action is lacking in efficiency: that it
is an uneconomic waste of a good grandmother. But that could only
depend on the value, which is again an individual matter. The only
real point that is worth mentioning is that the action is wicked,
because your grandmother has a right not to be beaten to death. But
of this simple moral explanation modern journalism has, as I say, a
standing fear. It will call the action anything else–mad,
bestial, vulgar, idiotic, rather than call it sinful.
One example can be found in such
cases as that of the prank of the boy and the statue. When some trick
of this sort is played, the newspapers opposed to it always describe
it as “a senseless joke.” What is the good of saying
that? Every joke is a senseless joke. A joke is by its nature a
protest against sense. It is no good attacking nonsense for being
successfully nonsensical. Of course it is nonsensical to paint a
celebrated Italian General a bright red; it is as nonsensical as
“Alice in Wonderland.” It is also, in my opinion, very
nearly as funny. But the real answer to the affair is not to say that
it is nonsensical or even to say that it is not funny, but to point
out that it is wrong to spoil statues which belong to other people.
If the modern world will not insist on having some sharp and definite
moral law, capable of resisting the counter–attractions of art
and humour, the modern world will simply be given over as a spoil to
anybody who can manage to do a nasty thing in a nice way. Every
murderer who can murder entertainingly will be allowed to murder.
Every burglar who burgles in really humorous attitudes will burgle as
much as he likes.
There is another case of the thing
that I mean. Why on earth do the newspapers, in describing a dynamite
outrage or any other political assassination, call it a “dastardly
outrage” or a cowardly outrage? It is perfectly evident that it
is not dastardly in the least. It is perfectly evident that it is
about as cowardly as the Christians going to the lions. The man who
does it exposes himself to the chance of being torn in pieces by two
thousand people. What the thing is, is not cowardly, but profoundly
and detestably wicked. The man who does it is very infamous and very
brave. But, again, the explanation is that our modern Press would
rather appeal to physical arrogance, or to anything, rather than
appeal to right and wrong.
In most of the matters of modern
England, the real difficulty is that there is a negative revolution
without a positive revolution. Positive aristocracy is breaking up
without any particular appearance of positive democracy taking its
place. The polished class is becoming less polished without becoming
less of a class; the nobleman who becomes a guinea–pig keeps
all his privileges but loses some of his tradition; he becomes less
of a gentleman without becoming less of a nobleman. In the same way
(until some recent and happy revivals) it seemed highly probable that
the Church of England would cease to be a religion long before it had
ceased to be a Church. And in the same way, the vulgarisation of the
old, simple middle class does not even have the advantage of doing
away with class distinctions; the vulgar man is always the most
distinguished, for the very desire to be distinguished is vulgar.
At the same time, it must be
remembered that when a class has a morality it does not follow that
it is an adequate morality. The middle–class ethic was
inadequate for some purposes; so is the public–school ethic,
the ethic of the upper classes. On this last matter of the public
schools Dr. Spenser, the Head Master of University College School,
has lately made some valuable observations. But even he, I think,
overstates the claim of the public schools. “The strong point
of the English public schools,” he says, “has always lain
in their efficiency as agencies for the formation of character and
for the inculcation of the great notion of obligation which
distinguishes a gentleman. On the physical and moral sides the
public–school men of England are, I believe, unequalled.”
And he goes on to say that it is on the mental side that they are
defective. But, as a matter of fact, the public–school training
is in the strict sense defective upon the moral side also; it leaves
out about half of morality. Its just claim is that, like the old
middle class (and the Zulus), it trains some virtues and therefore
suits some people for some situations. Put an old English merchant to
serve in an army and he would have been irritated and clumsy. Put the
men from English public schools to rule Ireland, and they make the
greatest hash in human history.
Touching the morality of the public
schools, I will take one point only, which is enough to prove the
case. People have got into their heads an extraordinary idea that
English public–school boys and English youth generally are
taught to tell the truth. They are taught absolutely nothing of the
kind. At no English public school is it even suggested, except by
accident, that it is a man’s duty to tell the truth. What is
suggested is something entirely different: that it is a man’s
duty not to tell lies. So completely does this mistake soak through
all civilisation that we hardly ever think even of the difference
between the two things. When we say to a child, “You must tell
the truth,” we do merely mean that he must refrain from verbal
inaccuracies. But the thing we never teach at all is the general duty
of telling the truth, of giving a complete and fair picture of
anything we are talking about, of not misrepresenting, not evading,
not suppressing, not using plausible arguments that we know to be
unfair, not selecting unscrupulously to prove an ex parte
case, not telling all the nice stories about the Scotch, and all the
nasty stories about the Irish, not pretending to be disinterested
when you are really angry, not pretending to be angry when you are
really only avaricious. The one thing that is never taught by any
chance in the atmosphere of public schools is exactly that–that
there is a whole truth of things, and that in knowing it and speaking
it we are happy.
If any one has the smallest doubt of
this neglect of truth in public schools he can kill his doubt with
one plain question. Can any one on earth believe that if the seeing
and telling of the whole truth were really one of the ideals of the
English governing class, there could conceivably exist such a thing
as the English party system? Why, the English party system is founded
upon the principle that telling the whole truth does not matter. It
is founded upon the principle that half a truth is better than no
politics. Our system deliberately turns a crowd of men who might be
impartial into irrational partisans. It teaches some of them to tell
lies and all of them to believe lies. It gives every man an arbitrary
brief that he has to work up as best he may and defend as best he
can. It turns a room full of citizens into a room full of barristers.
I know that it has many charms and virtues, fighting and
good–fellowship; it has all the charms and virtues of a game. I
only say that it would be a stark impossibility in a nation which
believed in telling the truth.
LIMERICKS AND COUNSELS OF PERFECTION
It is customary to remark that modern
problems cannot easily be attacked because they are so complex. In
many cases I believe it is really because they are so simple. Nobody
would believe in such simplicity of scoundrelism even if it were
pointed out. People would say that the truth was a charge of mere
melodramatic villainy; forgetting that nearly all villains really are
melodramatic. Thus, for instance, we say that some good measures are
frustrated or some bad officials kept in power by the press and
confusion of public business; whereas very often the reason is simple
healthy human bribery. And thus especially we say that the Yellow
Press is exaggerative, over–emotional, illiterate, and
anarchical, and a hundred other long words; whereas the only
objection to it is that it tells lies. We waste our fine intellects
in finding exquisite phraseology to fit a man, when in a well–ordered
society we ought to be finding handcuffs to fit him.
This criticism of the modern type of
righteous indignation must have come into many people’s minds,
I think, in reading Dr. Horton’s eloquent expressions of
disgust at the “corrupt Press,” especially in connection
with the Limerick craze. Upon the Limerick craze itself, I fear Dr.
Horton will not have much effect; such fads perish before one has had
time to kill them. But Dr. Horton’s protest may really do good
if it enables us to come to some clear understanding about what is
really wrong with the popular Press, and which means it might be
useful and which permissible to use for its reform. We do not want a
censorship of the Press; but we are long past talking about that. At
present it is not we that silence the Press; it is the Press that
silences us. It is not a case of the Commonwealth settling how much
the editors shall say; it is a case of the editors settling how much
the Commonwealth shall know. If we attack the Press we shall be
rebelling, not repressing. But shall we attack it?
Now it is just here that the chief
difficulty occurs. It arises from the very rarity and rectitude of
those minds which commonly inaugurate such crusades. I have the
warmest respect for Dr. Horton’s thirst after righteousness;
but it has always seemed to me that his righteousness would be more
effective without his refinement. The curse of the Nonconformists is
their universal refinement. They dimly connect being good with being
delicate, and even dapper; with not being grotesque or loud or
violent; with not sitting down on one’s hat. Now it is always a
pleasure to be loud and violent, and sometimes it is a duty.
Certainly it has nothing to do with sin; a man can be loudly and
violently virtuous–nay, he can be loudly and violently saintly,
though that is not the type of saintliness that we recognise in Dr.
Horton. And as for sitting on one’s hat, if it is done for any
sublime object (as, for instance, to amuse the children), it is
obviously an act of very beautiful self–sacrifice, the
destruction and surrender of the symbol of personal dignity upon the
shrine of public festivity. Now it will not do to attack the modern
editor merely for being unrefined, like the great mass of mankind. We
must be able to say that he is immoral, not that he is undignified or
ridiculous. I do not mind the Yellow Press editor sitting on his hat.
My only objection to him begins to dawn when he attempts to sit on my
hat; or, indeed (as is at present the case), when he proceeds to sit
on my head.
But in reading between the lines of
Dr. Horton’s invective one continually feels that he is not
only angry with the popular Press for being unscrupulous: he is
partly angry with the popular Press for being popular. He is not only
irritated with Limericks for causing a mean money–scramble; he
is also partly irritated with Limericks for being Limericks. The
enormous size of the levity gets on his nerves, like the glare and
blare of Bank Holiday. Now this is a motive which, however human and
natural, must be strictly kept out of the way. It takes all sorts to
make a world; and it is not in the least necessary that everybody
should have that love of subtle and unobtrusive perfections in the
matter of manners or literature which does often go with the type of
the ethical idealist. It is not in the least desirable that everybody
should be earnest. It is highly desirable that everybody should be
honest, but that is a thing that can go quite easily with a coarse
and cheerful character. But the ineffectualness of most protests
against the abuse of the Press has been very largely due to the
instinct of democracy (and the instinct of democracy is like the
instinct of one woman, wild but quite right) that the people who were
trying to purify the Press were also trying to refine it; and to this
the democracy very naturally and very justly objected. We are
justified in enforcing good morals, for they belong to all mankind;
but we are not justified in enforcing good manners, for good manners
always mean our own manners. We have no right to purge the popular
Press of all that we think vulgar or trivial. Dr. Horton may possibly
loathe and detest Limericks just as I loathe and detest riddles; but
I have no right to call them flippant and unprofitable; there are
wild people in the world who like riddles. I am so afraid of this
movement passing off into mere formless rhetoric and platform passion
that I will even come close to the earth and lay down specifically
some of the things that, in my opinion, could be, and ought to be,
done to reform the Press.
First, I would make a law, if there
is none such at present, by which an editor, proved to have published
false news without reasonable verification, should simply go to
prison. This is not a question of influences or atmospheres; the
thing could be carried out as easily and as practically as the
punishment of thieves and murderers. Of course there would be the
usual statement that the guilt was that of a subordinate. Let the
accused editor have the right of proving this if he can; if he does,
let the subordinate be tried and go to prison. Two or three good rich
editors and proprietors properly locked up would take the sting out
of the Yellow Press better than centuries of Dr. Horton.
Second, it’s impossible to pass
over altogether the most unpleasant, but the most important part of
this problem. I will deal with it as distantly as possible. I do not
believe there is any harm whatever in reading about murders; rather,
if anything, good; for the thought of death operates very powerfully
with the poor in the creation of brotherhood and a sense of human
dignity. I do not believe there is a pennyworth of harm in the police
news, as such. Even divorce news, though contemptible enough, can
really in most cases be left to the discretion of grown people; and
how far children get hold of such things is a problem for the home
and not for the nation. But there is a certain class of evils which a
healthy man or woman can actually go through life without knowing
anything about at all. These, I say, should be stamped and blackened
out of every newspaper with the thickest black of the Russian censor.
Such cases should either be always tried in camera or
reporting them should be a punishable offence. The common weakness of
Nature and the sins that flesh is heir to we can leave people to find
in newspapers. Men can safely see in the papers what they have
already seen in the streets. They may safely find in their journals
what they have already found in themselves. But we do not want the
imaginations of rational and decent people clouded with the horrors
of some obscene insanity which has no more to do with human life than
the man in Bedlam who thinks he is a chicken. And, if this vile
matter is admitted, let it be simply with a mention of the Latin or
legal name of the crime, and with no details whatever. As it is,
exactly the reverse is true. Papers are permitted to terrify and
darken the fancy of the young with innumerable details, but not
permitted to state in clean legal language what the thing is about.
They are allowed to give any fact about the thing except the fact
that it is a sin.
Third, I would do my best to
introduce everywhere the practice of signed articles. Those who urge
the advantages of anonymity are either people who do not realise the
special peril of our time or they are people who are profiting by it.
It is true, but futile, for instance, to say that there is something
noble in being nameless when a whole corporate body is bent on a
consistent aim: as in an army or men building a cathedral. The point
of modern newspapers is that there is no such corporate body and
common aim; but each man can use the authority of the paper to
further his own private fads and his own private finances.
ANONYMITY AND FURTHER COUNSELS
The end of the article which I write
is always cut off, and, unfortunately, I belong to that lower class
of animals in whom the tail is important. It is not anybody’s
fault but my own; it arises from the fact that I take such a long
time to get to the point. Somebody, the other day, very reasonably
complained of my being employed to write prefaces. He was perfectly
right, for I always write a preface to the preface, and then I am
stopped; also quite justifiably.
In my last article I said that I
favoured three things–first, the legal punishment of
deliberately false information; secondly, a distinction, in the
matter of reported immorality, between those sins which any healthy
man can see in himself and those which he had better not see
anywhere; and thirdly, an absolute insistence in the great majority
of cases upon the signing of articles. It was at this point that I
was cut short, I will not say by the law of space, but rather by my
own lawlessness in the matter of space. In any case, there is
something more that ought to be said.
It would be an exaggeration to say
that I hope some day to see an anonymous article counted as
dishonourable as an anonymous letter. For some time to come, the idea
of the leading article, expressing the policy of the whole paper,
must necessarily remain legitimate; at any rate, we have all written
such leading articles, and should never think the worse of any one
for writing one. But I should certainly say that writing anonymously
ought to have some definite excuse, such as that of the leading
article. Writing anonymously ought to be the exception; writing a
signed article ought to be the rule. And anonymity ought to be not
only an exception, but an accidental exception; a man ought always to
be ready to say what anonymous article he had written. The
journalistic habit of counting it something sacred to keep secret the
origin of an article is simply part of the conspiracy which seeks to
put us who are journalists in the position of a much worse sort of
Jesuits or Freemasons.
As has often been said, anonymity
would be all very well if one could for a moment imagine that it was
established from good motives. Suppose, for instance, that we were
all quite certain that the men on the Thunderer newspaper were
a band of brave young idealists who were so eager to overthrow
Socialism, Municipal and National, that they did not care to which of
them especially was given the glory of striking it down.
Unfortunately, however, we do not believe this. What we believe, or,
rather, what we know, is that the attack on Socialism in the
Thunderer arises from a chaos of inconsistent and mostly evil
motives, any one of which would lose simply by being named. A
jerry–builder whose houses have been condemned writes
anonymously and becomes the Thunderer. A Socialist who has
quarrelled with the other Socialists writes anonymously, and he
becomes the Thunderer. A monopolist who has lost his monopoly,
and a demagogue who has lost his mob, can both write anonymously and
become the same newspaper. It is quite true that there is a young and
beautiful fanaticism in which men do not care to reveal their names.
But there is a more elderly and a much more common excitement in
which men do not dare to reveal them.
Then there is another rule for making
journalism honest on which I should like to insist absolutely. I
should like it to be a fixed thing that the name of the proprietor as
well as the editor should be printed upon every paper. If the paper
is owned by shareholders, let there be a list of shareholders. If (as
is far more common in this singularly undemocratic age) it is owned
by one man, let that one man’s name be printed on the paper, if
possible in large red letters. Then, if there are any obvious
interests being served, we shall know that they are being served. My
friends in Manchester are in a terrible state of excitement about the
power of brewers and the dangers of admitting them to public office.
But at least, if a man has controlled politics through beer, people
generally know it: the subject of beer is too fascinating for any one
to miss such personal peculiarities. But a man may control politics
through journalism, and no ordinary English citizen know that he is
controlling them at all. Again and again in the lists of Birthday
Honours you and I have seen some Mr. Robinson suddenly elevated to
the Peerage without any apparent reason. Even the Society papers
(which we read with avidity) could tell us nothing about him except
that he was a sportsman or a kind landlord, or interested in the
breeding of badgers. Now I should like the name of that Mr. Robinson
to be already familiar to the British public. I should like them to
know already the public services for which they have to thank him. I
should like them to have seen the name already on the outside of that
organ of public opinion called Tootsie’s Tips, or The
Boy Blackmailer, or Nosey Knows, that bright little
financial paper which did so much for the Empire and which so
narrowly escaped a criminal prosecution. If they had seen it thus,
they would estimate more truly and tenderly the full value of the
statement in the Society paper that he is a true gentleman and a
sound Churchman.
Finally, it should be practically
imposed by custom (it so happens that it could not possibly be
imposed by law) that letters of definite and practical complaint
should be necessarily inserted by any editor in any paper. Editors
have grown very much too lax in this respect. The old editor used
dimly to regard himself as an unofficial public servant for the
transmitting of public news. If he suppressed anything, he was
supposed to have some special reason for doing so; as that the
material was actually libellous or literally indecent. But the modern
editor regards himself far too much as a kind of original artist, who
can select and suppress facts with the arbitrary ease of a poet or a
caricaturist. He “makes up” the paper as man “makes
up” a fairy tale, he considers his newspaper solely as a work
of art, meant to give pleasure, not to give news. He puts in this one
letter because he thinks it clever. He puts in these three or four
letters because he thinks them silly. He suppresses this article
because he thinks it wrong. He suppresses this other and more
dangerous article because he thinks it right. The old idea that he is
simply a mode of the expression of the public, an “organ”
of opinion, seems to have entirely vanished from his mind. To–day
the editor is not only the organ, but the man who plays on the organ.
For in all our modern movements we move away from Democracy.
This is the whole danger of our time.
There is a difference between the oppression which has been too
common in the past and the oppression which seems only too probable
in the future. Oppression in the past, has commonly been an
individual matter. The oppressors were as simple as the oppressed,
and as lonely. The aristocrat sometimes hated his inferiors; he
always hated his equals. The plutocrat was an individualist. But in
our time even the plutocrat has become a Socialist. They have science
and combination, and may easily inaugurate a much greater tyranny
than the world has ever seen.
ON THE CRYPTIC AND THE ELLIPTIC
Surely the art of reporting speeches
is in a strange state of degeneration. We should not object, perhaps,
to the reporter’s making the speeches much shorter than they
are; but we do object to his making all the speeches much worse than
they are. And the method which he employs is one which is dangerously
unjust. When a statesman or philosopher makes an important speech,
there are several courses which the reporter might take without being
unreasonable. Perhaps the most reasonable course of all would be not
to report the speech at all. Let the world live and love, marry and
give in marriage, without that particular speech, as they did (in
some desperate way) in the days when there were no newspapers. A
second course would be to report a small part of it; but to get that
right. A third course, far better if you can do it, is to understand
the main purpose and argument of the speech, and report that in clear
and logical language of your own. In short, the three possible
methods are, first, to leave the man’s speech alone; second, to
report what he says or some complete part of what he says; and third,
to report what he means. But the present way of reporting speeches
(mainly created, I think, by the scrappy methods of the Daily
Mail) is something utterly different from both these ways, and
quite senseless and misleading.
The present method is this: the
reporter sits listening to a tide of words which he does not try to
understand, and does not, generally speaking, even try to take down;
he waits until something occurs in the speech which for some reason
sounds funny, or memorable, or very exaggerated, or, perhaps, merely
concrete; then he writes it down and waits for the next one. If the
orator says that the Premier is like a porpoise in the sea under some
special circumstances, the reporter gets in the porpoise even if he
leaves out the Premier. If the orator begins by saying that Mr.
Chamberlain is rather like a violoncello, the reporter does not even
wait to hear why he is like a violoncello. He has got hold of
something material, and so he is quite happy. The strong words all
are put in; the chain of thought is left out. If the orator uses the
word “donkey,” down goes the word “donkey.”
If the orator uses the word “damnable,” down goes the
word “damnable.” They follow each other so abruptly in
the report that it is often hard to discover the fascinating fact as
to what was damnable or who was being compared with a donkey. And the
whole line of argument in which these things occurred is entirely
lost. I have before me a newspaper report of a speech by Mr. Bernard
Shaw, of which one complete and separate paragraph runs like
this—“Capital meant spare money over and above one’s
needs. Their country was not really their country at all except in
patriotic songs.”
I am well enough acquainted with the
whole map of Mr. Bernard Shaw’s philosophy to know that those
two statements might have been related to each other in a hundred
ways. But I think that if they were read by an ordinary intelligent
man, who happened not to know Mr. Shaw’s views, he would form
no impression at all except that Mr. Shaw was a lunatic of more than
usually abrupt conversation and disconnected mind. The other two
methods would certainly have done Mr. Shaw more justice: the reporter
should either have taken down verbatim what the speaker really said
about Capital, or have given an outline of the way in which this idea
was connected with the idea about patriotic songs.
But we
have not the advantage of knowing what Mr. Shaw really did say, so we
had better illustrate the different methods from something that we do
know. Most of us, I suppose, know Mark Antony’s Funeral Speech
in “Julius Cæsar.” Now Mark Antony would have no
reason to complain if he were not reported at all; if the Daily
Pilum or the Morning Fasces, or whatever it was, confined
itself to saying, “Mr. Mark Antony also spoke,” or “Mr.
Mark Antony, having addressed the audience, the meeting broke up in
some confusion.” The next honest method, worthy of a noble
Roman reporter, would be that since he could not report the whole of
the speech, he should report some of the speech. He might say–”Mr.
Mark Antony, in the course of his speech, said—’ When
that the poor have cried Cæsar hath wept: Ambition should be
made of sterner stuff.’”
In that case one good, solid argument
of Mark Antony would be correctly reported. The third and far higher
course for the Roman reporter would be to give a philosophical
statement of the purport of the speech. As thus–”Mr. Mark
Antony, in the course of a powerful speech, conceded the high motives
of the Republican leaders, and disclaimed any intention of raising
the people against them; he thought, however, that many instances
could be quoted against the theory of Cæsar’s ambition,
and he concluded by reading, at the request of the audience, the will
of Cæsar, which proved that he had the most benevolent designs
towards the Roman people.” That is (I admit) not quite so fine
as Shakspere, but it is a statement of the man’s political
position. But if a Daily Mail reporter were sent to take down
Antony’s oration, he would simply wait for any expressions that
struck him as odd and put them down one after another without any
logical connection at all. It would turn out something like this:
“Mr. Mark Antony wished for his audience’s ears. He had
thrice offered Cæsar a crown. Cæsar was like a deer. If
he were Brutus he would put a wound in every tongue. The stones of
Rome would mutiny. See what a rent the envious Casca paid. Brutus was
Cæsar’s angel. The right honourable gentleman concluded
by saying that he and the audience had all fallen down.” That
is the report of a political speech in a modern, progressive, or
American manner, and I wonder whether the Romans would have put up
with it.
The reports of the debates in the
Houses of Parliament are constantly growing smaller and smaller in
our newspapers. Perhaps this is partly because the speeches are
growing duller and duller. I think in some degree the two things act
and re–act on each other. For fear of the newspapers
politicians are dull, and at last they are too dull even for the
newspapers. The speeches in our time are more careful and elaborate,
because they are meant to be read, and not to be heard. And exactly
because they are more careful and elaborate, they are not so likely
to be worthy of a careful and elaborate report. They are not
interesting enough. So the moral cowardice of modern politicians has,
after all, some punishment attached to it by the silent anger of
heaven. Precisely because our political speeches are meant to be
reported, they are not worth reporting. Precisely because they are
carefully designed to be read, nobody reads them.
Thus we may concede that politicians
have done something towards degrading journalism. It was not entirely
done by us, the journalists. But most of it was. It was mostly the
fruit of our first and most natural sin–the habit of regarding
ourselves as conjurers rather than priests, for the definition is
that a conjurer is apart from his audience, while a priest is a part
of his. The conjurer despises his congregation; if the priest
despises any one, it must be himself. The curse of all journalism,
but especially of that yellow journalism which is the shame of our
profession, is that we think ourselves cleverer than the people for
whom we write, whereas, in fact, we are generally even stupider. But
this insolence has its Nemesis; and that Nemesis is well illustrated
in this matter of reporting.
For the journalist, having grown
accustomed to talking down to the public, commonly talks too low at
last, and becomes merely barbaric and unintelligible. By his very
efforts to be obvious he becomes obscure. This just punishment may
specially be noticed in the case of those staggering and staring
headlines which American journalism introduced and which some English
journalism imitates. I once saw a headline in a London paper which
ran simply thus: “Dobbin’s Little Mary.” This was
intended to be familiar and popular, and therefore, presumably,
lucid. But it was some time before I realised, after reading about
half the printed matter underneath, that it had something to do with
the proper feeding of horses. At first sight, I took it, as the
historical leader of the future will certainly take it, as containing
some allusion to the little daughter who so monopolised the
affections of the Major at the end of “Vanity Fair.” The
Americans carry to an even wilder extreme this darkness by excess of
light. You may find a column in an American paper headed “Poet
Brown Off Orange–flowers,” or “Senator Robinson
Shoehorns Hats Now,” and it may be quite a long time before the
full meaning breaks upon you: it has not broken upon me yet.
And something of this intellectual
vengeance pursues also those who adopt the modern method of reporting
speeches. They also become mystical, simply by trying to be vulgar.
They also are condemned to be always trying to write like George R.
Sims, and succeeding, in spite of themselves, in writing like
Maeterlinck. That combination of words which I have quoted from an
alleged speech of Mr. Bernard Shaw’s was written down by the
reporter with the idea that he was being particularly plain and
democratic. But, as a matter of fact, if there is any connection
between the two sentences, it must be something as dark as the
deepest roots of Browning, or something as invisible as the most airy
filaments of Meredith. To be simple and to be democratic are two very
honourable and austere achievements; and it is not given to all the
snobs and self–seekers to achieve them. High above even
Maeterlinck or Meredith stand those, like Homer and Milton, whom no
one can misunderstand. And Homer and Milton are not only better poets
than Browning (great as he was), but they would also have been very
much better journalists than the young men on the Daily Mail.
As it is, however, this
misrepresentation of speeches is only a part of a vast journalistic
misrepresentation of all life as it is. Journalism is popular, but it
is popular mainly as fiction. Life is one world, and life seen in the
newspapers another; the public enjoys both, but it is more or less
conscious of the difference. People do not believe, for instance,
that the debates in the House of Commons are as dramatic as they
appear in the daily papers. If they did they would go, not to the
daily paper, but to the House of Commons. The galleries would be
crowded every night as they were in the French Revolution; for
instead of seeing a printed story for a penny they would be seeing an
acted drama for nothing. But the, people know in their hearts that
journalism is a conventional art like any other, that it selects,
heightens, and falsifies. Only its Nemesis is the same as that of
other arts: if it loses all care for truth it loses all form
likewise. The modern who paints too cleverly produces a picture of a
cow which might be the earthquake at San Francisco. And the
journalist who reports a speech too cleverly makes it mean nothing at
all.
THE WORSHIP OF THE WEALTHY
There has crept, I notice, into our
literature and journalism a new way of flattering the wealthy and the
great. In more straightforward times flattery itself was more
straight–forward; falsehood itself was more true. A poor man
wishing to please a rich man simply said that he was the wisest,
bravest, tallest, strongest, most benevolent and most beautiful of
mankind; and as even the rich man probably knew that he wasn’t
that, the thing did the less harm. When courtiers sang the praises of
a King they attributed to him things that were entirely improbable,
as that he resembled the sun at noonday, that they had to shade their
eyes when he entered the room, that his people could not breathe
without him, or that he had with his single sword conquered Europe,
Asia, Africa, and America. The safety of this method was its
artificiality; between the King and his public image there was really
no relation. But the moderns have invented a much subtler and more
poisonous kind of eulogy. The modern method is to take the prince or
rich man, to give a credible picture of his type of personality, as
that he is business–like, or a sportsman, or fond of art, or
convivial, or reserved; and then enormously exaggerate the value and
importance of these natural qualities. Those who praise Mr. Carnegie
do not say that he is as wise as Solomon and as brave as Mars; I wish
they did. It would be the next most honest thing to giving their real
reason for praising him, which is simply that he has money. The
journalists who write about Mr. Pierpont Morgan do not say that he is
as beautiful as Apollo; I wish they did. What they do is to take the
rich man’s superficial life and manner, clothes, hobbies, love
of cats, dislike of doctors, or what not; and then with the
assistance of this realism make the man out to be a prophet and a
saviour of his kind, whereas he is merely a private and stupid man
who happens to like cats or to dislike doctors. The old flatterer
took for granted that the King was an ordinary man, and set to work
to make him out extraordinary. The newer and cleverer flatterer takes
for granted that he is extraordinary, and that therefore even
ordinary things about him will be of interest.
I have noticed one very amusing way
in which this is done. I notice the method applied to about six of
the wealthiest men in England in a book of interviews published by an
able and well–known journalist. The flatterer contrives to
combine strict truth of fact with a vast atmosphere of awe and
mystery by the simple operation of dealing almost entirely in
negatives. Suppose you are writing a sympathetic study of Mr.
Pierpont Morgan. Perhaps there is not much to say about what he does
think, or like, or admire; but you can suggest whole vistas of his
taste and philosophy by talking a great deal about what he does not
think, or like, or admire. You say of him–”But little
attracted to the most recent schools of German philosophy, he stands
almost as resolutely aloof from the tendencies of transcendental
Pantheism as from the narrower ecstasies of Neo–Catholicism.”
Or suppose I am called upon to praise the charwoman who has just come
into my house, and who certainly deserves it much more. I say–”It
would be a mistake to class Mrs. Higgs among the followers of Loisy;
her position is in many ways different; nor is she wholly to be
identified with the concrete Hebraism of Harnack.” It is a
splendid method, as it gives the flatterer an opportunity of talking
about something else besides the subject of the flattery, and it
gives the subject of the flattery a rich, if somewhat bewildered,
mental glow, as of one who has somehow gone through agonies of
philosophical choice of which he was previously unaware. It is a
splendid method; but I wish it were applied sometimes to charwomen
rather than only to millionaires.
There is another way of flattering
important people which has become very common, I notice, among
writers in the newspapers and elsewhere. It consists in applying to
them the phrases “simple,” or “quiet,” or
“modest,” without any sort of meaning or relation to the
person to whom they are applied. To be simple is the best thing in
the world; to be modest is the next best thing. I am not so sure
about being quiet. I am rather inclined to think that really modest
people make a great deal of noise. It is quite self–evident
that really simple people make a great deal of noise. But simplicity
and modesty, at least, are very rare and royal human virtues, not to
be lightly talked about. Few human beings, and at rare intervals,
have really risen into being modest; not one man in ten or in twenty
has by long wars become simple, as an actual old soldier does by
[**Note: Apparent typesetting error here in original.] long wars
become simple. These virtues are not things to fling about as mere
flattery; many prophets and righteous men have desired to see these
things and have not seen them. But in the description of the births,
lives, and deaths of very luxurious men they are used incessantly and
quite without thought. If a journalist has to describe a great
politician or financier (the things are substantially the same)
entering a room or walking down a thoroughfare, he always says, “Mr.
Midas was quietly dressed in a black frock coat, a white waistcoat,
and light grey trousers, with a plain green tie and simple flower in
his button–hole.” As if any one would expect him to have
a crimson frock coat or spangled trousers. As if any one would expect
him to have a burning Catherine wheel in his button–hole.
But this process, which is absurd
enough when applied to the ordinary and external lives of worldly
people, becomes perfectly intolerable when it is applied, as it
always is applied, to the one episode which is serious even in the
lives of politicians. I mean their death. When we have been
sufficiently bored with the account of the simple costume of the
millionaire, which is generally about as complicated as any that he
could assume without being simply thought mad; when we have been told
about the modest home of the millionaire, a home which is generally
much too immodest to be called a home at all; when we have followed
him through all these unmeaning eulogies, we are always asked last of
all to admire his quiet funeral. I do not know what else people think
a funeral should be except quiet. Yet again and again, over the grave
of every one of those sad rich men, for whom one should surely feel,
first and last, a speechless pity–over the grave of Beit, over
the grave of Whiteley–this sickening nonsense about modesty and
simplicity has been poured out. I well remember that when Beit was
buried, the papers said that the mourning–coaches contained
everybody of importance, that the floral tributes were sumptuous,
splendid, intoxicating; but, for all that, it was a simple and quiet
funeral. What, in the name of Acheron, did they expect it to be? Did
they think there would be human sacrifice–the immolation of
Oriental slaves upon the tomb? Did they think that long rows of
Oriental dancing–girls would sway hither and thither in an
ecstasy of lament? Did they look for the funeral games of Patroclus?
I fear they had no such splendid and pagan meaning. I fear they were
only using the words “quiet” and “modest” as
words to fill up a page–a mere piece of the automatic hypocrisy
which does become too common among those who have to write rapidly
and often. The word “modest” will soon become like the
word “honourable,” which is said to be employed by the
Japanese before any word that occurs in a polite sentence, as “Put
honourable umbrella in honourable umbrella–stand;” or
“condescend to clean honourable boots.” We shall read in
the future that the modest King went out in his modest crown, clad
from head to foot in modest gold and attended with his ten thousand
modest earls, their swords modestly drawn. No! if we have to pay for
splendour let us praise it as splendour, not as simplicity. When next
I meet a rich man I intend to walk up to him in the street and
address him with Oriental hyperbole. He will probably run away.
SCIENCE AND RELIGION
In these days we are accused of
attacking science because we want it to be scientific. Surely there
is not any undue disrespect to our doctor in saying that he is our
doctor, not our priest, or our wife, or ourself. It is not the
business of the doctor to say that we must go to a watering–place;
it is his affair to say that certain results of health will follow if
we do go to a watering–place. After that, obviously, it is for
us to judge. Physical science is like simple addition: it is either
infallible or it is false. To mix science up with philosophy is only
to produce a philosophy that has lost all its ideal value and a
science that has lost all its practical value. I want my private
physician to tell me whether this or that food will kill me. It is
for my private philosopher to tell me whether I ought to be killed. I
apologise for stating all these truisms. But the truth is, that I
have just been reading a thick pamphlet written by a mass of highly
intelligent men who seem never to have heard of any of these truisms
in their lives.
Those who detest the harmless writer
of this column are generally reduced (in their final ecstasy of
anger) to calling him “brilliant;” which has long ago in
our journalism become a mere expression of contempt. But I am afraid
that even this disdainful phrase does me too much honour. I am more
and more convinced that I suffer, not from a shiny or showy
impertinence, but from a simplicity that verges upon imbecility. I
think more and more that I must be very dull, and that everybody else
in the modern world must be very clever. I have just been reading
this important compilation, sent to me in the name of a number of men
for whom I have a high respect, and called “New Theology and
Applied Religion.” And it is literally true that I have read
through whole columns of the things without knowing what the people
were talking about. Either they must be talking about some black and
bestial religion in which they were brought up, and of which I never
even heard, or else they must be talking about some blazing and
blinding vision of God which they have found, which I have never
found, and which by its very splendour confuses their logic and
confounds their speech. But the best instance I can quote of the
thing is in connection with this matter of the business of physical
science on the earth, of which I have just spoken. The following
words are written over the signature of a man whose intelligence I
respect, and I cannot make head or tail of them—“When
modern science declared that the cosmic process knew nothing of a
historical event corresponding to a Fall, but told, on the contrary,
the story of an incessant rise in the scale of being, it was quite
plain that the Pauline scheme–I mean the argumentative
processes of Paul’s scheme of salvation–had lost its very
foundation; for was not that foundation the total depravity of the
human race inherited from their first parents?. . . . But now there
was no Fall; there was no total depravity, or imminent danger of
endless doom; and, the basis gone, the superstructure followed.”
It is written with earnestness and in
excellent English; it must mean something. But what can it mean? How
could physical science prove that man is not depraved? You do not cut
a man open to find his sins. You do not boil him until he gives forth
the unmistakable green fumes of depravity. How could physical science
find any traces of a moral fall? What traces did the writer expect to
find? Did he expect to find a fossil Eve with a fossil apple inside
her? Did he suppose that the ages would have spared for him a
complete skeleton of Adam attached to a slightly faded fig–leaf?
The whole paragraph which I have quoted is simply a series of
inconsequent sentences, all quite untrue in themselves and all quite
irrelevant to each other. Science never said that there could have
been no Fall. There might have been ten Falls, one on top of the
other, and the thing would have been quite consistent with everything
that we know from physical science. Humanity might have grown morally
worse for millions of centuries, and the thing would in no way have
contradicted the principle of Evolution. Men of science (not being
raving lunatics) never said that there had been “an incessant
rise in the scale of being;” for an incessant rise would mean a
rise without any relapse or failure; and physical evolution is full
of relapse and failure. There were certainly some physical Falls;
there may have been any number of moral Falls. So that, as I have
said, I am honestly bewildered as to the meaning of such passages as
this, in which the advanced person writes that because geologists
know nothing about the Fall, therefore any doctrine of depravity is
untrue. Because science has not found something which obviously it
could not find, therefore something entirely different–the
psychological sense of evil–is untrue. You might sum up this
writer’s argument abruptly, but accurately, in some way like
this–”We have not dug up the bones of the Archangel
Gabriel, who presumably had none, therefore little boys, left to
themselves, will not be selfish.” To me it is all wild and
whirling; as if a man said–”The plumber can find nothing
wrong with our piano; so I suppose that my wife does love me.”
I am not going to enter here into the
real doctrine of original sin, or into that probably false version of
it which the New Theology writer calls the doctrine of depravity. But
whatever else the worst doctrine of depravity may have been, it was a
product of spiritual conviction; it had nothing to do with remote
physical origins. Men thought mankind wicked because they felt wicked
themselves. If a man feels wicked, I cannot see why he should
suddenly feel good because somebody tells him that his ancestors once
had tails. Man’s primary purity and innocence may have dropped
off with his tail, for all anybody knows. The only thing we all know
about that primary purity and innocence is that we have not got it.
Nothing can be, in the strictest sense of the word, more comic than
to set so shadowy a thing as the conjectures made by the vaguer
anthropologists about primitive man against so solid a thing as the
human sense of sin. By its nature the evidence of Eden is something
that one cannot find. By its nature the evidence of sin is something
that one cannot help finding.
Some statements I disagree with;
others I do not understand. If a man says, “I think the human
race would be better if it abstained totally from fermented liquor,”
I quite understand what he means, and how his view could be defended.
If a man says, “I wish to abolish beer because I am a
temperance man,” his remark conveys no meaning to my mind. It
is like saying, “I wish to abolish roads because I am a
moderate walker.” If a man says, “I am not a
Trinitarian,” I understand. But if he says (as a lady once said
to me), “I believe in the Holy Ghost in a spiritual sense,”
I go away dazed. In what other sense could one believe in the Holy
Ghost? And I am sorry to say that this pamphlet of progressive
religious views is full of baffling observations of that kind. What
can people mean when they say that science has disturbed their view
of sin? What sort of view of sin can they have had before science
disturbed it? Did they think that it was something to eat? When
people say that science has shaken their faith in immortality, what
do they mean? Did they think that immortality was a gas?
Of course the real truth is that
science has introduced no new principle into the matter at all. A man
can be a Christian to the end of the world, for the simple reason
that a man could have been an Atheist from the beginning of it. The
materialism of things is on the face of things; it does not require
any science to find it out. A man who has lived and loved falls down
dead and the worms eat him. That is Materialism if you like. That is
Atheism if you like. If mankind has believed in spite of that, it can
believe in spite of anything. But why our human lot is made any more
hopeless because we know the names of all the worms who eat him, or
the names of all the parts of him that they eat, is to a thoughtful
mind somewhat difficult to discover. My chief objection to these
semi–scientific revolutionists is that they are not at all
revolutionary. They are the party of platitude. They do not shake
religion: rather religion seems to shake them. They can only answer
the great paradox by repeating the truism.
THE METHUSELAHITE
I Saw in a newspaper paragraph the
other day the following entertaining and deeply philosophical
incident. A man was enlisting as a soldier at Portsmouth, and some
form was put before him to be filled up, common, I suppose, to all
such cases, in which was, among other things, an inquiry about what
was his religion. With an equal and ceremonial gravity the man wrote
down the word “Methuselahite.” Whoever looks over such
papers must, I should imagine, have seen some rum religions in his
time; unless the Army is going to the dogs. But with all his
specialist knowledge he could not “place” Methuselahism
among what Bossuet called the variations of Protestantism. He felt a
fervid curiosity about the tenets and tendencies of the sect; and he
asked the soldier what it meant. The soldier replied that it was his
religion “to live as long as he could.”
Now, considered as an incident in the
religious history of Europe, that answer of that soldier was worth
more than a hundred cartloads of quarterly and monthly and weekly and
daily papers discussing religious problems and religious books. Every
day the daily paper reviews some new philosopher who has some new
religion; and there is not in the whole two thousand words of the
whole two columns one word as witty as or wise as that word
“Methuselahite.” The whole meaning of literature is
simply to cut a long story short; that is why our modern books of
philosophy are never literature. That soldier had in him the very
soul of literature; he was one of the great phrase–makers of
modern thought, like Victor Hugo or Disraeli. He found one word that
defines the paganism of to–day.
Henceforward, when the modern
philosophers come to me with their new religions (and there is always
a kind of queue of them waiting all the way down the street) I shall
anticipate their circumlocutions and be able to cut them short with a
single inspired word. One of them will begin, “The New
Religion, which is based upon that Primordial Energy in Nature. . .
.” “Methuselahite,” I shall say sharply; “good
morning.” “Human Life,” another will say, “Human
Life, the only ultimate sanctity, freed from creed and dogma. . . .”
“Methuselahite!” I shall yell. “Out you go!”
“My religion is the Religion of Joy,” a third will
explain (a bald old man with a cough and tinted glasses), “the
Religion of Physical Pride and Rapture, and my. . . .”
“Methuselahite!” I shall cry again, and I shall slap him
boisterously on the back, and he will fall down. Then a pale young
poet with serpentine hair will come and say to me (as one did only
the other day): “Moods and impressions are the only realities,
and these are constantly and wholly changing. I could hardly
therefore define my religion. . . .” “I can,” I
should say, somewhat sternly. “Your religion is to live a long
time; and if you stop here a moment longer you won’t fulfil
it.”
A new philosophy generally means in
practice the praise of some old vice. We have had the sophist who
defends cruelty, and calls it masculinity. We have had the sophist
who defends profligacy, and calls it the liberty of the emotions. We
have had the sophist who defends idleness, and calls it art. It will
almost certainly happen–it can almost certainly be
prophesied–that in this saturnalia of sophistry there will at
some time or other arise a sophist who desires to idealise cowardice.
And when we are once in this unhealthy world of mere wild words, what
a vast deal there would be to say for cowardice! “Is not life a
lovely thing and worth saving?” the soldier would say as he ran
away. “Should I not prolong the exquisite miracle of
consciousness?” the householder would say as he hid under the
table. “As long as there are roses and lilies on the earth
shall I not remain here?” would come the voice of the citizen
from under the bed. It would be quite as easy to defend the coward as
a kind of poet and mystic as it has been, in many recent books, to
defend the emotionalist as a kind of poet and mystic, or the tyrant
as a kind of poet and mystic. When that last grand sophistry and
morbidity is preached in a book or on a platform, you may depend upon
it there will be a great stir in its favour, that is, a great stir
among the little people who live among books and platforms. There
will be a new great Religion, the Religion of Methuselahism: with
pomps and priests and altars. Its devout crusaders will vow
themselves in thousands with a great vow to live long. But there is
one comfort: they won’t.
For, indeed, the weakness of this
worship of mere natural life (which is a common enough creed to–day)
is that it ignores the paradox of courage and fails in its own aim.
As a matter of fact, no men would be killed quicker than the
Methuselahites. The paradox of courage is that a man must be a little
careless of his life even in order to keep it. And in the very case I
have quoted we may see an example of how little the theory of
Methuselahism really inspires our best life. For there is one riddle
in that case which cannot easily be cleared up. If it was the man’s
religion to live as long as he could, why on earth was he enlisting
as a soldier?
SPIRITUALISM
I Have received a letter from a
gentleman who is very indignant at what he considers my flippancy in
disregarding or degrading Spiritualism. I thought I was defending
Spiritualism; but I am rather used to being accused of mocking the
thing that I set out to justify. My fate in most controversies is
rather pathetic. It is an almost invariable rule that the man with
whom I don’t agree thinks I am making a fool of myself, and the
man with whom I do agree thinks I am making a fool of him. There
seems to be some sort of idea that you are not treating a subject
properly if you eulogise it with fantastic terms or defend it by
grotesque examples. Yet a truth is equally solemn whatever figure or
example its exponent adopts. It is an equally awful truth that four
and four make eight, whether you reckon the thing out in eight onions
or eight angels, or eight bricks or eight bishops, or eight minor
poets or eight pigs. Similarly, if it be true that God made all
things, that grave fact can be asserted by pointing at a star or by
waving an umbrella. But the case is stronger than this. There is a
distinct philosophical advantage in using grotesque terms in a
serious discussion.
I think seriously, on the whole, that
the more serious is the discussion the more grotesque should be the
terms. For this, as I say, there is an evident reason. For a subject
is really solemn and important in so far as it applies to the whole
cosmos, or to some great spheres and cycles of experience at least.
So far as a thing is universal it is serious. And so far as a thing
is universal it is full of comic things. If you take a small thing,
it may be entirely serious: Napoleon, for instance, was a small
thing, and he was serious: the same applies to microbes. If you
isolate a thing, you may get the pure essence of gravity. But if you
take a large thing (such as the Solar System) it must be
comic, at least in parts. The germs are serious, because they kill
you. But the stars are funny, because they give birth to life, and
life gives birth to fun. If you have, let us say, a theory about man,
and if you can only prove it by talking about Plato and George
Washington, your theory may be a quite frivolous thing. But if you
can prove it by talking about the butler or the postman, then it is
serious, because it is universal. So far from it being irreverent to
use silly metaphors on serious questions, it is one’s duty to
use silly metaphors on serious questions. It is the test of one’s
seriousness. It is the test of a responsible religion or theory
whether it can take examples from pots and pans and boots and
butter–tubs. It is the test of a good philosophy whether you
can defend it grotesquely. It is the test of a good religion whether
you can joke about it.
When I was a very young journalist I
used to be irritated at a peculiar habit of printers, a habit which
most persons of a tendency similar to mine have probably noticed
also. It goes along with the fixed belief of printers that to be a
Rationalist is the same thing as to be a Nationalist. I mean the
printer’s tendency to turn the word “cosmic” into
the word “comic.” It annoyed me at the time. But since
then I have come to the conclusion that the printers were right. The
democracy is always right. Whatever is cosmic is comic.
Moreover, there is another reason
that makes it almost inevitable that we should defend grotesquely
what we believe seriously. It is that all grotesqueness is itself
intimately related to seriousness. Unless a thing is dignified, it
cannot be undignified. Why is it funny that a man should sit down
suddenly in the street? There is only one possible or intelligent
reason: that man is the image of God. It is not funny that anything
else should fall down; only that a man should fall down. No one sees
anything funny in a tree falling down. No one sees a delicate
absurdity in a stone falling down. No man stops in the road and roars
with laughter at the sight of the snow coming down. The fall of
thunderbolts is treated with some gravity. The fall of roofs and high
buildings is taken seriously. It is only when a man tumbles down that
we laugh. Why do we laugh? Because it is a grave religious matter: it
is the Fall of Man. Only man can be absurd: for only man can be
dignified.
The above, which occupies the great
part of my article, is a parenthises. It is time that I returned to
my choleric correspondent who rebuked me for being too frivolous
about the problem of Spiritualism. My correspondent, who is evidently
an intelligent man, is very angry with me indeed. He uses the
strongest language. He says I remind him of a brother of his: which
seems to open an abyss or vista of infamy. The main substance of his
attack resolves itself into two propositions. First, he asks me what
right I have to talk about Spiritualism at all, as I admit I have
never been to a séance. This is all very well, but
there are a good many things to which I have never been, but I have
not the smallest intention of leaving off talking about them. I
refuse (for instance) to leave off talking about the Siege of Troy. I
decline to be mute in the matter of the French Revolution. I will not
be silenced on the late indefensible assassination of Julius Cæsar.
If nobody has any right to judge of Spiritualism except a man who has
been to a séance, the results, logically speaking, are
rather serious: it would almost seem as if nobody had any right to
judge of Christianity who had not been to the first meeting at
Pentecost. Which would be dreadful. I conceive myself capable of
forming my opinion of Spiritualism without seeing spirits, just as I
form my opinion of the Japanese War without seeing the Japanese, or
my opinion of American millionaires without (thank God) seeing an
American millionaire. Blessed are they who have not seen and yet have
believed: a passage which some have considered as a prophecy of
modern journalism.
But my correspondent’s second
objection is more important. He charges me with actually ignoring the
value of communication (if it exists) between this world and the
next. I do not ignore it. But I do say this–That a different
principle attaches to investigation in this spiritual field from
investigation in any other. If a man baits a line for fish, the fish
will come, even if he declares there are no such things as fishes. If
a man limes a twig for birds, the birds will be caught, even if he
thinks it superstitious to believe in birds at all. But a man cannot
bait a line for souls. A man cannot lime a twig to catch gods. All
wise schools have agreed that this latter capture depends to some
extent on the faith of the capturer. So it comes to this: If you have
no faith in the spirits your appeal is in vain; and if you have–is
it needed? If you do not believe, you cannot. If you do–you
will not.
That is the real distinction between
investigation in this department and investigation in any other. The
priest calls to the goddess, for the same reason that a man calls to
his wife, because he knows she is there. If a man kept on shouting
out very loud the single word “Maria,” merely with the
object of discovering whether if he did it long enough some woman of
that name would come and marry him, he would be more or less in the
position of the modern spiritualist. The old religionist cried out
for his God. The new religionist cries out for some god to be his.
The whole point of religion as it has hitherto existed in the world
was that you knew all about your gods, even before you saw them, if
indeed you ever did. Spiritualism seems to me absolutely right on all
its mystical side. The supernatural part of it seems to me quite
natural. The incredible part of it seems to me obviously true. But I
think it so far dangerous or unsatisfactory that it is in some degree
scientific. It inquires whether its gods are worth inquiring into. A
man (of a certain age) may look into the eyes of his lady–love
to see that they are beautiful. But no normal lady will allow that
young man to look into her eyes to see whether they are beautiful.
The same vanity and idiosyncrasy has been generally observed in gods.
Praise them; or leave them alone; but do not look for them unless you
know they are there. Do not look for them unless you want them. It
annoys them very much.
THE ERROR OF IMPARTIALITY
The refusal of the jurors in the Thaw
trial to come to an agreement is certainly a somewhat amusing sequel
to the frenzied and even fantastic caution with which they were
selected. Jurymen were set aside for reasons which seem to have only
the very wildest relation to the case–reasons which we cannot
conceive as giving any human being a real bias. It may be questioned
whether the exaggerated theory of impartiality in an arbiter or
juryman may not be carried so far as to be more unjust than
partiality itself. What people call impartiality may simply mean
indifference, and what people call partiality may simply mean mental
activity. It is sometimes made an objection, for instance, to a juror
that he has formed some primâ–facie opinion upon a
case: if he can be forced under sharp questioning to admit that he
has formed such an opinion, he is regarded as manifestly unfit to
conduct the inquiry. Surely this is unsound. If his bias is one of
interest, of class, or creed, or notorious propaganda, then that fact
certainly proves that he is not an impartial arbiter. But the mere
fact that he did form some temporary impression from the first facts
as far as he knew them–this does not prove that he is not an
impartial arbiter–it only proves that he is not a cold–blooded
fool.
If we walk down the street, taking
all the jurymen who have not formed opinions and leaving all the
jurymen who have formed opinions, it seems highly probable that we
shall only succeed in taking all the stupid jurymen and leaving all
the thoughtful ones. Provided that the opinion formed is really of
this airy and abstract kind, provided that it has no suggestion of
settled motive or prejudice, we might well regard it not merely as a
promise of capacity, but literally as a promise of justice. The man
who took the trouble to deduce from the police reports would probably
be the man who would take the trouble to deduce further and different
things from the evidence. The man who had the sense to form an
opinion would be the man who would have the sense to alter it.
It is worth while to dwell for a
moment on this minor aspect of the matter because the error about
impartiality and justice is by no means confined to a criminal
question. In much more serious matters it is assumed that the
agnostic is impartial; whereas the agnostic is merely ignorant. The
logical outcome of the fastidiousness about the Thaw jurors would be
that the case ought to be tried by Esquimaux, or Hottentots, or
savages from the Cannibal Islands–by some class of people who
could have no conceivable interest in the parties, and moreover, no
conceivable interest in the case. The pure and starry perfection of
impartiality would be reached by people who not only had no opinion
before they had heard the case, but who also had no opinion after
they had heard it. In the same way, there is in modern discussions of
religion and philosophy an absurd assumption that a man is in some
way just and well–poised because he has come to no conclusion;
and that a man is in some way knocked off the list of fair judges
because he has come to a conclusion. It is assumed that the sceptic
has no bias; whereas he has a very obvious bias in favour of
scepticism. I remember once arguing with an honest young atheist, who
was very much shocked at my disputing some of the assumptions which
were absolute sanctities to him (such as the quite unproved
proposition of the independence of matter and the quite improbable
proposition of its power to originate mind), and he at length fell
back upon this question, which he delivered with an honourable heat
of defiance and indignation: “Well, can you tell me any man of
intellect, great in science or philosophy, who accepted the
miraculous?” I said, “With pleasure. Descartes, Dr.
Johnson, Newton, Faraday, Newman, Gladstone, Pasteur, Browning,
Brunetiere–as many more as you please.” To which that
quite admirable and idealistic young man made this astonishing
reply–”Oh, but of course they had to say that;
they were Christians.” First he challenged me to find a black
swan, and then he ruled out all my swans because they were black. The
fact that all these great intellects had come to the Christian view
was somehow or other a proof either that they were not great
intellects or that they had not really come to that view. The
argument thus stood in a charmingly convenient form: “All men
that count have come to my conclusion; for if they come to your
conclusion they do not count.”
It did not seem to occur to such
controversialists that if Cardinal Newman was really a man of
intellect, the fact that he adhered to dogmatic religion proved
exactly as much as the fact that Professor Huxley, another man of
intellect, found that he could not adhere to dogmatic religion; that
is to say (as I cheerfully admit), it proved precious little either
way. If there is one class of men whom history has proved especially
and supremely capable of going quite wrong in all directions, it is
the class of highly intellectual men. I would always prefer to go by
the bulk of humanity; that is why I am a democrat. But whatever be
the truth about exceptional intelligence and the masses, it is
manifestly most unreasonable that intelligent men should be divided
upon the absurd modern principle of regarding every clever man who
cannot make up his mind as an impartial judge, and regarding every
clever man who can make up his mind as a servile fanatic. As it is,
we seem to regard it as a positive objection to a reasoner that he
has taken one side or the other. We regard it (in other words) as a
positive objection to a reasoner that he has contrived to reach the
object of his reasoning. We call a man a bigot or a slave of dogma
because he is a thinker who has thought thoroughly and to a definite
end. We say that the juryman is not a juryman because he has brought
in a verdict. We say that the judge is not a judge because he gives
judgment. We say that the sincere believer has no right to vote,
simply because he has voted.
PHONETIC SPELLING
A correspondent asks me to make more
lucid my remarks about phonetic spelling. I have no detailed
objection to items of spelling–reform; my objection is to a
general principle; and it is this. It seems to me that what is really
wrong with all modern and highly civilised language is that it does
so largely consist of dead words. Half our speech consists of similes
that remind us of no similarity; of pictorial phrases that call up no
picture; of historical allusions the origin of which we have
forgotten. Take any instance on which the eye happens to alight. I
saw in the paper some days ago that the well–known leader of a
certain religious party wrote to a supporter of his the following
curious words: “I have not forgotten the talented way in which
you held up the banner at Birkenhead.” Taking the ordinary
vague meaning of the word “talented,” there is no
coherency in the picture. The trumpets blow, the spears shake and
glitter, and in the thick of the purple battle there stands a
gentleman holding up a banner in a talented way. And when we come to
the original force of the word “talent” the matter is
worse: a talent is a Greek coin used in the New Testament as a symbol
of the mental capital committed to an individual at birth. If the
religious leader in question had really meant anything by his
phrases, he would have been puzzled to know how a man could use a
Greek coin to hold up a banner. But really he meant nothing by his
phrases. “Holding up the banner” was to him a colourless
term for doing the proper thing, and “talented” was a
colourless term for doing it successfully.
Now my own fear touching anything in
the way of phonetic spelling is that it would simply increase this
tendency to use words as counters and not as coins. The original life
in a word (as in the word “talent”) burns low as it is:
sensible spelling might extinguish it altogether. Suppose any
sentence you like: suppose a man says, “Republics generally
encourage holidays.” It looks like the top line of a copy–book.
Now, it is perfectly true that if you wrote that sentence exactly as
it is pronounced, even by highly educated people, the sentence would
run: “Ripubliks jenrally inkurrij hollidies.” It looks
ugly: but I have not the smallest objection to ugliness. My objection
is that these four words have each a history and hidden treasures in
them: that this history and hidden treasure (which we tend to forget
too much as it is) phonetic spelling tends to make us forget
altogether. Republic does not mean merely a mode of political choice.
Republic (as we see when we look at the structure of the word) means
the Public Thing: the abstraction which is us all.
A Republican is not a man who wants a
Constitution with a President. A Republican is a man who prefers to
think of Government as impersonal; he is opposed to the Royalist, who
prefers to think of Government as personal. Take the second word,
“generally.” This is always used as meaning “in the
majority of cases.” But, again, if we look at the shape and
spelling of the word, we shall see that “generally” means
something more like “generically,” and is akin to such
words as “generation” or “regenerate.” “Pigs
are generally dirty” does not mean that pigs are, in the
majority of cases, dirty, but that pigs as a race or genus are dirty,
that pigs as pigs are dirty–an important philosophical
distinction. Take the third word, “encourage.” The word
“encourage” is used in such modern sentences in the
merely automatic sense of promote; to encourage poetry means merely
to advance or assist poetry. But to encourage poetry means properly
to put courage into poetry–a fine idea. Take the fourth word,
“holidays.” As long as that word remains, it will always
answer the ignorant slander which asserts that religion was opposed
to human cheerfulness; that word will always assert that when a day
is holy it should also be happy. Properly spelt, these words all tell
a sublime story, like Westminster Abbey. Phonetically spelt, they
might lose the last traces of any such story. “Generally”
is an exalted metaphysical term; “jenrally” is not. If
you “encourage” a man, you pour into him the chivalry of
a hundred princes; this does not happen if you merely “inkurrij”
him. “Republics,” if spelt phonetically, might actually
forget to be public. “Holidays,” if spelt phonetically,
might actually forget to be holy.
Here is a case that has just
occurred. A certain magistrate told somebody whom he was examining in
court that he or she “should always be polite to the police.”
I do not know whether the magistrate noticed the circumstance, but
the word “polite” and the word “police” have
the same origin and meaning. Politeness means the atmosphere and
ritual of the city, the symbol of human civilisation. The policeman
means the representative and guardian of the city, the symbol of
human civilisation. Yet it may be doubted whether the two ideas are
commonly connected in the mind. It is probable that we often hear of
politeness without thinking of a policeman; it is even possible that
our eyes often alight upon a policeman without our thoughts instantly
flying to the subject of politeness. Yet the idea of the sacred city
is not only the link of them both, it is the only serious
justification and the only serious corrective of them both. If
politeness means too often a mere frippery, it is because it has not
enough to do with serious patriotism and public dignity; if policemen
are coarse or casual, it is because they are not sufficiently
convinced that they are the servants of the beautiful city and the
agents of sweetness and light. Politeness is not really a frippery.
Politeness is not really even a thing merely suave and deprecating.
Politeness is an armed guard, stern and splendid and vigilant,
watching over all the ways of men; in other words, politeness is a
policeman. A policeman is not merely a heavy man with a truncheon: a
policeman is a machine for the smoothing and sweetening of the
accidents of everyday existence. In other words, a policeman is
politeness; a veiled image of politeness–sometimes impenetrably
veiled. But my point is here that by losing the original idea of the
city, which is the force and youth of both the words, both the things
actually degenerate. Our politeness loses all manliness because we
forget that politeness is only the Greek for patriotism. Our
policemen lose all delicacy because we forget that a policeman is
only the Greek for something civilised. A policeman should often have
the functions of a knight–errant. A policeman should always
have the elegance of a knight–errant. But I am not sure that he
would succeed any the better n remembering this obligation of
romantic grace if his name were spelt phonetically, supposing that it
could be spelt phonetically. Some spelling–reformers, I am
told, in the poorer parts of London do spell his name phonetically,
very phonetically. They call him a “pleeceman.” Thus the
whole romance of the ancient city disappears from the word, and the
policeman’s reverent courtesy of demeanour deserts him quite
suddenly. This does seem to me the case against any extreme
revolution in spelling. If you spell a word wrong you have some
temptation to think it wrong.
HUMANITARIANISM AND STRENGTH
Somebody
writes complaining of something I said about progress. I have
forgotten what I said, but I am quite certain that it was (like a
certain Mr. Douglas in a poem which I have also forgotten) tender and
true. In any case, what I say now is this. Human history is so rich
and complicated that you can make out a case for any course of
improvement or retrogression. I could make out that the world has
been growing more democratic, for the English franchise has certainly
grown more democratic. I could also make out that the world has been
growing more aristocratic, for the English Public Schools have
certainly grown more aristocratic I could prove the decline of
militarism by the decline of flogging; I could prove the increase of
militarism by the increase of standing armies and conscription. But I
can prove anything in this way. I can prove that the world has always
been growing greener. Only lately men have invented absinthe and the
Westminster Gazette. I could prove the world has grown less
green. There are no more Robin Hood foresters, and fields are being
covered with houses. I could show that the world was less red with
khaki or more red with the new penny stamps. But in all cases
progress means progress only in some particular thing. Have you ever
noticed that strange line of Tennyson, in which he confesses, half
consciously, how very conventional progress is?—“Let
the great world spin for ever down the ringing grooves of change.”
Even in praising change, he takes for
a simile the most unchanging thing. He calls our modern change a
groove. And it is a groove; perhaps there was never anything so
groovy.
Nothing would induce me in so idle a
monologue as this to discuss adequately a great political matter like
the question of the military punishments in Egypt. But I may suggest
one broad reality to be observed by both sides, and which is,
generally speaking, observed by neither. Whatever else is right, it
is utterly wrong to employ the argument that we Europeans must do to
savages and Asiatics whatever savages and Asiatics do to us. I have
even seen some controversialists use the metaphor, “We must
fight them with their own weapons.” Very well; let those
controversialists take their metaphor, and take it literally. Let us
fight the Soudanese with their own weapons. Their own weapons are
large, very clumsy knives, with an occasional old–fashioned
gun. Their own weapons are also torture and slavery. If we fight them
with torture and slavery, we shall be fighting badly, precisely as if
we fought them with clumsy knives and old guns. That is the whole
strength of our Christian civilisation, that it does fight with its
own weapons and not with other people’s. It is not true that
superiority suggests a tit for tat. It is not true that if a small
hooligan puts his tongue out at the Lord Chief Justice, the Lord
Chief Justice immediately realises that his only chance of
maintaining his position is to put his tongue out at the little
hooligan. The hooligan may or may not have any respect at all for the
Lord Chief Justice: that is a matter which we may contentedly leave
as a solemn psychological mystery. But if the hooligan has any
respect at all for the Lord Chief Justice, that respect is certainly
extended to the Lord Chief Justice entirely because he does not put
his tongue out.
Exactly in the same way the ruder or
more sluggish races regard the civilisation of Christendom. If they
have any respect for it, it is precisely because it does not use
their own coarse and cruel expedients. According to some modern
moralists whenever Zulus cut off the heads of dead Englishmen,
Englishmen must cut off the heads of dead Zulus. Whenever Arabs or
Egyptians constantly use the whip to their slaves, Englishmen must
use the whip to their subjects. And on a similar principle (I
suppose), whenever an English Admiral has to fight cannibals the
English Admiral ought to eat them. However unattractive a menu
consisting entirely of barbaric kings may appear to an English
gentleman, he must try to sit down to it with an appetite. He must
fight the Sandwich Islanders with their own weapons; and their own
weapons are knives and forks. But the truth of the matter is, of
course, that to do this kind of thing is to break the whole spell of
our supremacy. All the mystery of the white man, all the fearful
poetry of the white man, so far as it exists in the eyes of these
savages, consists in the fact that we do not do such things. The
Zulus point at us and say, “Observe the advent of these
inexplicable demi–gods, these magicians, who do not cut off the
noses of their enemies.” The Soudanese say to each other, “This
hardy people never flogs its servants; it is superior to the simplest
and most obvious human pleasures.” And the cannibals say, “The
austere and terrible race, the race that denies itself even boiled
missionary, is upon us: let us flee.”
Whether or no[** “not”?
or just his style?] these details are a little conjectural, the
general proposition I suggest is the plainest common sense. The
elements that make Europe upon the whole the most humanitarian
civilisation are precisely the elements that make it upon the whole
the strongest. For the power which makes a man able to entertain a
good impulse is the same as that which enables him to make a good
gun; it is imagination. It is imagination that makes a man outwit his
enemy, and it is imagination that makes him spare his enemy. It is
precisely because this picturing of the other man’s point of
view is in the main a thing in which Christians and Europeans
specialise that Christians and Europeans, with all their faults, have
carried to such perfection both the arts of peace and war.
They alone have invented
machine–guns, and they alone have invented ambulances; they
have invented ambulances (strange as it may sound) for the same
reason for which they have invented machine–guns. Both involve
a vivid calculation of remote events. It is precisely because the
East, with all its wisdom, is cruel, that the East, with all its
wisdom, is weak. And it is precisely because savages are pitiless
that they are still–merely savages. If they could imagine their
enemy’s sufferings they could also imagine his tactics. If
Zulus did not cut off the Englishman’s head they might really
borrow it. For if you do not understand a man you cannot crush him.
And if you do understand him, very probably you will not.
When I was about seven years old I
used to think that the chief modern danger was a danger of
over–civilisation. I am inclined to think now that the chief
modern danger is that of a slow return towards barbarism, just such a
return towards barbarism as is indicated in the suggestions of
barbaric retaliation of which I have just spoken. Civilisation in the
best sense merely means the full authority of the human spirit over
all externals. Barbarism means the worship of those externals in
their crude and unconquered state. Barbarism means the worship of
Nature; and in recent poetry, science, and philosophy there has been
too much of the worship of Nature. Wherever men begin to talk much
and with great solemnity about the forces outside man, the note of it
is barbaric. When men talk much about heredity and environment they
are almost barbarians. The modern men of science are many of them
almost barbarians. Mr. Blatchford is in great danger of becoming a
barbarian. For barbarians (especially the truly squalid and unhappy
barbarians) are always talking about these scientific subjects from
morning till night. That is why they remain squalid and unhappy; that
is why they remain barbarians. Hottentots are always talking about
heredity, like Mr. Blatchford. Sandwich Islanders are always talking
about environment, like Mr. Suthers. Savages–those that are
truly stunted or depraved–dedicate nearly all their tales and
sayings to the subject of physical kinship, of a curse on this or
that tribe, of a taint in this or that family, of the invincible law
of blood, of the unavoidable evil of places. The true savage is a
slave, and is always talking about what he must do; the true
civilised man is a free man and is always talking about what he may
do. Hence all the Zola heredity and Ibsen heredity that has been
written in our time affects me as not merely evil, but as essentially
ignorant and retrogressive. This sort of science is almost the only
thing that can with strict propriety be called reactionary.
Scientific determinism is simply the primal twilight of all mankind;
and some men seem to be returning to it.
Another savage trait of our time is
the disposition to talk about material substances instead of about
ideas. The old civilisation talked about the sin of gluttony or
excess. We talk about the Problem of Drink–as if drink could be
a problem. When people have come to call the problem of human
intemperance the Problem of Drink, and to talk about curing it by
attacking the drink traffic, they have reached quite a dim stage of
barbarism. The thing is an inverted form of fetish worship; it is no
sillier to say that a bottle is a god than to say that a bottle is a
devil. The people who talk about the curse of drink will probably
progress down that dark hill. In a little while we shall have them
calling the practice of wife–beating the Problem of Pokers; the
habit of housebreaking will be called the Problem of the Skeleton–Key
Trade; and for all I know they may try to prevent forgery by shutting
up all the stationers’ shops by Act of Parliament.
I cannot help thinking that there is
some shadow of this uncivilised materialism lying at present upon a
much more dignified and valuable cause. Every one is talking just now
about the desirability of ingeminating peace and averting war. But
even war and peace are physical states rather than moral states, and
in talking about them only we have by no means got to the bottom of
the matter. How, for instance, do we as a matter of fact create peace
in one single community? We do not do it by vaguely telling every one
to avoid fighting and to submit to anything that is done to him. We
do it by definitely defining his rights and then undertaking to
avenge his wrongs. We shall never have a common peace in Europe till
we have a common principle in Europe. People talk of “The
United States of Europe;” but they forget that it needed the
very doctrinal “Declaration of Independence” to make the
United States of America. You cannot agree about nothing any more
than you can quarrel about nothing.
WINE WHEN IT IS RED
I suppose that there will be some
wigs on the green in connection with the recent manifesto signed by a
string of very eminent doctors on the subject of what is called
“alcohol.” “Alcohol” is, to judge by the
sound of it, an Arabic word, like “algebra” and
“Alhambra,” those two other unpleasant things. The
Alhambra in Spain I have never seen; I am told that it is a low and
rambling building; I allude to the far more dignified erection in
Leicester Square. If it is true, as I surmise, that “alcohol”
is a word of the Arabs, it is interesting to realise that our general
word for the essence of wine and beer and such things comes from a
people which has made particular war upon them. I suppose that some
aged Moslem chieftain sat one day at the opening of his tent and,
brooding with black brows and cursing in his black beard over wine as
the symbol of Christianity, racked his brains for some word ugly
enough to express his racial and religious antipathy, and suddenly
spat out the horrible word “alcohol.” The fact that the
doctors had to use this word for the sake of scientific clearness was
really a great disadvantage to them in fairly discussing the matter.
For the word really involves one of those beggings of the question
which make these moral matters so difficult. It is quite a mistake to
suppose that, when a man desires an alcoholic drink, he necessarily
desires alcohol.
Let a man walk ten miles steadily on
a hot summer’s day along a dusty English road, and he will soon
discover why beer was invented. The fact that beer has a very slight
stimulating quality will be quite among the smallest reasons that
induce him to ask for it. In short, he will not be in the least
desiring alcohol; he will be desiring beer. But, of course, the
question cannot be settled in such a simple way. The real difficulty
which confronts everybody, and which especially confronts doctors, is
that the extraordinary position of man in the physical universe makes
it practically impossible to treat him in either one direction or the
other in a purely physical way. Man is an exception, whatever else he
is. If he is not the image of God, then he is a disease of the dust.
If it is not true that a divine being fell, then we can only say that
one of the animals went entirely off its head. In neither case can we
really argue very much from the body of man simply considered as the
body of an innocent and healthy animal. His body has got too much
mixed up with his soul, as we see in the supreme instance of sex. It
may be worth while uttering the warning to wealthy philanthropists
and idealists that this argument from the animal should not be
thoughtlessly used, even against the atrocious evils of excess; it is
an argument that proves too little or too much.
Doubtless, it is unnatural to be
drunk. But then in a real sense it is unnatural to be human.
Doubtless, the intemperate workman wastes his tissues in drinking;
but no one knows how much the sober workman wastes his tissues by
working. No one knows how much the wealthy philanthropist wastes his
tissues by talking; or, in much rarer conditions, by thinking. All
the human things are more dangerous than anything that affects the
beasts–sex, poetry, property, religion. The real case against
drunkenness is not that it calls up the beast, but that it calls up
the Devil. It does not call up the beast, and if it did it would not
matter much, as a rule; the beast is a harmless and rather amiable
creature, as anybody can see by watching cattle. There is nothing
bestial about intoxication; and certainly there is nothing
intoxicating or even particularly lively about beasts. Man is always
something worse or something better than an animal; and a mere
argument from animal perfection never touches him at all. Thus, in
sex no animal is either chivalrous or obscene. And thus no animal
ever invented anything so bad as drunkenness–or so good as
drink.
The pronouncement of these particular
doctors is very clear and uncompromising; in the modern atmosphere,
indeed, it even deserves some credit for moral courage. The majority
of modern people, of course, will probably agree with it in so far as
it declares that alcoholic drinks are often of supreme value in
emergencies of illness; but many people, I fear, will open their eyes
at the emphatic terms in which they describe such drink as considered
as a beverage; but they are not content with declaring that the drink
is in moderation harmless: they distinctly declare that it is in
moderation beneficial. But I fancy that, in saying this, the doctors
had in mind a truth that runs somewhat counter to the common opinion.
I fancy that it is the experience of most doctors that giving any
alcohol for illness (though often necessary) is about the most
morally dangerous way of giving it. Instead of giving it to a healthy
person who has many other forms of life, you are giving it to a
desperate person, to whom it is the only form of life. The invalid
can hardly be blamed if by some accident of his erratic and
overwrought condition he comes to remember the thing as the very
water of vitality and to use it as such. For in so far as drinking is
really a sin it is not because drinking is wild, but because drinking
is tame; not in so far as it is anarchy, but in so far as it is
slavery. Probably the worst way to drink is to drink medicinally.
Certainly the safest way to drink is to drink carelessly; that is,
without caring much for anything, and especially not caring for the
drink.
The doctor, of course, ought to be
able to do a great deal in the way of restraining those individual
cases where there is plainly an evil thirst; and beyond that the only
hope would seem to be in some increase, or, rather, some
concentration of ordinary public opinion on the subject. I have
always held consistently my own modest theory on the subject. I
believe that if by some method the local public–house could be
as definite and isolated a place as the local post–office or
the local railway station, if all types of people passed through it
for all types of refreshment, you would have the same safeguard
against a man behaving in a disgusting way in a tavern that you have
at present against his behaving in a disgusting way in a post–office:
simply the presence of his ordinary sensible neighbours. In such a
place the kind of lunatic who wants to drink an unlimited number of
whiskies would be treated with the same severity with which the post
office authorities would treat an amiable lunatic who had an appetite
for licking an unlimited number of stamps. It is a small matter
whether in either case a technical refusal would be officially
employed. It is an essential matter that in both cases the
authorities could rapidly communicate with the friends and family of
the mentally afflicted person. At least, the postmistress would not
dangle a strip of tempting sixpenny stamps before the enthusiast’s
eyes as he was being dragged away with his tongue out. If we made
drinking open and official we might be taking one step towards making
it careless. In such things to be careless is to be sane: for neither
drunkards nor Moslems can be careless about drink.
DEMAGOGUES AND MYSTAGOGUES
I once heard a man call this age the
age of demagogues. Of this I can only say, in the admirably sensible
words of the angry coachman in “Pickwick,” that “that
remark’s political, or what is much the same, it ain’t
true.” So far from being the age of demagogues, this is really
and specially the age of mystagogues. So far from this being a time
in which things are praised because they are popular, the truth is
that this is the first time, perhaps, in the whole history of the
world in which things can be praised because they are unpopular. The
demagogue succeeds because he makes himself understood, even if he is
not worth understanding. But the mystagogue succeeds because he gets
himself misunderstood; although, as a rule, he is not even worth
misunderstanding. Gladstone was a demagogue: Disraeli a mystagogue.
But ours is specially the time when a man can advertise his wares not
as a universality, but as what the tradesmen call “a
speciality.” We all know this, for instance, about modern art.
Michelangelo and Whistler were both fine artists; but one is
obviously public, the other obviously private, or, rather, not
obvious at all. Michelangelo’s frescoes are doubtless finer
than the popular judgment, but they are plainly meant to strike the
popular judgment. Whistler’s pictures seem often meant to
escape the popular judgment; they even seem meant to escape the
popular admiration. They are elusive, fugitive; they fly even from
praise. Doubtless many artists in Michelangelo’s day declared
themselves to be great artists, although they were unsuccessful. But
they did not declare themselves great artists because they were
unsuccessful: that is the peculiarity of our own time, which has a
positive bias against the populace.
Another case of the same kind of
thing can be found in the latest conceptions of humour. By the
wholesome tradition of mankind, a joke was a thing meant to amuse
men; a joke which did not amuse them was a failure, just as a fire
which did not warm them was a failure. But we have seen the process
of secrecy and aristocracy introduced even into jokes. If a joke
falls flat, a small school of æsthetes only ask us to notice
the wild grace of its falling and its perfect flatness after its
fall. The old idea that the joke was not good enough for the company
has been superseded by the new aristocratic idea that the company was
not worthy of the joke. They have introduced an almost insane
individualism into that one form of intercourse which is specially
and uproariously communal. They have made even levities into secrets.
They have made laughter lonelier than tears.
There is a third thing to which the
mystagogues have recently been applying the methods of a secret
society: I mean manners. Men who sought to rebuke rudeness used to
represent manners as reasonable and ordinary; now they seek to
represent them as private and peculiar. Instead of saying to a man
who blocks up a street or the fireplace, “You ought to know
better than that,” the moderns say, “You, of course,
don’t know better than that.”
I have just been reading an amusing
book by Lady Grove called “The Social Fetich,” which is a
positive riot of this new specialism and mystification. It is due to
Lady Grove to say that she has some of the freer and more honourable
qualities of the old Whig aristocracy, as well as their wonderful
worldliness and their strange faith in the passing fashion of our
politics. For instance, she speaks of Jingo Imperialism with a
healthy English contempt; and she perceives stray and striking
truths, and records them justly–as, for instance, the greater
democracy of the Southern and Catholic countries of Europe. But in
her dealings with social formulæ here in England she is, it
must frankly be said, a common mystagogue. She does not, like a
decent demagogue, wish to make people understand; she wishes to make
them painfully conscious of not understanding. Her favourite method
is to terrify people from doing things that are quite harmless by
telling them that if they do they are the kind of people who would do
other things, equally harmless. If you ask after somebody’s
mother (or whatever it is), you are the kind of person who would have
a pillow–case, or would not have a pillow–case. I forget
which it is; and so, I dare say, does she. If you assume the ordinary
dignity of a decent citizen and say that you don’t see the harm
of having a mother or a pillow–case, she would say that of
course you wouldn’t. This is what I call being a
mystagogue. It is more vulgar than being a demagogue; because it is
much easier.
The primary point I meant to
emphasise is that this sort of aristocracy is essentially a new sort.
All the old despots were demagogues; at least, they were demagogues
whenever they were really trying to please or impress the demos. If
they poured out beer for their vassals it was because both they and
their vassals had a taste for beer. If (in some slightly different
mood) they poured melted lead on their vassals, it was because both
they and their vassals had a strong distaste for melted lead. But
they did not make any mystery about either of the two substances.
They did not say, “You don’t like melted lead?. . . . Ah!
no, of course, you wouldn’t; you are probably the kind
of person who would prefer beer. . . . It is no good asking you even
to imagine the curious undercurrent of psychological pleasure felt by
a refined person under the seeming shock of melted lead.” Even
tyrants when they tried to be popular, tried to give the people
pleasure; they did not try to overawe the people by giving them
something which they ought to regard as pleasure. It was the same
with the popular presentment of aristocracy. Aristocrats tried to
impress humanity by the exhibition of qualities which humanity
admires, such as courage, gaiety, or even mere splendour. The
aristocracy might have more possession in these things, but the
democracy had quite equal delight in them. It was much more sensible
to offer yourself for admiration because you had drunk three bottles
of port at a sitting, than to offer yourself for admiration (as Lady
Grove does) because you think it right to say “port wine”
while other people think it right to say “port.” Whether
Lady Grove’s preference for port wine (I mean for the phrase
port wine) is a piece of mere nonsense I do not know; but at least it
is a very good example of the futility of such tests in the matter
even of mere breeding. “Port wine” may happen to be the
phrase used n certain good families; but numberless aristocrats say
“port,” and all barmaids say “port wine.” The
whole thing is rather more trivial than collecting tram–tickets;
and I will not pursue Lady Grove’s further distinctions. I pass
over the interesting theory that I ought to say to Jones (even
apparently if he is my dearest friend), “How is Mrs. Jones?”
instead of “How is your wife?” and I pass over an
impassioned declamation about bedspreads (I think) which has failed
to fire my blood.
The truth of the matter is really
quite simple. An aristocracy is a secret society; and this is
especially so when, as in the modern world, it is practically a
plutocracy. The one idea of a secret society is to change the
password. Lady Grove falls naturally into a pure perversity because
she feels subconsciously that the people of England can be more
effectively kept at a distance by a perpetual torrent of new tests
than by the persistence of a few old ones. She knows that in the
educated “middle class” there is an idea that it is
vulgar to say port wine; therefore she reverses the idea–she
says that the man who would say “port” is a man who would
say, “How is your wife?” She says it because she knows
both these remarks to be quite obvious and reasonable.
The only thing to be done or said in
reply, I suppose, would be to apply the same principle of bold
mystification on our own part. I do not see why I should not write a
book called “Etiquette in Fleet Street,” and terrify
every one else out of that thoroughfare by mysterious allusions to
the mistakes that they generally make. I might say: “This is
the kind of man who would wear a green tie when he went into a
tobacconist’s,” or “You don’t see anything
wrong in drinking a Benedictine on Thursday?. . . . No, of course you
wouldn’t.” I might asseverate with passionate disgust and
disdain: “The man who is capable of writing sonnets as well as
triolets is capable of climbing an omnibus while holding an
umbrella.” It seems a simple method; if ever I should master it
perhaps I may govern England.
THE “EATANSWILL GAZETTE.”
The other day some one presented me
with a paper called the Eatanswill Gazette. I need hardly say
that I could not have been more startled if I had seen a coach coming
down the road with old Mr. Tony Weller on the box. But, indeed, the
case is much more extraordinary than that would be. Old Mr. Weller
was a good man, a specially and seriously good man, a proud father, a
very patient husband, a sane moralist, and a reliable ally. One could
not be so very much surprised if somebody pretended to be Tony
Weller. But the Eatanswill Gazette is definitely depicted in
“Pickwick” as a dirty and unscrupulous rag, soaked with
slander and nonsense. It was really interesting to find a modern
paper proud to take its name. The case cannot be compared to anything
so simple as a resurrection of one of the “Pickwick”
characters; yet a very good parallel could easily be found. It is
almost exactly as if a firm of solicitors were to open their offices
to–morrow under the name of Dodson and Fogg.
It was at once apparent, of course,
that the thing was a joke. But what was not apparent, what only grew
upon the mind with gradual wonder and terror, was the fact that it
had its serious side. The paper is published in the well–known
town of Sudbury, in Suffolk. And it seems that there is a standing
quarrel between Sudbury and the county town of Ipswich as to which
was the town described by Dickens in his celebrated sketch of an
election. Each town proclaims with passion that it was Eatanswill. If
each town proclaimed with passion that it was not Eatanswill, I might
be able to understand it. Eatanswill, according to Dickens, was a
town alive with loathsome corruption, hypocritical in all its public
utterances, and venal in all its votes. Yet, two highly respectable
towns compete for the honour of having been this particular cesspool,
just as ten cities fought to be the birthplace of Homer. They claim
to be its original as keenly as if they were claiming to be the
original of More’s “Utopia” or Morris’s
“Earthly Paradise.” They grow seriously heated over the
matter. The men of Ipswich say warmly, “It must have been our
town; for Dickens says it was corrupt, and a more corrupt town than
our town you couldn’t have met in a month.” The men of
Sudbury reply with rising passion, “Permit us to tell you,
gentlemen, that our town was quite as corrupt as your town any day of
the week. Our town was a common nuisance; and we defy our enemies to
question it.” “Perhaps you will tell us,” sneer the
citizens of Ipswich, “that your politics were ever as
thoroughly filthy as–” “As filthy as anything,”
answer the Sudbury men, undauntedly. “Nothing in politics could
be filthier. Dickens must have noticed how disgusting we were.”
“And could he have failed to notice,” the others reason
indignantly, “how disgusting we were? You could smell us a mile
off. You Sudbury fellows may think yourselves very fine, but let me
tell you that, compared to our city, Sudbury was an honest place.”
And so the controversy goes on. It seems to me to be a new and odd
kind of controversy.
Naturally, an outsider feels inclined
to ask why Eatanswill should be either one or the other. As a matter
of fact, I fear Eatanswill was every town in the country. It is
surely clear that when Dickens described the Eatanswill election he
did not mean it as a satire on Sudbury or a satire on Ipswich; he
meant it as a satire on England. The Eatanswill election is not a
joke against Eatanswill; it is a joke against elections. If the
satire is merely local, it practically loses its point; just as the
“Circumlocution Office” would lose its point if it were
not supposed to be a true sketch of all Government offices; just as
the Lord Chancellor in “Bleak House” would lose his point
if he were not supposed to be symbolic and representative of all Lord
Chancellors. The whole moral meaning would vanish if we supposed that
Oliver Twist had got by accident into an exceptionally bad workhouse,
or that Mr. Dorrit was in the only debtors’ prison that was not
well managed. Dickens was making game, not of places, but of methods.
He poured all his powerful genius into trying to make the people
ashamed of the methods. But he seems only to have succeeded in making
people proud of the places. In any case, the controversy is conducted
in a truly extraordinary way. No one seems to allow for the fact
that, after all, Dickens was writing a novel, and a highly fantastic
novel at that. Facts in support of Sudbury or Ipswich are quoted not
only from the story itself, which is wild and wandering enough, but
even from the yet wilder narratives which incidentally occur in the
story, such as Sam Weller’s description of how his father, on
the way to Eatanswill, tipped all the voters into the canal. This may
quite easily be (to begin with) an entertaining tarradiddle of Sam’s
own invention, told, like many other even more improbable stories,
solely to amuse Mr. Pickwick. Yet the champions of these two towns
positively ask each other to produce a canal, or to fail for ever in
their attempt to prove themselves the most corrupt town in England.
As far as I remember, Sam’s story of the canal ends with Mr.
Pickwick eagerly asking whether everybody was rescued, and Sam
solemnly replying that one old gentleman’s hat was found, but
that he was not sure whether his head was in it. If the canal is to
be taken as realistic, why not the hat and the head? If these critics
ever find the canal I recommend them to drag it for the body of the
old gentleman.
Both sides refuse to allow for the
fact that the characters in the story are comic characters. For
instance, Mr. Percy Fitzgerald, the eminent student of Dickens,
writes to the Eatanswill Gazette to say that Sudbury, a small
town, could not have been Eatanswill, because one of the candidates
speaks of its great manufactures. But obviously one of the candidates
would have spoken of its great manufactures if it had had nothing but
a row of apple–stalls. One of the candidates might have said
that the commerce of Eatanswill eclipsed Carthage, and covered every
sea; it would have been quite in the style of Dickens. But when the
champion of Sudbury answers him, he does not point out this plain
mistake. He answers by making another mistake exactly of the same
kind. He says that Eatanswill was not a busy, important place. And
his odd reason is that Mrs. Pott said she was dull there. But
obviously Mrs. Pott would have said she was dull anywhere. She was
setting her cap at Mr. Winkle. Moreover, it was the whole point of
her character in any case. Mrs. Pott was that kind of woman. If she
had been in Ipswich she would have said that she ought to be in
London. If she was in London she would have said that she ought to be
in Paris. The first disputant proves Eatanswill grand because a
servile candidate calls it grand. The second proves it dull because a
discontented woman calls it dull.
The great part of the controversy
seems to be conducted in the spirit of highly irrelevant realism.
Sudbury cannot be Eatanswill, because there was a fancy–dress
shop at Eatanswill, and there is no record of a fancy–dress
shop at Sudbury. Sudbury must be Eatanswill because there were heavy
roads outside Eatanswill, and there are heavy roads outside Sudbury.
Ipswich cannot be Eatanswill, because Mrs. Leo Hunter’s country
seat would not be near a big town. Ipswich must be Eatanswill because
Mrs. Leo Hunter’s country seat would be near a large town.
Really, Dickens might have been allowed to take liberties with such
things as these, even if he had been mentioning the place by name. If
I were writing a story about the town of Limerick, I should take the
liberty of introducing a bun–shop without taking a journey to
Limerick to see whether there was a bun–shop there. If I wrote
a romance about Torquay, I should hold myself free to introduce a
house with a green door without having studied a list of all the
coloured doors in the town. But if, in order to make it particularly
obvious that I had not meant the town for a photograph either of
Torquay or Limerick, I had gone out of my way to give the place a
wild, fictitious name of my own, I think that in that case I should
be justified in tearing my hair with rage if the people of Limerick
or Torquay began to argue about bun–shops and green doors. No
reasonable man would expect Dickens to be so literal as all that even
about Bath or Bury St. Edmunds, which do exist; far less need he be
literal about Eatanswill, which didn’t exist.
I must confess, however, that I
incline to the Sudbury side of the argument. This does not only arise
from the sympathy which all healthy people have for small places as
against big ones; it arises from some really good qualities in this
particular Sudbury publication. First of all, the champions of
Sudbury seem to be more open to the sensible and humorous view of the
book than the champions of Ipswich–at least, those that appear
in this discussion. Even the Sudbury champion, bent on finding
realistic clothes, rebels (to his eternal honour) when Mr. Percy
Fitzgerald tries to show that Bob Sawyer’s famous statement
that he was neither Buff nor Blue, “but a sort of plaid,”
must have been copied from some silly man at Ipswich who said that
his politics were “half and half.” Anybody might have
made either of the two jokes. But it was the whole glory and meaning
of Dickens that he confined himself to making jokes that anybody
might have made a little better than anybody would have made them.
FAIRY TALES
Some
solemn and superficial people (for nearly all very superficial people
are solemn) have declared that the fairy–tales are immoral;
they base this upon some accidental circumstances or regrettable
incidents in the war between giants and boys, some cases in which the
latter indulged in unsympathetic deceptions or even in practical
jokes. The objection, however, is not only false, but very much the
reverse of the facts. The fairy–tales are at root not only
moral in the sense of being innocent, but moral in the sense of being
didactic, moral in the sense of being moralising. It is all very well
to talk of the freedom of fairyland, but there was precious little
freedom in fairyland by the best official accounts. Mr. W.B. Yeats
and other sensitive modern souls, feeling that modern life is about
as black a slavery as ever oppressed mankind (they are right enough
there), have especially described elfland as a place of utter ease
and abandonment–a place where the soul can turn every way at
will like the wind. Science denounces the idea of a capricious God;
but Mr. Yeats’s school suggests that in that world every one is
a capricious god. Mr. Yeats himself has said a hundred times in that
sad and splendid literary style which makes him the first of all
poets now writing in English (I will not say of all English poets,
for Irishmen are familiar with the practice of physical assault), he
has, I say, called up a hundred times the picture of the terrible
freedom of the fairies, who typify the ultimate anarchy of art—“Where
nobody grows old or weary or wise, Where nobody grows old or godly
or grave.”
But, after all (it is a shocking
thing to say), I doubt whether Mr. Yeats really knows the real
philosophy of the fairies. He is not simple enough; he is not stupid
enough. Though I say it who should not, in good sound human stupidity
I would knock Mr. Yeats out any day. The fairies like me better than
Mr. Yeats; they can take me in more. And I have my doubts whether
this feeling of the free, wild spirits on the crest of hill or wave
is really the central and simple spirit of folk–lore. I think
the poets have made a mistake: because the world of the fairy–tales
is a brighter and more varied world than ours, they have fancied it
less moral; really it is brighter and more varied because it is more
moral. Suppose a man could be born in a modern prison. It is
impossible, of course, because nothing human can happen in a modern
prison, though it could sometimes in an ancient dungeon. A modern
prison is always inhuman, even when it is not inhumane. But suppose a
man were born in a modern prison, and grew accustomed to the deadly
silence and the disgusting indifference; and suppose he were then
suddenly turned loose upon the life and laughter of Fleet Street. He
would, of course, think that the literary men in Fleet Street were a
free and happy race; yet how sadly, how ironically, is this the
reverse of the case! And so again these toiling serfs in Fleet
Street, when they catch a glimpse of the fairies, think the fairies
are utterly free. But fairies are like journalists in this and many
other respects. Fairies and journalists have an apparent gaiety and a
delusive beauty. Fairies and journalists seem to be lovely and
lawless; they seem to be both of them too exquisite to descend to the
ugliness of everyday duty. But it is an illusion created by the
sudden sweetness of their presence. Journalists live under law; and
so in fact does fairyland.
If you really read the fairy–tales,
you will observe that one idea runs from one end of them to the
other–the idea that peace and happiness can only exist on some
condition. This idea, which is the core of ethics, is the core of the
nursery–tales. The whole happiness of fairyland hangs upon a
thread, upon one thread. Cinderella may have a dress woven on
supernatural looms and blazing with unearthly brilliance; but she
must be back when the clock strikes twelve. The king may invite
fairies to the christening, but he must invite all the fairies or
frightful results will follow. Bluebeard’s wife may open all
doors but one. A promise is broken to a cat, and the whole world goes
wrong. A promise is broken to a yellow dwarf, and the whole world
goes wrong. A girl may be the bride of the God of Love himself if she
never tries to see him; she sees him, and he vanishes away. A girl is
given a box on condition she does not open it; she opens it, and all
the evils of this world rush out at her. A man and woman are put in a
garden on condition that they do not eat one fruit: they eat it, and
lose their joy in all the fruits of the earth.
This great idea, then, is the
backbone of all folk–lore–the idea that all happiness
hangs on one thin veto; all positive joy depends on one negative.
Now, it is obvious that there are many philosophical and religious
ideas akin to or symbolised by this; but it is not with them I wish
to deal here. It is surely obvious that all ethics ought to be taught
to this fairy–tale tune; that, if one does the thing forbidden,
one imperils all the things provided. A man who breaks his promise to
his wife ought to be reminded that, even if she is a cat, the case of
the fairy–cat shows that such conduct may be incautious. A
burglar just about to open some one else’s safe should be
playfully reminded that he is in the perilous posture of the
beautiful Pandora: he is about to lift the forbidden lid and loosen
evils unknown. The boy eating some one’s apples in some one’s
apple tree should be a reminder that he has come to a mystical moment
of his life, when one apple may rob him of all others. This is the
profound morality of fairy–tales; which, so far from being
lawless, go to the root of all law. Instead of finding (like common
books of ethics) a rationalistic basis for each Commandment, they
find the great mystical basis for all Commandments. We are in this
fairyland on sufferance; it is not for us to quarrel with the
conditions under which we enjoy this wild vision of the world. The
vetoes are indeed extraordinary, but then so are the concessions. The
idea of property, the idea of some one else’s apples, is a rum
idea; but then the idea of there being any apples is a rum idea. It
is strange and weird that I cannot with safety drink ten bottles of
champagne; but then the champagne itself is strange and weird, if you
come to that. If I have drunk of the fairies’ drink it is but
just I should drink by the fairies’ rules. We may not see the
direct logical connection between three beautiful silver spoons and a
large ugly policeman; but then who in fairy tales ever could see the
direct logical connection between three bears and a giant, or between
a rose and a roaring beast? Not only can these fairy–tales be
enjoyed because they are moral, but morality can be enjoyed because
it puts us in fairyland, in a world at once of wonder and of war.
TOM JONES AND MORALITY
The two hundredth anniversary of
Henry Fielding is very justly celebrated, even if, as far as can be
discovered, it is only celebrated by the newspapers. It would be too
much to expect that any such merely chronological incident should
induce the people who write about Fielding to read him; this kind of
neglect is only another name for glory. A great classic means a man
whom one can praise without having read. This is not in itself wholly
unjust; it merely implies a certain respect for the realisation and
fixed conclusions of the mass of mankind. I have never read Pindar (I
mean I have never read the Greek Pindar; Peter Pindar I have read all
right), but the mere fact that I have not read Pindar, I think, ought
not to prevent me and certainly would not prevent me from talking of
“the masterpieces of Pindar,” or of “great poets
like Pindar or Æschylus.” The very learned men are
angularly unenlightened on this as on many other subjects; and the
position they take up is really quite unreasonable. If any ordinary
journalist or man of general reading alludes to Villon or to Homer,
they consider it a quite triumphant sneer to say to the man, “You
cannot read mediæval French,” or “You cannot read
Homeric Greek.” But it is not a triumphant sneer–or,
indeed, a sneer at all. A man has got as much right to employ in his
speech the established and traditional facts of human history as he
has to employ any other piece of common human information. And it is
as reasonable for a man who knows no French to assume that Villon was
a good poet as it would be for a man who has no ear for music to
assume that Beethoven was a good musician. Because he himself has no
ear for music, that is no reason why he should assume that the human
race has no ear for music. Because I am ignorant (as I am), it does
not follow that I ought to assume that I am deceived. The man who
would not praise Pindar unless he had read him would be a low,
distrustful fellow, the worst kind of sceptic, who doubts not only
God, but man. He would be like a man who could not call Mount Everest
high unless he had climbed it. He would be like a man who would not
admit that the North Pole was cold until he had been there.
But I think there is a limit, and a
highly legitimate limit, to this process. I think a man may praise
Pindar without knowing the top of a Greek letter from the bottom. But
I think that if a man is going to abuse Pindar, if he is going to
denounce, refute, and utterly expose Pindar, if he is going to show
Pindar up as the utter ignoramus and outrageous impostor that he is,
then I think it will be just as well perhaps–I think, at any
rate, it would do no harm–if he did know a little Greek, and
even had read a little Pindar. And I think the same situation would
be involved if the critic were concerned to point out that Pindar was
scandalously immoral, pestilently cynical, or low and beastly in his
views of life. When people brought such attacks against the morality
of Pindar, I should regret that they could not read Greek; and when
they bring such attacks against the morality of Fielding, I regret
very much that they cannot read English.
There seems to be an extraordinary
idea abroad that Fielding was in some way an immoral or offensive
writer. I have been astounded by the number of the leading articles,
literary articles, and other articles written about him just now in
which there is a curious tone of apologising for the man. One critic
says that after all he couldn’t help it, because he lived in
the eighteenth century; another says that we must allow for the
change of manners and ideas; another says that he was not altogether
without generous and humane feelings; another suggests that he clung
feebly, after all, to a few of the less important virtues. What on
earth does all this mean? Fielding described Tom Jones as going on in
a certain way, in which, most unfortunately, a very large number of
young men do go on. It is unnecessary to say that Henry Fielding knew
that it was an unfortunate way of going on. Even Tom Jones knew that.
He said in so many words that it was a very unfortunate way of going
on; he said, one may almost say, that it had ruined his life; the
passage is there for the benefit of any one who may take the trouble
to read the book. There is ample evidence (though even this is of a
mystical and indirect kind), there is ample evidence that Fielding
probably thought that it was better to be Tom Jones than to be an
utter coward and sneak. There is simply not one rag or thread or
speck of evidence to show that Fielding thought that it was better to
be Tom Jones than to be a good man. All that he is concerned with is
the description of a definite and very real type of young man; the
young man whose passions and whose selfish necessities sometimes
seemed to be stronger than anything else in him.
The practical morality of Tom Jones
is bad, though not so bad, spiritually speaking, as the
practical morality of Arthur Pendennis or the practical morality of
Pip, and certainly nothing like so bad as the profound practical
immorality of Daniel Deronda. The practical morality of Tom Jones is
bad; but I cannot see any proof that his theoretical morality was
particularly bad. There is no need to tell the majority of modern
young men even to live up to the theoretical ethics of Henry
Fielding. They would suddenly spring into the stature of archangels
if they lived up to the theoretic ethics of poor Tom Jones. Tom Jones
is still alive, with all his good and all his evil; he is walking
about the streets; we meet him every day. We meet with him, we drink
with him, we smoke with him, we talk with him, we talk about him. The
only difference is that we have no longer the intellectual courage to
write about him. We split up the supreme and central human being, Tom
Jones, into a number of separate aspects. We let Mr. J.M. Barrie
write about him in his good moments, and make him out better than he
is. We let Zola write about him in his bad moments, and make him out
much worse than he is. We let Maeterlinck celebrate those moments of
spiritual panic which he knows to be cowardly; we let Mr. Rudyard
Kipling celebrate those moments of brutality which he knows to be far
more cowardly. We let obscene writers write about the obscenities of
this ordinary man. We let puritan writers write about the purities of
this ordinary man. We look through one peephole that makes men out as
devils, and we call it the new art. We look through another peephole
that makes men out as angels, and we call it the New Theology. But if
we pull down some dusty old books from the bookshelf, if we turn over
some old mildewed leaves, and if in that obscurity and decay we find
some faint traces of a tale about a complete man, such a man as is
walking on the pavement outside, we suddenly pull a long face, and we
call it the coarse morals of a bygone age.
The truth is that all these things
mark a certain change in the general view of morals; not, I think, a
change for the better. We have grown to associate morality in a book
with a kind of optimism and prettiness; according to us, a moral book
is a book about moral people. But the old idea was almost exactly the
opposite; a moral book was a book about immoral people. A moral book
was full of pictures like Hogarth’s “Gin Lane” or
“Stages of Cruelty,” or it recorded, like the popular
broadsheet, “God’s dreadful judgment” against some
blasphemer or murderer. There is a philosophical reason for this
change. The homeless scepticism of our time has reached a
sub–conscious feeling that morality is somehow merely a matter
of human taste–an accident of psychology. And if goodness only
exists in certain human minds, a man wishing to praise goodness will
naturally exaggerate the amount of it that there is in human minds or
the number of human minds in which it is supreme. Every confession
that man is vicious is a confession that virtue is visionary. Every
book which admits that evil is real is felt in some vague way to be
admitting that good is unreal. The modern instinct is that if the
heart of man is evil, there is nothing that remains good. But the
older feeling was that if the heart of man was ever so evil, there
was something that remained good–goodness remained good. An
actual avenging virtue existed outside the human race; to that men
rose, or from that men fell away. Therefore, of course, this law
itself was as much demonstrated in the breach as in the observance.
If Tom Jones violated morality, so much the worse for Tom Jones.
Fielding did not feel, as a melancholy modern would have done, that
every sin of Tom Jones was in some way breaking the spell, or we may
even say destroying the fiction of morality. Men spoke of the sinner
breaking the law; but it was rather the law that broke him. And what
modern people call the foulness and freedom of Fielding is generally
the severity and moral stringency of Fielding. He would not have
thought that he was serving morality at all if he had written a book
all about nice people. Fielding would have considered Mr. Ian
Maclaren extremely immoral; and there is something to be said for
that view. Telling the truth about the terrible struggle of the human
soul is surely a very elementary part of the ethics of honesty. If
the characters are not wicked, the book is. This older and firmer
conception of right as existing outside human weakness and without
reference to human error can be felt in the very lightest and loosest
of the works of old English literature. It is commonly unmeaning
enough to call Shakspere a great moralist; but in this particular way
Shakspere is a very typical moralist. Whenever he alludes to right
and wrong it is always with this old implication. Right is right,
even if nobody does it. Wrong is wrong, even if everybody is wrong
about it.
THE MAID OF ORLEANS
A considerable time ago (at far too
early an age, in fact) I read Voltaire’s “La Pucelle,”
a savage sarcasm on the traditional purity of Joan of Arc, very
dirty, and very funny. I had not thought of it again for years, but
it came back into my mind this morning because I began to turn over
the leaves of the new “Jeanne d’Arc,” by that great
and graceful writer, Anatole France. It is written in a tone of
tender sympathy, and a sort of sad reverence; it never loses touch
with a noble tact and courtesy, like that of a gentleman escorting a
peasant girl through the modern crowd. It is invariably respectful to
Joan, and even respectful to her religion. And being myself a furious
admirer of Joan the Maid, I have reflectively compared the two
methods, and I come to the conclusion that I prefer Voltaire’s.
When a man of Voltaire’s school
has to explode a saint or a great religious hero, he says that such a
person is a common human fool, or a common human fraud. But when a
man like Anatole France has to explode a saint, he explains a saint
as somebody belonging to his particular fussy little literary set.
Voltaire read human nature into Joan of Arc, though it was only the
brutal part of human nature. At least it was not specially Voltaire’s
nature. But M. France read M. France’s nature into Joan of
Arc–all the cold kindness, all the homeless sentimental sin of
the modern literary man. There is one book that it recalled to me
with startling vividness, though I have not seen the matter mentioned
anywhere; Renan’s “Vie de Jésus.” It has
just the same general intention: that if you do not attack
Christianity, you can at least patronise it. My own instinct, apart
from my opinions, would be quite the other way. If I disbelieved in
Christianity, I should be the loudest blasphemer in Hyde Park.
Nothing ought to be too big for a brave man to attack; but there are
some things too big for a man to patronise.
And I must say that the historical
method seems to me excessively unreasonable. I have no knowledge of
history, but I have as much knowledge of reason as Anatole France.
And, if anything is irrational, it seems to me that the Renan–France
way of dealing with miraculous stories is irrational. The
Renan–France method is simply this: you explain supernatural
stories that have some foundation simply by inventing natural stories
that have no foundation. Suppose that you are confronted with the
statement that Jack climbed up the beanstalk into the sky. It is
perfectly philosophical to reply that you do not think that he did.
It is (in my opinion) even more philosophical to reply that he may
very probably have done so. But the Renan–France method is to
write like this: “When we consider Jack’s curious and
even perilous heredity, which no doubt was derived from a female
greengrocer and a profligate priest, we can easily understand how the
ideas of heaven and a beanstalk came to be combined in his mind.
Moreover, there is little doubt that he must have met some wandering
conjurer from India, who told him about the tricks of the mango
plant, and how t is sent up to the sky. We can imagine these two
friends, the old man and the young, wandering in the woods together
at evening, looking at the red and level clouds, as on that night
when the old man pointed to a small beanstalk, and told his too
imaginative companion that this also might be made to scale the
heavens. And then, when we remember the quite exceptional psychology
of Jack, when we remember how there was in him a union of the
prosaic, the love of plain vegetables, with an almost irrelevant
eagerness for the unattainable, for invisibility and the void, we
shall no longer wonder that it was to him especially that was sent
this sweet, though merely symbolic, dream of the tree uniting earth
and heaven.” That is the way that Renan and France write, only
they do it better. But, really, a rationalist like myself becomes a
little impatient and feels inclined to say, “But, hang it all,
what do you know about the heredity of Jack or the psychology of
Jack? You know nothing about Jack at all, except that some people say
that he climbed up a beanstalk. Nobody would ever have thought of
mentioning him if he hadn’t. You must interpret him in terms of
the beanstalk religion; you cannot merely interpret religion in terms
of him. We have the materials of this story, and we can believe them
or not. But we have not got the materials to make another story.”
It is no exaggeration to say that
this is the manner of M. Anatole France in dealing with Joan of Arc.
Because her miracle is incredible to his somewhat old–fashioned
materialism, he does not therefore dismiss it and her to fairyland
with Jack and the Beanstalk. He tries to invent a real story, for
which he can find no real evidence. He produces a scientific
explanation which is quite destitute of any scientific proof. It is
as if I (being entirely ignorant of botany and chemistry) said that
the beanstalk grew to the sky because nitrogen and argon got into the
subsidiary ducts of the corolla. To take the most obvious example,
the principal character in M. France’s story is a person who
never existed at all. All Joan’s wisdom and energy, it seems,
came from a certain priest, of whom there is not the tiniest trace in
all the multitudinous records of her life. The only foundation I can
find for this fancy is the highly undemocratic idea that a peasant
girl could not possibly have any ideas of her own. It is very hard
for a freethinker to remain democratic. The writer seems altogether
to forget what is meant by the moral atmosphere of a community. To
say that Joan must have learnt her vision of a virgin overthrowing
evil from a priest, is like saying that some modern girl in
London, pitying the poor, must have learnt it from a Labour
Member. She would learn it where the Labour Member learnt it–in
the whole state of our society.
But that is the modern method: the
method of the reverent sceptic. When you find a life entirely
incredible and incomprehensible from the outside, you pretend that
you understand the inside. As Renan, the rationalist, could not make
any sense out of Christ’s most public acts, he proceeded to
make an ingenious system out of His private thoughts. As Anatole
France, on his own intellectual principle, cannot believe in what
Joan of Arc did, he professes to be her dearest friend, and to know
exactly what she meant. I cannot feel it to be a very rational manner
of writing history; and sooner or later we shall have to find some
more solid way of dealing with those spiritual phenomena with which
all history is as closely spotted and spangled as the sky is with
stars.
Joan of Arc is a wild and wonderful
thing enough, but she is much saner than most of her critics and
biographers. We shall not recover the common sense of Joan until we
have recovered her mysticism. Our wars fail, because they begin with
something sensible and obvious–such as getting to Pretoria by
Christmas. But her war succeeded–because it began with
something wild and perfect–the saints delivering France. She
put her idealism in the right place, and her realism also in the
right place: we moderns get both displaced. She put her dreams and
her sentiment into her aims, where they ought to be; she put her
practicality into her practice. In modern Imperial wars, the case is
reversed. Our dreams, our aims are always, we insist, quite
practical. It is our practice that is dreamy.
It is not for us to explain this
flaming figure in terms of our tired and querulous culture. Rather we
must try to explain ourselves by the blaze of such fixed stars. Those
who called her a witch hot from hell were much more sensible than
those who depict her as a silly sentimental maiden prompted by her
parish priest. If I have to choose between the two schools of her
scattered enemies, I could take my place with those subtle clerks who
thought her divine mission devilish, rather than with those rustic
aunts and uncles who thought it impossible.
A DEAD POET
With Francis Thompson we lose the
greatest poetic energy since Browning. His energy was of somewhat the
same kind. Browning was intellectually intricate because he was
morally simple. He was too simple to explain himself; he was too
humble to suppose that other people needed any explanation. But his
real energy, and the real energy of Francis Thompson, was best
expressed in the fact that both poets were at once fond of immensity
and also fond of detail. Any common Imperialist can have large ideas
so long as he is not called upon to have small ideas also. Any common
scientific philosopher can have small ideas so long as he is not
called upon to have large ideas as well. But great poets use the
telescope and also the microscope. Great poets are obscure for two
opposite reasons; now, because they are talking about something too
large for any one to understand, and now again because they are
talking about something too small for any one to see. Francis
Thompson possessed both these infinities. He escaped by being too
small, as the microbe escapes; or he escaped by being too large, as
the universe escapes. Any one who knows Francis Thompson’s
poetry knows quite well the truth to which I refer. For the benefit
of any person who does not know it, I may mention two cases taken
from memory. I have not the book by me, so I can only render the
poetical passages in a clumsy paraphrase. But there was one poem of
which the image was so vast that it was literally difficult for a
time to take it in; he was describing the evening earth with its mist
and fume and fragrance, and represented the whole as rolling upwards
like a smoke; then suddenly he called the whole ball of the earth a
thurible, and said that some gigantic spirit swung it slowly before
God. That is the case of the image too large for comprehension.
Another instance sticks in my mind of the image which is too small.
In one of his poems, he says that abyss between the known and the
unknown is bridged by “Pontifical death.” There are about
ten historical and theological puns in that one word. That a priest
means a pontiff, that a pontiff means a bridge–maker, that
death is certainly a bridge, that death may turn out after all to be
a reconciling priest, that at least priests and bridges both attest
to the fact that one thing can get separated from another thing–these
ideas, and twenty more, are all actually concentrated in the word
“pontifical.” In Francis Thompson’s poetry, as in
the poetry of the universe, you can work infinitely out and out, but
yet infinitely in and in. These two infinities are the mark of
greatness; and he was a great poet.
Beneath the tide of praise which was
obviously due to the dead poet, there is an evident undercurrent of
discussion about him; some charges of moral weakness were at least
important enough to be authoritatively contradicted in the Nation;
and, in connection with this and other things, there has been a
continuous stir of comment upon his attraction to and gradual
absorption in Catholic theological ideas. This question is so
important that I think it ought to be considered and understood even
at the present time. It is, of course, true that Francis Thompson
devoted himself more and more to poems not only purely Catholic, but,
one may say, purely ecclesiastical. And it is, moreover, true that
(if things go on as they are going on at present) more and more good
poets will do the same. Poets will tend towards Christian orthodoxy
for a perfectly plain reason; because it is about the simplest and
freest thing now left in the world. On this point it is very
necessary to be clear. When people impute special vices to the
Christian Church, they seem entirely to forget that the world (which
is the only other thing there is) has these vices much more. The
Church has been cruel; but the world has been much more cruel. The
Church has plotted; but the world has plotted much more. The Church
has been superstitious; but it has never been so superstitious as the
world is when left to itself.
Now, poets in our epoch will tend
towards ecclesiastical religion strictly because it is just a little
more free than anything else. Take, for instance, the case of symbol
and ritualism. All reasonable men believe in symbol; but some
reasonable men do not believe in ritualism; by which they mean, I
imagine, a symbolism too complex, elaborate, and mechanical. But
whenever they talk of ritualism they always seem to mean the
ritualism of the Church. Why should they not mean the ritual of the
world? It is much more ritualistic. The ritual of the Army, the
ritual of the Navy, the ritual of the Law Courts, the ritual of
Parliament are much more ritualistic. The ritual of a dinner–party
is much more ritualistic. Priests may put gold and great jewels on
the chalice; but at least there is only one chalice to put them on.
When you go to a dinner–party they put in front of you five
different chalices, of five weird and heraldic shapes, to symbolise
five different kinds of wine; an insane extension of ritual from
which Mr. Percy Dearmer would fly shrieking. A bishop wears a mitre;
but he is not thought more or less of a bishop according to whether
you can see the very latest curves in his mitre. But a swell is
thought more or less of a swell according to whether you can see the
very latest curves in his hat. There is more fuss about
symbols in the world than in the Church.
And yet (strangely enough) though men
fuss more about the worldly symbols, they mean less by them. It is
the mark of religious forms that they declare something unknown. But
it is the mark of worldly forms that they declare something which is
known, and which is known to be untrue. When the Pope in an
Encyclical calls himself your father, it is a matter of faith or of
doubt. But when the Duke of Devonshire in a letter calls himself
yours obediently, you know that he means the opposite of what he
says. Religious forms are, at the worst, fables; they might be true.
Secular forms are falsehoods; they are not true. Take a more topical
case. The German Emperor has more uniforms than the Pope. But,
moreover, the Pope’s vestments all imply a claim to be
something purely mystical and doubtful. Many of the German Emperor’s
uniforms imply a claim to be something which he certainly is not and
which it would be highly disgusting if he were. The Pope may or may
not be the Vicar of Christ. But the Kaiser certainly is not an
English Colonel. If the thing were reality it would be treason. If it
is mere ritual, it is by far the most unreal ritual on earth.
Now, poetical people like Francis
Thompson will, as things stand, tend away from secular society and
towards religion for the reason above described: that there are
crowds of symbols in both, but that those of religion are simpler and
mean more. To take an evident type, the Cross is more poetical than
the Union Jack, because it is simpler. The more simple an idea is,
the more it is fertile in variations. Francis Thompson could have
written any number of good poems on the Cross, because it is a
primary symbol. The number of poems which Mr. Rudyard Kipling could
write on the Union Jack is, fortunately, limited, because the Union
Jack is too complex to produce luxuriance. The same principle applies
to any possible number of cases. A poet like Francis Thompson could
deduce perpetually rich and branching meanings out of two plain facts
like bread and wine; with bread and wine he can expand everything to
everywhere. But with a French menu he cannot expand anything; except
perhaps himself. Complicated ideas do not produce any more ideas.
Mongrels do not breed. Religious ritual attracts because there is
some sense in it. Religious imagery, so far from being subtle, is the
only simple thing left for poets. So far from being merely
superhuman, it is the only human thing left for human beings.
CHRISTMAS
There is no more dangerous or
disgusting habit than that of celebrating Christmas before it comes,
as I am doing in this article. It is the very essence of a festival
that it breaks upon one brilliantly and abruptly, that at one moment
the great day is not and the next moment the great day is. Up to a
certain specific instant you are feeling ordinary and sad; for it is
only Wednesday. At the next moment your heart leaps up and your soul
and body dance together like lovers; for in one burst and blaze it
has become Thursday. I am assuming (of course) that you are a
worshipper of Thor, and that you celebrate his day once a week,
possibly with human sacrifice. If, on the other hand, you are a
modern Christian Englishman, you hail (of course) with the same
explosion of gaiety the appearance of the English Sunday. But I say
that whatever the day is that is to you festive or symbolic, it is
essential that there should be a quite clear black line between it
and the time going before. And all the old wholesome customs in
connection with Christmas were to the effect that one should not
touch or see or know or speak of something before the actual coming
of Christmas Day. Thus, for instance, children were never given their
presents until the actual coming of the appointed hour. The presents
were kept tied up in brown–paper parcels, out of which an arm
of a doll or the leg of a donkey sometimes accidentally stuck. I wish
this principle were adopted in respect of modern Christmas ceremonies
and publications. Especially it ought to be observed in connection
with what are called the Christmas numbers of magazines. The editors
of the magazines bring out their Christmas numbers so long before the
time that the reader is more likely to be still lamenting for the
turkey of last year than to have seriously settled down to a solid
anticipation of the turkey which is to come. Christmas numbers of
magazines ought to be tied up in brown paper and kept for Christmas
Day. On consideration, I should favour the editors being tied up in
brown paper. Whether the leg or arm of an editor should ever be
allowed to protrude I leave to individual choice.
Of course, all this secrecy about
Christmas is merely sentimental and ceremonial; if you do not like
what is sentimental and ceremonial, do not celebrate Christmas at
all. You will not be punished if you don’t; also, since we are
no longer ruled by those sturdy Puritans who won for us civil and
religious liberty, you will not even be punished if you do. But I
cannot understand why any one should bother about a ceremonial except
ceremonially. If a thing only exists in order to be graceful, do it
gracefully or do not do it. If a thing only exists as something
professing to be solemn, do it solemnly or do not do it. There is no
sense in doing it slouchingly; nor is there even any liberty. I can
understand the man who takes off his hat to a lady because it is the
customary symbol. I can understand him, I say; in fact, I know him
quite intimately. I can also understand the man who refuses to take
off his hat to a lady, like the old Quakers, because he thinks that a
symbol is superstition. But what point would there be in so
performing an arbitrary form of respect that it was not a form of
respect? We respect the gentleman who takes off his hat to the lady;
we respect the fanatic who will not take off his hat to the lady. But
what should we think of the man who kept his hands in his pockets and
asked the lady to take his hat off for him because he felt tired?
This is combining insolence and
superstition; and the modern world is full of the strange
combination. There is no mark of the immense weak–mindedness of
modernity that is more striking than this general disposition to keep
up old forms, but to keep them up informally and feebly. Why take
something which was only meant to be respectful and preserve it
disrespectfully? Why take something which you could easily abolish as
a superstition and carefully perpetuate it as a bore? There have been
many instances of this half–witted compromise. Was it not true,
for instance, that the other day some mad American was trying to buy
Glastonbury Abbey and transfer it stone by stone to America? Such
things are not only illogical, but idiotic. There is no particular
reason why a pushing American financier should pay respect to
Glastonbury Abbey at all. But if he is to pay respect to Glastonbury
Abbey, he must pay respect to Glastonbury. If it is a matter of
sentiment, why should he spoil the scene? If it is not a matter of
sentiment, why should he ever have visited the scene? To call this
kind of thing Vandalism is a very inadequate and unfair description.
The Vandals were very sensible people. They did not believe in a
religion, and so they insulted it; they did not see any use for
certain buildings, and so they knocked them down. But they were not
such fools as to encumber their march with the fragments of the
edifice they had themselves spoilt. They were at least superior to
the modern American mode of reasoning. They did not desecrate the
stones because they held them sacred.
Another instance of the same
illogicality I observed the other day at some kind of “At
Home.” I saw what appeared to be a human being dressed in a
black evening–coat, black dress–waistcoat, and black
dress–trousers, but with a shirt–front made of Jaegar
wool. What can be the sense of this sort of thing? If a man thinks
hygiene more important than convention (a selfish and heathen view,
for the beasts that perish are more hygienic than man, and man is
only above them because he is more conventional), if, I say, a man
thinks that hygiene is more important than convention, what on earth
is there to oblige him to wear a shirt–front at all? But to
take a costume of which the only conceivable cause or advantage is
that it is a sort of uniform, and then not wear it in the uniform
way–this is to be neither a Bohemian nor a gentleman. It is a
foolish affectation, I think, in an English officer of the Life
Guards never to wear his uniform if he can help it. But it would be
more foolish still if he showed himself about town in a scarlet coat
and a Jaeger breast–plate. It is the custom nowadays to have
Ritual Commissions and Ritual Reports to make rather unmeaning
compromises in the ceremonial of the Church of England. So perhaps we
shall have an ecclesiastical compromise by which all the Bishops
shall wear Jaeger copes and Jaeger mitres. Similarly the King might
insist on having a Jaeger crown. But I do not think he will, for he
understands the logic of the matter better than that. The modern
monarch, like a reasonable fellow, wears his crown as seldom as he
can; but if he does it at all, then the only point of a crown is that
it is a crown. So let me assure the unknown gentleman in the woollen
vesture that the only point of a white shirt–front is that it
is a white shirt–front. Stiffness may be its impossible defect;
but it is certainly its only possible merit.
Let us be consistent, therefore,
about Christmas, and either keep customs or not keep them. If you do
not like sentiment and symbolism, you do not like Christmas; go away
and celebrate something else; I should suggest the birthday of Mr.
M’Cabe. No doubt you could have a sort of scientific Christmas
with a hygienic pudding and highly instructive presents stuffed into
a Jaeger stocking; go and have it then. If you like those things,
doubtless you are a good sort of fellow, and your intentions are
excellent. I have no doubt that you are really interested in
humanity; but I cannot think that humanity will ever be much
interested in you. Humanity is unhygienic from its very nature and
beginning. It is so much an exception in Nature that the laws of
Nature really mean nothing to it. Now Christmas is attacked also on
the humanitarian ground. Ouida called it a feast of slaughter and
gluttony. Mr. Shaw suggested that it was invented by poulterers. That
should be considered before it becomes more considerable.
I do not know whether an animal
killed at Christmas has had a better or a worse time than it would
have had if there had been no Christmas or no Christmas dinners. But
I do know that the fighting and suffering brotherhood to which I
belong and owe everything, Mankind, would have a much worse time if
there were no such thing as Christmas or Christmas dinners. Whether
the turkey which Scrooge gave to Bob Cratchit had experienced a
lovelier or more melancholy career than that of less attractive
turkeys is a subject upon which I cannot even conjecture. But that
Scrooge was better for giving the turkey and Cratchit happier for
getting it I know as two facts, as I know that I have two feet. What
life and death may be to a turkey is not my business; but the soul of
Scrooge and the body of Cratchit are my business. Nothing shall
induce me to darken human homes, to destroy human festivities, to
insult human gifts and human benefactions for the sake of some
hypothetical knowledge which Nature curtained from our eyes. We men
and women are all in the same boat, upon a stormy sea. We owe to each
other a terrible and tragic loyalty. If we catch sharks for food, let
them be killed most mercifully; let any one who likes love the
sharks, and pet the sharks, and tie ribbons round their necks and
give them sugar and teach them to dance. But if once a man suggests
that a shark is to be valued against a sailor, or that the poor shark
might be permitted to bite off a nigger’s leg occasionally;
then I would court–martial the man–he is a traitor to the
ship.
And while I take this view of
humanitarianism of the anti–Christmas kind, it is cogent to say
that I am a strong anti–vivisectionist. That is, if there is
any vivisection, I am against it. I am against the cutting–up
of conscious dogs for the same reason that I am in favour of the
eating of dead turkeys. The connection may not be obvious; but that
is because of the strangely unhealthy condition of modern thought. I
am against cruel vivisection as I am against a cruel anti–Christmas
asceticism, because they both involve the upsetting of existing
fellowships and the shocking of normal good feelings for the sake of
something that is intellectual, fanciful, and remote. It is not a
human thing, it is not a humane thing, when you see a poor woman
staring hungrily at a bloater, to think, not of the obvious feelings
of the woman, but of the unimaginable feelings of the deceased
bloater. Similarly, it is not human, it is not humane, when you look
at a dog to think about what theoretic discoveries you might possibly
make if you were allowed to bore a hole in his head. Both the
humanitarians’ fancy about the feelings concealed inside the
bloater, and the vivisectionists’ fancy about the knowledge
concealed inside the dog, are unhealthy fancies, because they upset a
human sanity that is certain for the sake of something that is of
necessity uncertain. The vivisectionist, for the sake of doing
something that may or may not be useful, does something that
certainly is horrible. The anti–Christmas humanitarian, in
seeking to have a sympathy with a turkey which no man can have with a
turkey, loses the sympathy he has already with the happiness of
millions of the poor.
It is not uncommon nowadays for the
insane extremes in reality to meet. Thus I have always felt that
brutal Imperialism and Tolstoian non–resistance were not only
not opposite, but were the same thing. They are the same contemptible
thought that conquest cannot be resisted, looked at from the two
standpoints of the conqueror and the conquered. Thus again
teetotalism and the really degraded gin–selling and
dram–drinking have exactly the same moral philosophy. They are
both based on the idea that fermented liquor is not a drink, but a
drug. But I am specially certain that the extreme of vegetarian
humanity is, as I have said, akin to the extreme of scientific
cruelty–they both permit a dubious speculation to interfere
with their ordinary charity. The sound moral rule in such matters as
vivisection always presents itself to me in this way. There is no
ethical necessity more essential and vital than this: that
casuistical exceptions, though admitted, should be admitted as
exceptions. And it follows from this, I think, that, though we may do
a horrid thing in a horrid situation, we must be quite certain that
we actually and already are in that situation. Thus, all sane
moralists admit that one may sometimes tell a lie; but no sane
moralist would approve of telling a little boy to practise telling
lies, in case he might one day have to tell a justifiable one. Thus,
morality has often justified shooting a robber or a burglar. But it
would not justify going into the village Sunday school and shooting
all the little boys who looked as if they might grow up into
burglars. The need may arise; but the need must have arisen. It seems
to me quite clear that if you step across this limit you step off a
precipice.
Now, whether torturing an animal is
or is not an immoral thing, it is, at least, a dreadful thing. It
belongs to the order of exceptional and even desperate acts. Except
for some extraordinary reason I would not grievously hurt an animal;
with an extraordinary reason I would grievously hurt him. If (for
example) a mad elephant were pursuing me and my family, and I could
only shoot him so that he would die in agony, he would have to die in
agony. But the elephant would be there. I would not do it to a
hypothetical elephant. Now, it always seems to me that this is the
weak point in the ordinary vivisectionist argument, “Suppose
your wife were dying.” Vivisection is not done by a man whose
wife is dying. If it were it might be lifted to the level of the
moment, as would be lying or stealing bread, or any other ugly
action. But this ugly action is done in cold blood, at leisure, by
men who are not sure that it will be of any use to anybody–men
of whom the most that can be said is that they may conceivably make
the beginnings of some discovery which may perhaps save the life of
some one else’s wife in some remote future. That is too cold
and distant to rob an act of its immediate horror. That is like
training the child to tell lies for the sake of some great dilemma
that may never come to him. You are doing a cruel thing, but not with
enough passion to make it a kindly one.
So much for why I am an
anti–vivisectionist; and I should like to say, in conclusion,
that all other anti–vivisectionists of my acquaintance weaken
their case infinitely by forming this attack on a scientific
speciality in which the human heart is commonly on their side, with
attacks upon universal human customs in which the human heart is not
at all on their side. I have heard humanitarians, for instance, speak
of vivisection and field sports as if they were the same kind of
thing. The difference seems to me simple and enormous. In sport a man
goes into a wood and mixes with the existing life of that wood;
becomes a destroyer only in the simple and healthy sense in which all
the creatures are destroyers; becomes for one moment to them what
they are to him–another animal. In vivisection a man takes a
simpler creature and subjects it to subtleties which no one but man
could inflict on him, and for which man is therefore gravely and
terribly responsible.
Meanwhile, it remains true that I
shall eat a great deal of turkey this Christmas; and it is not in the
least true (as the vegetarians say) that I shall do it because I do
not realise what I am doing, or because I do what I know is wrong, or
that I do it with shame or doubt or a fundamental unrest of
conscience. In one sense I know quite well what I am doing; in
another sense I know quite well that I know not what I do. Scrooge
and the Cratchits and I are, as I have said, all in one boat; the
turkey and I are, to say the most of it, ships that pass in the
night, and greet each other in passing. I wish him well; but it is
really practically impossible to discover whether I treat him well. I
can avoid, and I do avoid with horror, all special and artificial
tormenting of him, sticking pins in him for fun or sticking knives in
him for scientific investigation. But whether by feeding him slowly
and killing him quickly for the needs of my brethren, I have improved
in his own solemn eyes his own strange and separate destiny, whether
I have made him in the sight of God a slave or a martyr, or one whom
the gods love and who die young–that is far more removed from
my possibilities of knowledge than the most abstruse intricacies of
mysticism or theology. A turkey is more occult and awful than all the
angels and archangels In so far as God has partly revealed to us an
angelic world, he has partly told us what an angel means. But God has
never told us what a turkey means. And if you go and stare at a live
turkey for an hour or two, you will find by the end of it that the
enigma has rather increased than diminished.
ILLUSTRATIONS
Illustration
1
Illustration
2
Illustration
3
Illustration
4
Illustration
5
Illustration
6
Illustration
7
Illustration
8
Illustration
9
Illustration
10
TABLE OF CONTENTS
PUBLISHER II
www.eCatholic2000.com
|