Enchiridion On Faith, Hope and Love by Saint Augustine
CHAPTER III
GOD THE CREATOR
OF ALL; AND THE GOODNESS
OF ALL CREATION
9.
Wherefore, when it is asked what we ought to believe in matters of
religion,
the answer is not to be sought in the exploration of the nature of
things
[rerum
natura], after the manner of those whom the
Greeks called "physicists."20
Nor
should we be dismayed if Christians are ignorant about the properties
and the
number
of the basic elements of nature, or about the motion, order, and
deviations
of
the stars, the map of the heavens, the kinds and nature of animals,
plants,
stones,
springs, rivers, and mountains; about the divisions of space and
time, about
the
signs of impending storms, and the myriad other things which these
"physicists"
have
come to understand, or think they have. For even these men, gifted
with such
superior
insight, with their ardor in study and their abundant leisure,
exploring
some
of these matters by human conjecture and others through historical
inquiry,
have
not yet learned everything there is to know. For that matter, many of
the
things
they are so proud to have discovered are more often matters of
opinion than
of
verified knowledge.
For
the Christian, it is enough to believe that the cause of all created
things,
whether
in heaven or on earth, whether visible or invisible, is nothing other
than
the
goodness of the Creator, who is the one and the true God.21
Further, the
Christian
believes that nothing exists save God himself and what comes from
him;
and
he believes that God is triune, i.e., the Father, and the Son
begotten of the
Father,
and the Holy Spirit proceeding from the same Father, but one and the
same
Spirit
of the Father and the Son.
10.
By this Trinity, supremely and equally and immutably good, were all
things
created. But they were not created supremely, equally, nor immutably
good.
Still,
each single created thing is good, and taken as a whole they are very
good,
because
together they constitute a universe of admirable beauty.
11.
In this universe, even what is called evil, when it is rightly
ordered and
kept
in its place, commends the good more eminently, since good things
yield
greater
pleasure and praise when compared to the bad things. For the
Omnipotent
God,
whom even the heathen acknowledge as the Supreme Power over all,
would
not
allow any evil in his works, unless in his omnipotence and goodness,
as the
Supreme
Good, he is able to bring forth good out of evil. What, after all, is
anything
we
call evil except the privation of good? In animal bodies, for
instance, sickness and
wounds
are nothing but the privation of health. When a cure is effected, the
evils
which
were present (i.e., the sickness and the wounds) do not retreat and
go
elsewhere.
Rather, they simply do not exist any more. For such evil is not a
substance;
the wound or the disease is a defect of the bodily substance which,
as a
substance,
is good. Evil, then, is an accident, i.e., a privation of that good
which is
called
health. Thus, whatever defects there are in a soul are privations of
a natural
good.
When a cure takes place, they are not transferred elsewhere but,
since they
are
no longer present in the state of health, they no longer exist at
all.22
20One
of the standard titles of early Greek philosophical treatises was
peri fnsewz, which would
translate
into Latin as De rerum natura. This is, in fact, the title of
Lucretius' famous poem, the
greatest
philosophical work written in classical Latin.
21This
basic motif appears everywhere in Augustine's thought as the very
foundation of his whole
system.
22This
section (Chs. III and IV) is the most explicit statement of a major
motif which pervades the
whole
of Augustinian metaphysics. We see it in his earliest writings,
Soliloquies, 1, 2, and De ordine,
II,
7. It is obviously a part of the Neoplatonic heritage which Augustine
appropriated for his
Christian
philosophy. The good is positive, constructive, essential; evil is
privative, destructive,
|