|
TRANSLATOR'S INTRODUCTION.
|
THE following Treatise presents, at first sight, considerable difficulties.
They do not arise from any defect in the Saint's mode of expression, but are
inherent in his subject and manner of treatment, "going deep down into the
roots" of the Love of God. Thus he speaks in his Preface, and continues:
"The first four books, and some chapters of the others might doubtless have
been omitted without disadvantage to such souls as seek only the practice of
holy love. . . . I have been forced to say many things which will appear
more obscure than they are. The depths of science are always somewhat hard
to sound." But he tells us that the state of the minds of his age required
this deeper treatment; and whatever may be thought as to the best way of
presenting modern religious teaching to an age so ignorant, so shallow and
so unthinking as is our own with regard to spiritual truths, there can be no
question that this masterpiece of the chief doctor of ascetic theology must
not be brought down to our level, but that we must raise ourselves towards
it. The necessity of giving some explanation of the sequence of its
doctrine, and of the difficulties which occur, must be our chief excuse for
daring to place words of ours by the side of this finished work of S.
Francis de Sales.
A second reason lies in the fact that the "Treatise on the Love of God" was,
with others of his writings, the chief subject of the celebrated controversy
between Fénélon and Bossuet. There can be little doubt that this lowered the
authority of the work. Not because the mere fact of a discussion seemed to
throw over it an air of unsafeness or suspicion. Descriptions of the sublime
and mysterious operations of the soul under the influence of grace are
always capable of being misunderstood, and "wrested" from their proper
sense, and no Christian mystic, from S. Paul downwards, has escaped this
danger. The shameless abuse of the Saint's authority by the Jansenists left
it eventually quite unimpaired. Hence the mistakes of Molinos, Père Lacombe,
Madame Guyon, and even of Fénélon himself would have thrown no permanent
discredit on this treatise, if Bossuet had defended it in a proper spirit
and with full knowledge and discretion. Incredible as the fact may seem, it
is nevertheless true that neither Fénélon nor Bossuet had properly studied
the works in dispute. The former went to them prepossessed. His opinions
were already formed, and he merely sought a confirmation of them. He read in
a most superficial manner. He precipitately chose out what seemed to suit
his purpose, and neglected important statements and obvious interpretations
which were inconsistent with it. He even went so far in what must be called
a sincere dishonesty of misapprehension, as to insist on clinging to
mistakes he had fallen into through using Bailly's Lyons edition of the
"Conferences" (1628), which Bossuet had proved to be spurious. Bossuet, on
his side, admits that he had not previously read it properly, he only
studied what seemed necessary to answer his opponent, and lacked that high
complete knowledge of S. Francis's teaching as a whole which was necessary
for taking a proper view of details and parts. Indeed he only then (1695)
began those profounder studies of mystic theology which enabled him later to
write his treatises on matters which to S. Francis, by the experience of
sanctity more even than by the studies of a lifetime, were as familiar as
the sights and sounds of home. Hence it came about that while he easily
justified the teaching of the Saint, he not only failed to give the full
influence of his genius and authority to unassailably establish its
triumphant reputation, but on the contrary he incidentally disparaged it. He
says, for instance: "S. Francis is a great saint, and I have always
maintained that his doctrine which is objected against us is entirely for us
as to the matters in question: but we must not therefore make him
infallible, and it cannot be forgotten that he has shown more good intention
than knowledge on some points." Fortunately Bossuet mentions these points,
and the reader shall see directly Bossuet's entire misapprehension of the
Saint's meaning, and meanwhile "it cannot be forgotten" that while Bossuet
refused the title "infallible" to S. Francis, for whom no one claims it, he
refused it to the successor of S. Peter to whose office it really belongs.
Bossuet says further: "According to the spirit of his time he had perhaps
less read the Fathers than the modern Scholastics." Did Bossuet remember
that he was speaking of the age of Sirmond, of Bellarmine, of Venerable
Canisius, and, we may say, of Petavius? Francis was a master and a leader of
his age, and, as is clear from this Treatise alone, was excellently versed
both in the Fathers and the Scholastics, if any distinction is to be made
between them. In conclusion, Bossuet presumes to say: "In these places and
in some others his theology might be more exact and his principles more sure
. . . . one would not follow him in certain condescensions which I will not
particularize." In this also it will be shown that Bossuet is most unjust,
but for the present we may consider that he neutralizes his own objection,
when in the same sentence he says: "As director of souls he is truly
sublime." In answer to these attacks, Fénélon gladly changed places with
Bossuet, but his hasty defence was not so complete as the charges were
unwarranted and presumptuous. [1]
We shall briefly touch upon these controverted points as they occur among
the difficulties of the Treatise. Of these difficulties Book I. contains by
far the largest proportion, and we will give an abstract of this Book
sufficiently complete to prevent the necessity, not indeed of studying it,
but, of a too laborious study. [2]
In this first Book the Saint treats in general of the will and its
affections, in particular of its chief affection, love, and of the will's
natural inclination towards a sovereign love of God.
The first chapter is to show that the unity required for the beauty of that
assemblage of perfections called man, lies in this, that all his powers are
grouped round the will and subordinated to it. Then (c. 2) it is shown that
the will exercises its authority in different ways, according to the
different nature of human powers. It governs: (a) exterior movements, at its
pleasure, like slaves; (b) the senses and corporal functions, by a certain
management, like horses or hawks; (c) the fancy, memory, understanding, by
direction and command, like wife and children, who are able to disobey if
they choose; (d) the sensual appetite (c. 3), in the same manner as the
last-named; it is still less under the will's control, but there is no moral
guilt so long as the will refuses to consent to or adopt its wrong desires.
Then are described the twelve movements of this sensual appetite,—viz.,
desire, hatred, hope, &c., which are called perturbations or passions. They
are all forms of the chief, and, in a sense, the only passion, love. These
passions are left in man on purpose to exercise his will. A universal
experience, testified to in effect even by those who pretend to deny it,
such as the Stoics, proves that these movements are necessary qualities of
human nature. Love being (c. 4) the root of the others their action is good
or bad according as the love is rightly or wrongly placed. Nay the very will
is bad or good according to its love; and its supremacy does not lie in this
that it can reject all love, but in this that it can choose amongst the
loves presented to it, by directing the understanding to consider one more
favourably or more attentively than another. In the will, now defined (c. 5)
as "the reasonable appetite," there are affections, that is, movements or
forms of love, similar to the passions of the sensual appetite. Having
different and higher objects they often run counter to the passions, and the
reasonable will often forces a soul to remain in circumstances most
repugnant to its sensual inclinations. These affections or tendencies of the
will are divided into four classes according to their dignity, that is, the
dignity of their objects: 1°. Natural affections, where the word natural is
not used in opposition to supernatural (as in this sense the next class
would also be natural), but to signify those first and spontaneous
affections which by the very natural constitution of our reason arise from
the perception of sensible goods. Indeed the word sensible exactly explains
his use of the word natural, provided that we carefully remember that he is
speaking not of the movements of the merely sensual appetite or
concupiscence which are anterior to reason, but of our reasonable and lawful
affections for sensible goods. Such are the affections we have for health,
food, agreeable society. 2°. Reasonable affections, where it will now
easily be understood that the word, which could be applied also to the
preceding class, is restricted to those which are par excellence reasonable,
that is, the affections which arise in the spiritual part of reason, from
the light of nature indeed, but from the higher light of nature—such as the
affections for the moral virtues. 3°. Christian affections, which spring
from the consideration of truths of the Christian revelation, such as
affections for poverty, chastity, heavenly glory. 4°. Divine, or (entirely)
supernatural affections which God effects in us, and which tend to him as
known by a light entirely above that of nature. These supernatural
affections are primarily three: love for the beautiful in the mysteries of
faith, love for the useful in the promises of hope, and love for the
sovereign good which is the Divinity.
The essential supremacy of divine love is proved (c. 6), and there follows a
wondrous description in four chapters of the nature and qualities of love in
general. Divine love or charity is not defined till chapter 13, and is not
specifically described till the last chapter of Book II.
There are (c. 7) five points in the process of love: 1. Natural affinity of
the will with good. 2. Delectation or complacency in it. 3. A movement,
following this complacency, towards union. 4. Taking the means required for
union. 5. Union itself. [3] It is in 2 and 3, complacency and movement,
that love more properly consists, and most precisely in 3, the movement or
outflowing of heart. Complacency has appeared to some to be the really
essential point of love, but it is not so, because love is a true passion or
affection, that is, a movement. Complacency spreads the wings, love actually
flies. When the object loved is present and the lover has but to grasp it,
the love is called a love of complacency, because complacency has no sooner
produced the movement of love than it ends in a second complacency. When the
object is absent, or, like God, not as present as it may become, the
tending, advancing, aspiring movement is called a love of desire, that is,
the cupidity of what we have not but hope to have. After certain exquisite
distinctions between various kinds of desires, he returns (c. 8) to the
correspondence or affinity with good which is the root of love, and which
consists not exclusively in resemblance, but in a certain relation between
things which makes them apt to union for their mutual perfection. Finally,
coming to union and the means thereto, it is exquisitely proved (c. 9) that
love tends to union but (c. 10) to a spiritual union, and that carnal union,
instead of being an expression of true love or a help to it, is positively a
hindrance, a deviation, a degradation.
The next two chapters (11, 12) treat the important distinction between the
two parts of the soul, the inferior and the superior. It will clear matters
to notice that the Saint means the two parts of the reasonable soul, and
that in the first two paragraphs of chapter 11 he simply says that his
distinction does not refer to the soul as a mere animating principle, or,
again, as the principle of that life which man shares with plants and
animals. He speaks of the human soul as such, that is, as having the gift of
reason.
Even the inferior part of the soul truly reasons and wills (so that his
distinction of inferior and superior is not the distinction between
concupiscence and reason), but it is inferior because it only reasons and
wills according to data furnished by the senses: the superior part reasons
and wills on intellectual and spiritual considerations. But it must be
noticed that these considerations are not necessarily supernatural. The
distinction between the inferior and the superior part of the reasonable
soul is quite independent of revelation: it rests on the distinction between
what we have called the lower light of nature and that higher light which,
for instance, heathen philosophers used, when, for love of country or moral
virtue, they chose to submit to sensible pain or even to death which their
lower reason would direct them to avoid. The existence of this lower reason
is clearly shown in Our Blessed Saviour's prayer in the garden. Willing and
praying are acts of reason, yet in this case they were acts of a lower
reason which Christ permitted to manifest itself, but which had to give way
to higher considerations.
Now the inferior part of reason forms by itself one degree of the reason,
but the superior part has three degrees; in the lowest of which we reason
according to higher natural light, or as the Saint calls it, "human
sciences," in the next according to faith, and in the highest we do not
properly reason, but, "by a simple view of the understanding, and simple
acquiescence," or assent, "of the will" we correspond with God's action,
when he spreads faith, hope and charity in this supreme point of our
reasonable soul. The distinction corresponds exactly with that made in
chapter 5, into natural, reasonable, Christian and divine. The Saint there
spoke of affections or tendencies, he here speaks of reasonings and willings
which are the fulfilment of those tendencies. We may remark here, as an
instance of the superficial way in which Fénélon and Bossuet studied this
Treatise, that they take a totally different ground of distinction in
separating the soul into superior and inferior (viz., sensible perception
and intellectual cognition), and yet do not perceive that they are differing
from the Saint. [4] To sum up (cc. 11, 12): in man there are some powers
altogether below reason; and reason, which is of course one and simple in
itself, has four degrees, according to the rank of the objects presented for
its consideration and love,—sensible things, spiritual things known by the
light of nature, spiritual things known by the revelation of Christ, and
spiritual knowledge communicated by the immediate communication of God's
light. Between the last and the last but one there is not exactly a
difference of rank in the objects, but a difference in clearness of
perception and strength of acceptance.
Having finished this subject, which is to some extent a digression, the
Saint returns to the consideration of love, and gives (c. 13) its two main
divisions,—viz., love of cupidity when we love good for our own sake, and
love of benevolence when we love good for its sake—i.e. love of
self-interest and disinterested love. He has already, in chapter 7,
sub-divided the love of cupidity into love of benevolence and love of
desire, according as the loved good is present or absent, and now he applies
the same division and the same ground of division to the love of
benevolence. This also is either a love of complacency or a love of desire
according as the good is present to or absent from the person we love: we
rejoice in the good he already has, we desire him the good he has not. This
double form of the love of benevolence, besides occurring frequently
throughout, enters particularly into the structure of Book V., and is
importantly needed for the full understanding of Book VIII. It is necessary
here to point out that whereas he has just placed the names complacency and
desire under the generic head, benevolence, he afterwards uses the word
benevolence, specifically, instead of desire, as if dividing benevolence
into complacency, and benevolence proper. This use of the word in the sense
of desire agrees with its etymology,—bene-volentia, bien-veuillance,
well-wishing.
Cupidity alone is exercised in the inferior reason, but in the superior
reason both find place. The love of God for his own sake which is necessary
for eternal life belongs exclusively to the supreme degree of the superior
reason, but the Saint teaches (as Bossuet has clearly shown against Fénélon)
that there is a reasonable, high love of cupidity, that is, a love of God as
good to us, even in the highest degree and supreme point of the spirit. This
indeed is the precise motive of Christian hope, which must be kept
subordinate to disinterested love, but can only be separated from it by
abstraction and by a non-permanent act.
The love of benevolence is called friendship when it is mutual. This
friendship has degrees. When it is beyond all comparison with other
friendships, supereminent, sovereign, it is called charity—the friendship or
mutual love of God and man.
The Saint shows (c. 14.) that to employ the word love instead of charity is
not against the use of Scripture, and he mentions one reason for his
preferring the word love which gives us an important help to the
understanding of the Treatise. It is, he says, because he is speaking for
the most part not of the habitual charity, or state of friendship between
God and the soul in grace, but of actual charity, that is, of the acts of
love which at once express and increase the state of charity. Even in the
three following books, in which he is speaking of the formation, or
progress, or loss, of habitual charity, he is still chiefly concerned with
the acts by which this is done.
In the remaining four chapters preparation is made for the account of the
communication of grace and charity to the soul. He shows (c. 15) that there
is a natural affinity of the soul with its God which is the root of love;
that thus, by a glorious paradox, God and man need one another for their
mutual perfection; that we have (c. 16) a natural inclination to love God
above all things; that (c. 17) we cannot fulfil this inclination by natural
powers; but (c. 18) that still the inclination is not left in our hearts for
nothing, as it makes possible the communication of grace, and is the handle
by which grace takes hold of us.
It is chiefly against these three chapters that Bossuet's animadversions are
directed. He accuses the Saint of two errors: 1°. in saying (p. 61) that
God would give grace to one who did his best by the forces of nature as
certainly as he would give a further grace to one who corresponded with a
first grace; 2°. of saying (p. 57) that in the state of original justice
our love of God would not be supernatural.
Fénélon misapprehends the Saint's meaning, and gives a very confused,
imperfect answer to the two objections. The real answer to the first is that
Bossuet is quite outside the question. S. Francis is not speaking of the
step by which a man passes from the natural to the supernatural order, but
of the process by which his natural inclination to love God above all things
ripens into that actual love of him above all things which belongs still to
the natural order. [5]
Bossuet falls into a somewhat similar error in his second objection. S.
Francis is considering, separately, the natural love of God which those
would have who might be in the state of original justice, who would, of
course, by the very terms, have supernatural love. Not only is Bossuet's
criticism ridiculously irrelevant, but his language, to ears which have
heard the Saint declared "Doctor of the Church," sounds almost like
impertinence. "What," he says, "would this humble servant of God have done
if it had been represented to him that in the state of original justice we
should have loved God supernaturally? Would he not have confessed that he
was forgetting the most essential condition of that state?" And it is after
these mistakes that Bossuet complacently observes: "These opinions rectify
themselves in practice when the intention is good;" and "In some points his
theology might be more exact and his principles more sure."
Book II. describes the generation of charity, which, being supernatural,
must be created in the soul as a new quality. And after two introductory
chapters, the remaining twenty are evenly divided between the history of the
action of God in bestowing, and the action of man in appropriating this
gift. The two introductory chapters, which seem at first sight somewhat
foreign to the subject of the book, are directed to put steadily and
unmistakeably before us the truth that when theologians speak of many
perfections, many acts, a most various order of decrees and execution, this
is only according to the human method of viewing, and that our God is really
but one perfection and one act, which is himself. This truth is developed
partly also to introduce a description of the perfections of the God of
whose love the Saint is speaking. At the end of the Treatise he refers to
these chapters as his chief treatment of the chief motive of love—the
infinite goodness of God in himself.
After this caution and preface, he begins (c. 3) his account of the action
of God in the production of charity. He speaks, first, of God's providence
in general, including under this title his actual providing or foreseeing,
his creating, and his governance. Then (c. 4) he comes to the divine decree
to create Christ's Humanity, angels and men for him, inferior creatures for
men—following here the Scotist teaching that Christ would have become man
(though of course he would not have died) even if Adam had not sinned. God
decreed to create angels and man in the supernatural state of charity, and,
foreseeing that some angels and the whole nature or race of man would fall
from this state, God decreed to condemn the former, but to redeem the latter
by his Son's death, making the state of redemption a hundred times better
than the state of innocence. God decreed (c. 6) special favours, such as the
Immaculate Conception of Mary, for certain rare creatures who were to come
nearest to his Son, and then for men in general an immense abundance and
universal showers of grace, an all-illuminating light. He gives a whole
exquisite chapter (c. 8) to show the sincerity and strength of the desire
God thus manifests that we should love him, and then comes (c. 9) to the
effecting this desire by preventing our hearts with his grace, taking hold
of our natural inclination to love him. We can (c. 10) repulse his grace,
not because (c. 11) there is anything wanting in God's offer, but (c. 12) as
an inevitable consequence of our having free-will; in case we accept it, we
begin to mingle our action with God's. Here we must remark that the Saint is
not concerned with the sacramental action of God which creates or re-creates
charity in the soul by baptism or penance, still less does he treat the
semi-miraculous production of charity by Baptism in souls which have not yet
the use of reason, but he speaks of the intellectual and moral process or
set of acts by which a soul gifted with the use of reason is conducted from
infidelity to faith and charity, he treats of the justification which is
made by love even before the actual reception of a Sacrament.
Our first act under divine inspiration is (c. 13) the consenting to those
first stirrings of love which God causes in the soul even before it has
faith. Then (c. 14) comes the production of faith. This may follow after
argument and the acceptance of the fact of miracles, but it is not precisely
an effect of these. Such things make truths of faith extremely credible, but
God alone makes them actually believed. And the effect is from God not only
in this sense that the extremest effort of natural intelligence could not
attain to faith, but also because a moving of the will is required and is
contained in the intellectual act of faith itself, what the Saint calls an
affectionate sentiment of complacency in the beauty and sweetness of the
truth accepted, so that faith is an acquiescence, an assent, an assurance.
The Jews saw the force of the argument from Christ's miracles, but they did
not assent to the conclusion because they loved it not. Hence faith includes
a certain commencement of love in the will, but a love not as yet enough for
eternal life.
Then (cc. 15, 16, 17) comes the production of hope, which brings yet closer
to charity. As soon as faith shows the divine object of man's affections,
there arises a movement of complacency and desiring love. This desire would
be a torment to us unless we had an assurance that we might obtain its
object. God gives this assurance by his promise, and this promise, while it
makes desire stronger, causes at the same time a sense of calm which the
Saint calls the "root" of hope. From it spring two movements or acts of the
soul, the one by which she expects from God the promised happiness, and this
is really the chief element of hope—esperer, the other by which she excites
herself to do all that is required on her part—aspirer. This aspiration is
the condition but not the positive ground of our esperation (to coin a
word). That is to say, we may not expect the fruition of God except in so
far as we have a courageous design to do all we can; then, we may infalliby
expect it, yet still ever from the pure mercy of God. Hope, then, is defined
"an expecting and aspiring love," or "the loving complacency we take in the
expecting and seeking our soverign good." It is then a distinct advance in
love. Faith includes a beginning of love in the movement of the will though
its real seat is the intelligence; hope is all love, and its seat is the
will. However hope as such is still insufficient, because, however noble, it
is a love of cupidity, and not that love of God for his own sake which is
necessary for eternal life. By it we love God sovereignly, because we desire
him above all other goods, yet our love is not sovereign, because it is not
the highest kind of love. The Saint is of course speaking of the action of
hope before charity. Hope remains also after charity, existing, as we have
said, in the very heights of perfect love, and after charity its acts merit
before those of every other virtue.
Then comes the production of penitence or repentance. He distinguishes (c.
18) first, a merely human repentance; secondly, a religious repentance
belonging to the merely natural order; thirdly, a supernatural inferior
repentance, which (c. 19) is good but insufficient; and fourthly (c. 20),
perfect repentance, that is, sorrow for sin arising from the loving
consideration of the sovereignly amiable goodness which has been offended
thereby. This is not precisely charity, because charity is, precisely, a
movement towards union, whereas repentance is, precisely, a movement of
separation (from sin); but though it is not precisely charity and therefore
has not the sweetness of charity, it has the virtue and uniting property of
charity, because the object of its movement of separation from sin is union
with God. In practice there is no means, or need, to distinguish, because
perfect repentance is always immediately followed or preceded by charity, or
else the one is born within the other.
The Saint then reminds us (c. 21) that all this has been done by the loving
action of God's grace, which, after awakening our souls and inspiring them
to pray has brought them through faith and hope to penitence and perfect
love. In conclusion (c. 22) he describes charity.
Book III. treats of the progress and perseverance of the soul in charity on
earth, and of the perfection of triumphant charity in heaven. We have only
one remark to make on this book. The Abbé Baudry expresses surprise that the
Saint when speaking (c. 2) of the increase of charity by good works does not
mention its increase by the Sacraments. But he includes them under the name
good-works, and in Book IV., c. 4, where he sums up this part of Book III.
mentions them explicitly. He does not dwell on them because his object in
chapter 2 is to show how easy God has made the increase of charity. He takes
therefore as his examples the smallest works, such as the giving a cup of
cold water, and he leaves us to draw the conclusion that the faithful and
loving reception of God's Sacraments would â fortiori increase love. Still
it is true that neither here nor elsewhere does he treat the Sacraments
except quite incidentally, and the explanation of this fact gives us a
further insight into the true character and object of the Treatise. He is
concerned with the action of grace in general, not with its action by
particular means; he is more concerned with the interior movements of man
under grace than with the effects worked on him, as it were from outside;
and, as he is treating of actual charity, he is more concerned with the good
acts for which God gives (whether by Sacraments or in any other way) an
increase of grace, than he is concerned with the actual reception of the
grace. We mention this to show that one must not be surprised at not finding
a fuller treatment of, for instance, the Blessed Eucharist. We must also
remember that this Treatise supposes the "Introduction to a Devout Life" as
a foundation. And though he only introduces the Sacraments incidentally, he
does not fail to speak of them frequently, and with such magnificent praises
as we should expect from the Saint of love. As when he says (ii. 22) that
the communication of Christ's body and blood is the very consummation of the
charity he is writing of, and the crown of God's love-dealings with us; or
as when he says, speaking of the return of the penitent soul to reunite
herself, immediately, with her God: "Go and cry God's mercy in the very ear
of your confessor" (ix. 7).
Book IV. describes the relations of love and sin. The following five Books
treat of the exercise of benevolence in its generic sense—the sovereign love
of God for his own sake.
Book V. treats in general of the double action or manifestation of this
love,—in complacency, and in benevolence in its specific sense, that is,
desire.
Books VI. and VII. treat of union with God by affection, that is, by prayer;
the former treating of meditation, and of contemplation as far as union, the
latter of union itself. The various degrees of the prayer of quiet are
treated in these books, and Quietists bring forward passages from them, as
from other parts of the Saint's works, in support of their extravagant
system of annihilation of the powers and of purely passive prayer. We have
said elsewhere [6] as much as we think it necessary to say to overthrow
these allegations. But it is important to show that Fénélon was utterly
wrong in appealing to the Saint's authority in support of his erroneous
doctrine on this point in his "Maximes des Saints." Bossuet has exposed
these errors and given a full explanation of the passages cited from S.
Francis; particularly in the 8th and 9th Books of his "Instruction pastorale
sur les états d’oraison." The Saint expresses in this as in all things the
very teaching of the Church. He rightly teaches that there is, even short of
suspension and ecstasy, a kind of prayer in which God takes into his own
hands the powers of the soul, and produces in it acts far above the ordinary
operations of faith, hope and charity. When God lifts a soul to this prayer,
and also to some extent in preparation and expectancy of this elevation, the
will acts, by a placing of itself (remise) in the hands of God, and even
continues to act, though insensibly: hence the soul is not purely passive,
but the action of God is so mighty, and so far beyond all proportion to that
of the will, that S. Francis says this is "as it were passive." And as the
soul must offer itself to be lifted, and must co-operate with God, therefore
also must it help to acquire and preserve that "quiet" which is the
condition of God's operation: it must abstain from intrusive acts of
reasoning and from other acts of the will, especially from violent ones. But
this prayer, however frequent, long, uninterrupted, absorbing, it may
become, is of itself a non-permanent state, and not of the nature of a
habit, but is always an act of charity. And far from saying that for
perfection it is necessary to be raised to and to keep oneself in this
state, the Saint teaches in a hundred places that the soul, however perfect,
must exercise itself in all ordinary acts of prayer, faith, hope, petition,
which are only put on one side for the time in which God has raised it. The
practice of S. Jane Frances, whose authority was invoked even more
speciously than that of her saintly director by the advocates of passive
prayer, bears on this. We are told that: "She wrote out and signed with her
blood a long prayer which she had composed of petitions, praises,
thanksgivings, for general and particular favours, for relations and
friends, for the living and the dead, in fine for all intentions to which
she considered herself obliged, with the Credo of the Missal, also signed
with her blood. She carried this in a little bag night and day round her
neck, and she had made a loving covenant with Our Lord that whenever she
pressed this to her heart she should be taken to have made all the acts of
faith, the thanks and the petitions she had written." [7] And, at last,
prayer is not a character of perfection, but a means to it, and the two
following statements of S. Francis in his second Conference absolutely
settle the whole question as to his teaching. "It happens often enough that
Our Lord gives these quietudes and tranquillities to souls that are far from
perfection." . . . . and on the other hand: "There are persons who are very
perfect to whom Our Lord has never given such sweetnesses nor such
quietudes; who do all with the superior part of the soul, and make their
will die in the will of God by main force, and with the supreme point of the
reason; and this death is the death of the cross, much more excellent than
that other, which should rather be called a slumber than a death."
As in treating affective love Book VII. completes Book VI., so in treating
effective love Book VIII., which treats of obedience to the already
signified will of God, is completed by Book IX., which treats of
indifference, or the state of perfect readiness to accept all that God's
good-pleasure may choose to send us.
On the doctrine of indifference we venture again to refer the reader to our
Essay [8] just quoted. We add a few words to show how completely Fénélon
erred in appealing to this Treatise to support his extravagant and condemned
propositions that indifference extends to eternal salvation as our
salvation, and to virtuousness as such. The Saint expressly teaches that
while God's glory must be our principal end, we may, indeed we must—our
nature so requires—desire salvation and virtue as good also in themselves.
Much less can we acquiesce in a supposed decree of damnation, with that
species of absolute act which Fénélon requires as the last test of the
disinterestedness of love. [9] With regard to eternal salvation, we have
only to study the sentiments the Saint places in the hearts and mouths of
those whose love is refined to its highest point at the moment of death (v.
10, vii. 11, 12). He has a chapter to prove that the preceding desire of
heaven increases the enjoyment of it (iii. 10); and he teaches that not only
mercenary hope but also servile fear remain in the soul as part of its habit
of charity so long as it is in this life (xi. 17). With regard to virtues he
says (xi. 13): "Let us love the particular virtues, but principally because
they are agreeable to God;" and: "We must make this heavenly good-pleasure
the soul of our actions, loving the goodness and beauty of virtue
principally because it is agreeable to God." Here the word "principally" is
the key of the whole question.
Bossuet triumphantly vindicates [10] the Saint's doctrine on indifference,
but has a very ill-judged criticism on his use of the word. He is quite
right in saying that indifference is only a degree of resignation, but he
forgets how far ordinary resignation is below indifference. Bossuet gives a
full explanation of all the passages alleged by Fénélon from S. Francis, but
he was hampered, as Fénélon was totally misled, by Maupas's erroneous
account of S. Francis's famous temptation to despair.
Of the remaining three books, Book X. is dedicated entirely to the
commandment of loving God above all things; Books XI. arid XII. are on the
theory and practice of the particular virtues. Indeed it must be remembered
that the object of the Treatise, even in its speculative parts, is
exclusively practical. And as we have shown that in its theory it is free
from error, so we may now be allowed to indicate some of its glorious
truths, particularly with regard to the practice of holy living.
It is not a book, like other spiritual books, treating only a section or a
single element of the devout life, but it is one by which and on which the
whole spiritual life can be formed; it is, with the "Introduction to a
Devout Life," a perfect book, a "complete food," containing all the
ingredients necessary for spiritual sustenance.
It contains in the first place an immense mass of instruction, dogmatic and
moral, on the science of the love of God. It treats not only in broad
outline but also in subtle detail of God and the soul, this world and the
world to come, grace and free-will, holiness and sin, commandments and
counsels, ordinary virtue and perfection, all questions of prayer; it treats
the virtues in detail, not only the virtue of charity in all its parts, but
also faith, hope and fear, zeal, obedience, resignation. The direct course
of the Treatise takes us through all these, and they are not only treated
fully in themselves, but so treated as to bring out in illustrating them a
hundred related truths. A whole theology of Mary might be gathered as we
pass along; her Immaculate Conception (ii. 3), her graces and privileges
(iii. 8.; ix. 14.; vii. 13, 14), her praise of God (v. 11), her heavenly
death (vii. 13, 14). A new light is thrown on the sense of Holy Scripture,
and on the principles and actions of the Saints.
But, in the second place, we more particularly wish to point out some of his
practical principles and rules, the manner of loving and serving God. The
most important of these is what may be called the Saint's general idea or
philosophy of life. It begins thus: "We know by faith that the divinity is
an incomprehensible abyss of all perfection. . . . . And this truth which
faith teaches we consider attentively by meditation, regarding this
immensity of goods which are in God. . . . . Now when we have made our
understanding very attentive to the greatness of the goods which are in this
divine object, it is impossible that our will should not be touched with
complacency in this good . . . . and especially when we see amidst his
perfections that of his infinite love excellently shining" (v. 1, 2.). The
loving soul does not stay in complacency but goes on to benevolence, wishing
her God all possible goods; but as she is at the very same time exulting in
the thought that nothing is wanting to him, she can at first but spend
herself in desiring him what he already has, in desiring to be able to give
him something, and in praises, ever rising higher and higher until at last
she finds a sort of rest in the sense that her utter inability to desire him
anything which he has not, or to praise him fully, is the best proof of the
infinity of the goods he has. This delight in God and these loving desires
are an important part of her service, but they would be barren if she did
not go further. She turns, then, to her own powers, and finds that
exercising them in herself by internal acts of prayer (affective love), and
outside herself, amid creatures, by external acts of the virtues (effective
love), she can increase the glory of her beloved, not in itself, but in and
by herself. Thus the various interior and exterior acts are brought into
one, and the soul's life consists, on the one hand, in "a continual progress
in the sweet searching out of motives which may continually urge her" (v.
7), and, on the other hand, in acts of prayer, in obedience, and in
submission. She "employs every occasion," "does everything most perfectly,"
and, by the practice of Intention, Offering, and Ejaculatory Prayer
(according to methods minutely described in Book XI. 13, 14, 20, and
throughout Book XII.), subordinates and ranges every interior movement and
every exterior action to the service of divine love.
This "view" of life, this continual gazing at the beloved Master for whom we
work, this regarding the acts of life as a mere series of acts or offerings
of love, is the very central point of the ascetic teaching of S. Francis. It
not only gives the nobleness, the intensity, the meritoriousness of charity
to every act, but it gives also at the same time a great simplicity and
largeness, preserving the soul from formality and from getting lost or
wearied in the multitudinous details and minute practices of the spiritual
life; it creates a loving detachment and liberty of spirit, with a readiness
to follow every slightest indication of God's will. Finally, it gives order
to our various duties. For instance, it puts in their proper place, in
serene majesty above the cavils of worldlings, the works of religion and
"piety." These are the immediate services of the beloved, the first effects
of charity, and therefore charity itself teaches that: "Amongst all virtuous
actions we should carefully practise those of religion and reverence to
divine things, those of faith, hope and the most holy fear of God;—often
talking of heavenly things, thinking of and aspiring after eternity,
frequenting churches and holy services, reading spiritual books, observing
the ceremonies of the Christian religion; for holy love feeds at will amid
these exercises, and spreads its graces and properties more abundantly over
them than over the simply human virtues" (xi. 3). Yet there is no
fanaticism. The human virtues find their proper place at the proper time,
and, inferior in themselves, are raised by love, that is, by the fact that
for the time they are the will of God, to the highest rank in the eyes of
the loving soul,—"For in little and low exercises, charity is practised not
only more frequently, but also as a rule more humbly, and therefore more
profitably and more holily" (xii. 6). He has two glorious chapters on the
truth that legitimate occupations, be they even in court or camp, hinder not
the practice of divine love. "Curiosity, ambition, disquiet, together with
inadvertence to, or not considering, the end for which we are in this world,
are the causes why we have a hundred times more hindrances than affairs; and
it is these embarrassments, that is, the silly, vain, superfluous
undertakings with which we charge ourselves that turn us from the love of
God, and not the true and lawful exercise of our vocations" (xii. 4.). In
the one great principle of doing all for love we have signalized two
conditions or negative aspects of the same. 1°. The intellect must be kept
"very attentive." As the Saint says in the "Introduction to a Devout Life"
(v. 17), so here, consideration "is supposed throughout the entire work,"
the whole edifice is built on it, and therefore the want of it,
"inconsidération," is the ruin of the whole spiritual life (xi. 7.) This
"consideration" need not be called by the alarming name of mental prayer,
but whatever it is called it consists in a most serious attention to
spiritual truths according to the capacity of the individual: there must be
one great esteem, and therefore the energy of the intellect cannot be given
primarily to anything else. So (2°) in the will, there must be but one great
affection, one aim, one desire—"One to one." "The desire of exalting God
separates from inferior pleasures" (v. 7); and: "to have the desire of
sacred love we must cut off other desires" (xii. 3). "Those souls who ever
abound in desires, designs and projects never desire holy celestial love as
they ought:" "He who aspires to heavenly love must carefully reserve for it
his leisure, his spirit, and his affections:"—words which should be written
in letters of flame for the guidance of such as seek the right way to
perfection.
We will not stay to give examples of his more particular principles with
regard to prayer, but we select a few with regard to the virtues. The truly
loving heart not only observes the commandments, but loves the observance,
of them (viii. 5). "Inclination is neither vice nor virtue. . . . . How many
by natural disposition are sober, simple, silent, even chaste? All this
seems to be virtue, but it is not, until on such natural humours we have
grafted free and voluntary consent:" The whole chapter "On the imperfection
of the virtues of the pagans" (xi. 7.) is of the most practical importance
at the present day. The general, but surely most constraining, principle of
mortification,—that other pleasures and other desires must be put down for
the sake of divine love,—is applied to the interior in such more particular
methods as this:—irregular affections can be put down either on the
principle of curing contraries by contraries, or on the principle of curing
likes by likes: the inclination to trust in earthly things may be overcome
either by thinking of the vanity of earthly hopes or of the solidity of
heavenly hopes; desire of riches or of sensual pleasure may be kept down
either by the contempt of them or by the esteem of heavenly goods, "as fire
is extinguished either by water or by lightning" (xi. 20). It is applied to
the exterior thus: "It is useless to give orders of abstinence to the
palate, but the hands must be ordered to furnish the mouth with meat and
drink only in such and such a measure. . . . . If we desire our eyes not to
see we must turn them away, or (he has just compared our sensual appetite to
a hawk) cover them with their natural hood . . . . it would be folly to
command a horse not to wax fat, not to grow, not to kick,—to effect all
this, stop his corn" (i. 2). In this connection, and to show how beautiful,
how consistent, and how feasible his teaching is, it should be studied with
his life, as his life should be explained by his teaching. That his
extraordinary and almost unreasonable meekness sprang from no weakness or
ignorance, but was founded on the deepest wisdom and sincere humility, we
realize when we study his teaching (x.) on zeal and anger. His extremely
affectionate expressions towards his friends find their justification in the
truth that "the union to which love aspires is spiritual" (i. 10). The
ground of his missionary spirit and life is found in v. 9, and the whole
work is the explanation of his absolute devotion of himself to the loving
service of God and his neighbour.
In the third place, the Treatise contains a full exposition of the motives
for serving God, the why of a spiritual life. This is all reduced to the one
great motive of the infinite perfections—especially the amiableness, the
love, the goodness of God—brought before us in a hundred ways. His mere
descriptions are enough to bring home this motive to the heart that reads
them with attention, but the Saint himself puts them together (xii., 11, 12)
with the exact method of applying them. But besides the direct treatment of
the motives, the Treatise is pervaded by a heavenly persuasive unction,
which ever urges them. This is why S. Vincent calls it "the goad of the
slothful and the stimulus of love." While S. Francis seems only to be making
us clearly understand what virtue is, he at the same time makes us esteem
and love it; his reasons for loving God and practising virtue are not cold,
dry logic, but reach the heart, and command assent; and while he is
apparently only fixing our attention on the way to practise virtue he is at
the same time gently but effectively touching the springs of the will to
make us love and prepare to effect it. But besides this continual
stimulation he has direct exhortations; he stops, as it were, in his course
to preach. One chapter is headed: "An exhortation to the amorous submission
which we owe to the decrees of divine Providence" (iv. 8). Another is his
exposition of S. Paul's,—"The charity of Christ presseth us." Another—"An
exhortation to the sacrifice we ought to make to God of our free-will" (xii.
10). And other chapters, though not precisely in the form of exhortations,
contain the virtue of them. Such are the chapters "On condolence and
complacency in the Passion of Our Lord" (v. 5); on the "Marvellous history
of a gentleman who died of love on Mount Olivet" (vii. 12); and the last
chapter of all: "That Mount Calvary is the true academy of love."
But, in the fourth place, this Treatise is not only a manual and a guide to
perfection, but it is also a meditation-book, and a prayer-book. In such
chapters as those just mentioned the devout soul will find all the materials
of most excellent meditations;—not only deep pregnant thoughts, but also a
very fountain of affections and ejaculations, most pressing movements of the
will, and most effective resolutions. The summing up of motives, and method
of using them is already in the very form of meditation. But almost every
chapter could be used as such. For instance, if one wished to strengthen the
groundwork of love—the realization of the perfections of God—after thinking
out Book v. cc. 1. 2., he could add Book i. cc. 15, 18, Book ii. cc. 1, 2,
8, 15, 22, and Book iii. cc. 11, 12, 13. This Book III. furnishes grand
meditations on heaven, and every Book is full of the excellences of charity,
than which no consideration could be more touching or more practical.
Then, the Treatise is a prayer-book. Very frequently the Saint ends his
chapter with an exquisite prayer, himself giving the expression of the
ardours with which he has filled our hearts. All Book V. is a prayer;—for
instance, c. 5 on the Passion, c. 6 on Desires. Profound dogma, having
permeated the intellect, exhales itself, as it were, to God on the apex of
the spirit in such burning words as his—"Ah! then I am not made for this
world, &c." (i. 15), or—"Ah! Jesus, who will give me grace to be one single
spirit with thee, &c!" (vii. 3.)
We have now to speak of our text and rendering. We have followed the text of
Vivès's edition of the "Œuvres Complètes," which, with a little improvement
from subsequent editions, is a reproduction of the original work, published
at Lyons by Rigaud in 1616. We therefore follow in our quotations the
spelling and accentuation of the old French. We have of course used the
ordinary Catholic translation of the Bible, except where the Saint leaves
the Vulgate for the Septuagint or the Hebrew, which he occasionally does,
not, as he says, to get the true sense, but "to explain and confirm the true
sense." We have consulted the originals for the citations from the Fathers,
but the Saint himself quotes them with a certain freedom, and we have not
thought it necessary to give the exact references, as the student can easily
find them in Vivès or Migne. It has been decided to omit or modify in this
popular edition a few sentences in which the Saint refers to certain
delicate matters—in particular to certain Bible narratives which to his
original readers were matters of familiar knowledge—with the happy
simplicity of his day. As he says in his Preface, "it is of extreme
importance to remember the age in which one writes," and there can be no
doubt that if he had been writing for this age he would have consulted its
requirements, and would have conformed to the universal practice of modern
spiritual writers by forbearing reference to these subjects. He only
introduces them incidentally and merely for the purpose of illustrating his
main argument. The omissions or alterations taken altogether would not
amount to more than two pages. [11]
We are acquainted with only two English versions of the Treatise. The first
was made by Father Car, from the eighteenth French edition, [12] and we had
at first intended to take this as the basis of ours; but when we came to
actually test it by the original, we determined to make our translation
completely independent of it, and in many parts we did not refer to it at
all. As to the substance of the work it is satisfactory; though there are
many slight omissions, and a few somewhat serious mistakes. As to style,
taken by itself, it is a good and a very interesting specimen of the racy,
vigorous English of that day; but taken as a translation, the rendering is
unwarrantably free, and Father Car's manner is far too rugged to represent
that of the Saint, which is always graceful and flowing, even when the
thought is closest and the passion strongest. Father Car gives the structure
correctly, but his manipulation of conjunctions and adverbs, particularly in
the more argumentative parts, is painfully cumbrous. We should expect his
diction to be archaic, but some of his words are quite obsolete [13] . He is
occasionally mistaken in his use of words, as when he translates bonté,
"bounty," instead of "goodness;" he makes curious mistakes in words which
are spelt nearly alike. [14] We have laboured to preserve his delightful air
of antiqueness, which is singularly appropriate to the Saint's work.
The modern English translation, which was made, we believe, early in the
present century by an Irish lady, and which has been reprinted by various
publishers, is not worth criticizing. It is not so much a translation as a
very bad adaptation. A good deal of the substance of the book is left out,
and the translator, who was not properly acquainted either with the Saint's
language or her own, substitutes her style for his. We have no hesitation in
saying that there is not a page without important errors on commission or
omission.
We may add a few words on our own work. It is sometimes said that a
translation should read as if it were composed in the language in which it
appears, and, again, that a translator must not attend immediately to the
words of his text, but must, in the first place, aim at producing the same
impression on the minds of his readers as the author would produce on the
minds of those for whom he originally wrote. We cannot but consider both
these rules or principles to be fallacious. A Frenchman, for instance, is
different from an Englishman, and there are many words which necessarily
make a very different impression, according as they fall on a French or on
an English mind. So, again, the French tongue has national peculiarities and
differences which an English translator may not ignore, but which he cannot
represent in strict accordance with the genius of his own tongue. S.
Francis's work would have been totally different, both in itself and in its
effect, if he had been an Englishman writing for his countrymen in their
native language. The most that a translator can do is to put the foreign
reader in as good a position as he would be in if he had a familiar
knowledge of the original. When an Englishman having a familiar knowledge of
French reads a book written in that language, he does not indeed usually
advert to the expression therein of the national characteristics—vivacity,
use of gesture, frequent expression of emotion, strong sense of
personality—because he has for the time put on his French form of mind, but
there is certainly a latent sense of foreignness, of which he becomes
conscious when these peculiarities are exaggerated, as in such a writer as
Victor Hugo.
We say this in explanation of the general structure of the work, which could
not be altered without being revolutionized, but as regards particular words
and phrases, we have tried our best to spare our readers the disagreeable
jar which is caused by the introduction of a foreign idiom. In this matter
the Treatise presents less difficulty than is found in the more colloquial
writings, because its argument is very substantial, and its text largely
consists of quotations from the Holy Scriptures, the Fathers, and
philosophers. The difficulty lies deeper, and one must be extremely careful,
in obliterating Gallicisms, not to injure or destroy what belongs to the
very texture of the style. S. Francis's work cannot be made to read as
easily as do the empty, superficial writings of the day, or to appear in a
spick-and-span modern English dress. He is a classic, he is a master of
thought, having his individual characteristics, who wrote scientifically on
profoundest religious truths three ages back.
His style is old-world, antique. Words with him have more of their fresh
native simplicity than they now retain after having done service for three
hundred years. Some of them he was the first to bring out of their classic
use into modern circulation. Hence, we make no difficulty in using such
words as "contemplation," "sensible," "civil," in their original and more
proper sense, as English religious writers of his age—Hooker, Taylor or
Milton—used them.
Again, he is scientific—theological and philosophical. He writes a Treatise.
The world, which is only interested in its own matters, will not admit the
rights of the scientific writer on religion. Catholics of the
English-speaking race are placed at a double disadvantage, on account of the
small proportion their numbers bear to the mass of their countrymen. But
surely we are not to acquiesce in allowing terms to be prohibited which are
necessary or useful for properly and safely expressing the distinctive
truths of our religion: there is an interest at stake not merely literary,
but religious, and also patriotic. We claim, therefore, the right to use,
for instance, the words "religion," "religious," "professed," in our
technical Catholic sense, for the state and the persons of those who have
bound themselves to the service of God by vow.
S. Francis also had his special characteristics, which, therefore, are not
French but Salesian. He was slightly old-fashioned, even in his own time. He
was a patriarch of French literature, and devoted, in language as in other
things, to the old times, though so glorious a pioneer of the new. He is
simple in expression amongst the simple. But each word is charged with
thought and reflection, and sometimes an exclamation which one might at
first be tempted to suppress as a French superfluity, turns out to be a
"word," and welded into the substance of the phrase. He was a Saint, also,
and what would be an exclamation in others is an ejaculation in him.
But, after all, our object is devotional and not literary; we are far from
wishing to indulge any literary fancies or crotchets and have no intention
of straining our principles of translation. Our one aim is to make the true
teachings of S. Francis de Sales accessible, profitable, and attractive to
English readers, and so to contribute our poor efforts to advance the divine
Art of Holy Loving.
Weobley,
Feast of our most holy Father S. Benedict, 1884.
[1] For our authorities and full information on this important controversy
we refer our readers to the admirable "Dissertation," by Baudry, in the
supplementary volume (ix.) of Migne's edition of the "Works of S. Francis
and S. Jane Frances." There is an anonymous dissertation in vol. vi. which
bears on the same subject.
[2] The following part of our Introduction—viz., the analysis of Books i.,
ii., will probably be found more intelligible and useful after reading the
Saint's text.
[3] This division is the connecting chain of the whole Treatise, and it will
be found that each Book treats of one or more of its parts. Thus the three
following Books are on point 3, Book v. on point 2, Books vi.–ix. on points
4 and 5 (viz., union by affective and by effective love), x.–xii. on point
3.
[4] Certain expressions on p. 50 require explanation. It is there said that
in the superior part of the soul there are two degrees of reason—the answer
is that the Saint for the moment puts out of consideration the lowest degree
of the higher reason, and concerns himself with the two supernatural
degrees. And a little lower down he speaks of the action of faith "in the
inferior part of the soul," but he really means in the lower one of the two
highest degrees.
[5] It is true that elsewhere (Book iv. c. v.) S. Francis says, after S.
Thomas and S. Francis Xavier, that God is sure to give grace to those who
fulfil the natural law, but, since in the state of fallen nature the natural
law itself cannot be fully observed without grace, there is already supposed
in the hearts of such persons the existence of grace which draws the further
grace. This the Saint expressly states (xi. 1).
[6] "Four Essays on the Life and Writings of S. Francis de Sales," Essay
III. p. 88.
[7] From her life by Maupas, quoted by Bossuet in the "Instr. Past. sur les
états d’oraison," viii.
[8] Pp. 82-4.
[9] The Saint is careful to qualify any ambiguous statement (as in ix. 4) by
declaring that he speaks "par imagination de chose impossible."
[10] In the same "Instruction, &c."
[11] They occur in i. 5, 10; iv. 10; v. 1; vi. 15; vii. 1; viii. 1; ix. 10;
x. 7, 9; xi. 4, 10, 11, 14.
[12] "A Treatise of the Love of God." Written in French by B. Francis de
Sales, Bishope and Prince of Geneva. Translated into English by Miles Car,
priest of the English Colledge of Doway. The eighteenth edition. Printed at
Doway by Gerard Pinchon, at the sign of Coleyn, 1630.
[13] We would gladly have reintroduced such a fine old word as "yert," which
represents the now untranslateable eslan or eslancement.
[14] For instance nuisance as if it were naissance; jeusnes et veilles, as
if they were jeunes et vieilles.
|